The Revival of Natural Law Concepts  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

Jump to: navigation, search

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

The Revival of Natural Law Concepts (1930) is a text by Charles Grove Haines.

Full text[1]

                   THE REVIVAL OF 
                NATURAL LAW CONCEPTS


     A Study of the Establishment and of the 
  Interpretation of Limits on Legislatures with 
 special reference to the Development of certain 
       phases of American Constitutional Law


                        BY


               CHARLES GROVE HAINES


          Professor of Political Science, 
      University of California at Los Angeles




             HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS 
            CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS 
                       1930


             LONDON : HUMPHREY MILFORD 
              OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS



                               PREFACE


THE investigation of the practice of the review of legislative acts by the

courts to test their conformity with the provisions of written constitutions

has involved the consideration of theories of natural law and of ideas of

superior fundamental laws. These theories and ideas are closely related to

doctrines of higher or superior laws which have accompanied the growth of

legal systems. Due to the importance of such ideas in public law and in the

development of limits on the different branches of modern governments, a

study has been made of the main stages in the evolution of higher law

concepts. A considerable part of the study is devoted to the significance of

natural law ideas in the interpretation of the state and federal

constitutions in the United States, where natural law doctrines have been

extensively applied. The review of the growth of natural law ideas and the

presentation of representative opinions of European publicists are intended

to aid in the interpretation of American theories and as a perspective to

evaluate some modern tendencies in constitutional development in the United

States.


It is evident that the concepts of natural law and of fundamental law are

frequently associated. Though natural law may be thought of with little

relation to the notion involved in fundamental laws, and fundamental laws

may be conceived unrelated to natural law, it is customary at various stages

of such analyses for one idea to merge into the other. Carlyle, in speaking

of the views of the Roman jurists on natural law, doubted whether any of the

lawyers had very clear conceptions upon the matter. As a matter of fact all

theories of natural law have a singular vagueness which is both an advantage

and disadvantage in the application of the theories.


Philosophers emphasize the fact that such a term as natural law is a value

concept and the result of an attitude -- an attitude which presupposes

certain psychic processes. Such value concepts are in one sense subjective,

and in another sense they have a normative objectivity. It is beyond the

scope of this treatise to deal with the philosophical and psychological

processes which underlie natural law thinking. The purpose is to present

different types of theories in their legal development and to note their

applications by jurists and lawyers.


Articles by the writer relating in part to this subject have appeared in the

Yale Law Journal, Illinois Law Review, and the Texas Law Review. The

portions used from these articles have been rewritten in a continuous

account with the exception of extracts from the Texas Law Review which are

reprinted with some minor changes by permission of the editors. In the

presentation of ideas relating to natural law in European countries, I have

received invaluable assistance from Professor Georgio del Vecchio, Rector of

the University of Rome, and Professor Louis Le Fur of the Faculty of Law of

the University of Paris, who have favored me with very useful Italian and

French publications relating to natural law. In addition I have been

accorded the privilege by authors and publishers to translate and reprint

portions of the works of European authorities on natural law. I take

pleasure in expressing my appreciation for aid received from Dean Roscoe

Pound, who has frequently indicated in books and in articles the influence

of natural law concepts in the development of American law.


                                              CHARLES GROVE HAINES


                                              Los ANGELES, CALIFORNIA 
                                              November, 1929



                      CONTENTS


                       PART I


   A SURVEY OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF NATURAL LAW DOCTRINES


I. ANCIENT AND MEDIAEVAL NATURAL LAW THEORIES . . 3


1. Graeco-Roman Concepts ............ 4


2. Natural Law in the Middle Ages ......... 12


3. Theories following the Reformation ........ 17


4. Types of Natural Law Ideas in Ancient and Mediaeval Times

................. 24


II. ENGLISH HIGHER LAW DOCTRINES .......... 28


1. Natural Law Ideas and English Doctrines relating to Fundamental Laws

.............. 29


2. Natural Law and the Doctrine of the Supremacy of the Law

................... 32


3. Evidences of Natural Law Ideas in Judicial Decisions 39


4. Types of Natural Law Theories applied in English Law.....................

43


5. Differences between the Anglo-American and the Continental Legal Points

of View ........ 44


III. AMERICAN AND FRENCH NATURAL LAW DOCTRINES . . 49


1. Transition from Natural Law Doctrines to Theories of Natural Rights

................ 49


2. American Theories of Natural Law and of Inalienable Rights

................... 52


3. French Natural Law Concepts .......... 59


4. The Decline of the Natural Rights Philosophy ... 65


                       PART II


 THE ACCEPTANCE OF NATURAL LAW OR SUPERIOR LAW CONCEPTS IN THE PUBLIC LAW 

OF THE UNITED STATES


IV. JUDICIAL CONSTRUCTION or IMPLIED LIMITS ON AMERICAN LEGISLATURES

................. 75


1. Denial of the Application of Natural Law Concepts . 75


2. Natural Law Theories in the Formative Period of American Law

................ 77


3. Higher Law Theories as a Sanction for the Establishment of the Review of

Legislative Acts by Courts 80


4. Limits on Legislatures resulting from the Nature of the Social Compact

and from the Nature of Free Republican Governments ............ 86


5. Construction of Limits on Legislatures to protect Vested Rights

................ 88


6. The Main Purpose of the Establishment of Express and Implied Limits on

Legislative Powers .... 95


7. A Reaction from the Federalist Doctrine of Limiting Legislative

Activities ............. 97


8. The Return to the Former Natural Law Theories . . 99


V. NATURAL LAW THEORIES AND DUE PROCESS OF LAW . . 104


1. Divergent Views on the Meaning of Due Process of Law.....................

104


2. Due Process of Law as applied by the Justices of the State Courts prior

to 1870 ........... 108


3. Cooley's Efforts to extend the Meaning of Due Process of Law........

......... 116


4. Economic and Legal Bases for a Revival of Natural Law Thinking

................ 117


5. Due Process of Law made an Agency for the Maintenance of Reactionary

Tendencies ........ 122


                       PART III


   THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT AND NATURAL LAW THEORIES


VI. THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT TO THE FEDERAL CONSTITUTION AND DUE PROCESS OF

LAW ...... 143


1. Period of Restricted Interpretation ........ 145


2. Economic and Political Pressure brings about a Change in Supreme Court

Decisions .......... 149


3. Reversal of the Former Opinions on the Meaning of Due Process of Law

.............. 154


(a) Due Process of Law applied to the Procedure in the Regulation of Public

Utilities ...... 154


(6) Due Process of Law and Liberty of Contract . . 160


VII. THE DEVELOPMENT OF A GENERAL RULE OF REASON TO DETERMINE THE VALIDITY

OF LEGISLATIVE ACTS . . 166


1. Arbitrary Legislative and Administrative Acts are Void

.................... 166


2. Acts Contrary to Fundamental Rights are Void . . 172


3. Police Regulations must be Reasonable ...... 177


4. Results of the Extension of the Meaning of Due Process of Law

................ 182


5. Some Examples of Higher Law Concepts in Recent Supreme Court Decisions

........... 185


VIII. NATURAL LAW DOCTRINES AID IN CHANGING THE BASIS FOR JUDICIAL REVIEW OF

LEGISLATIVE ACTS ..... 196


1. Conservative Doctrines and Judicial Review of Legislation

.................... 198


2. Underlying Purpose of the Revival of the Natural Law Philosophy in

American Constitutional Law . 210


3. Types of Natural Law applied in the United States . 216


Appendix ... ............... 232


                       PART IV


  THE REVIVAL OF DROIT NATUREL, NATURRECHT, AND SUPERIOR LAW DOCTRINES IN 

THE JURISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF EUROPEAN WRITERS


IX. THE BACKGROUND FOR RECENT THEORIES OF NATURAL LAW AND THE GERMAN

DOCTRINE OF A "RECHTSSTAAT" 237


1. Continuance of Natural Law Theories in Europe . . 237


2. German Doctrine of a Rechtsstaat ......... 245


3. Current Views Relating to Natural Law in Germany 246


X. FRENCH THEORIES RELATING TO SUPERIOR LAW: HIGHER LAW DOCTRINES OF KRABBE

.......... 252


1. Views of Saleilles and Charmont ......... 252


2. Views of Duguit and Hauriou .......... 260


3. Higher Law Doctrines of Krabbe ......... 274


XI. REVIVAL OF NATURAL LAW IN METAPHYSICAL AND THEOLOGICAL SPECULATIONS;

NATURAL LAW THEORIES AND INTERNATIONAL LAW ............ 278


1. Natural Law Doctrines of Del Vecchio ....... 279


2. Theological Interpretation of Natural Law by Victor Cathrein

.................. 286


3. Metaphysical Doctrines of Geny ......... 288


4. Natural Law Theories and International Law ... 294


5. Theories of Natural Law Prevalent in Europe ... 302


                       PART V


    SIGNIFICANCE OF THE REVIVAL OF HIGHER LAW CONCEPTS IN THE PUBLIC LAW OF 

EUROPE AND OF AMERICA


XII. OBJECTIVES IN THE MODERN REVIVAL OF NATURAL LAW THINKING

.................. 309


1. Natural Law as a Device to introduce Ethical Concepts into the Law

.............. 310


2. Natural Law as an Ideal or Philosophical Standard . 316


3. Higher Laws to guide Judges as Legislators..... 323


4. Higher Law Theories as a Basis for Limits on State Sovereignty

.................. 331


5. Limits on the Power to amend Constitutions in America due to Fundamental

Principles and Rights 336


6. Concluding Comments ............. 342


BIBLIOGRAPHY ..................... 353


TABLE OF CASES .................... 373


INDEX ........................ 381



                      PART I


     A SURVEY OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF NATURAL LAW
                      DOCTRINES


                     CHAPTER I


     ANCIENT AND MEDIAEVAL NATURAL LAW THEORIES


THE conviction that there are superior principles of right, or higher laws

to which the ordinary civil rules made by man must conform and which

necessarily place limits on the operation of such rules, is one of the most

persistent ideas in the evolution of legal thought. There have been times

when the import of higher law concepts has been discredited or their

directive force in legal growth has been concealed by a different

terminology. But legal ideas have seldom been free from superior law

influences. Though the significance of this conviction in the growth of

systems of law has been examined frequently by exponents or critics of

natural law theories, the consideration of the ideas therein involved never

ceases to be of interest. Current tendencies in the legal thought of Europe

and of America render it appropriate to review once more certain

applications of these higher law concepts, and to consider their purport in

giving direction to various processes of modern legal adjustments. Only some

representative uses of these ideas in Europe may be considered as a basis

for comparison and contrast with their pervasive applications in the public

law of the United States. The best-known and most influential form of the

higher law doctrines centers around the term "natural law" or "law of

nature."[1]


1. Graeco-Roman Concepts. Few terms in the history of law have had such a

variety of meanings as the "law of nature" or "natural law." This phrase is

not only used differently by writers in the same period but is also not

infrequently employed in either a confused sense or with varying

connotations by the same writer.[2] And, as with most legal expressions, it

has conveyed divergent ideas in various stages of legal history. Because of

the variety of meanings attributed to the term, efforts have often been made

to discredit its use and to discard references to it in relation to legal

phenomena. Thereby it was thought clear thinking might be facilitated. It

remains to be seen whether such efforts have attained the desired object. A

summary of some of the more common uses of this term forms a necessary

background for a consideration of the modern revival of natural law

thinking.


There have been times when the term "law of nature" has been thought of as

comprising a customary law of divine origin. Such a divine origin of law

tended in early Greece to foster a distinction between laws which were

fundamental as in accordance with nature or ancient custom, and the

conventional rules resulting from ordinary human enactments.[3]


The historical background of natural law concepts has been so frequently

analyzed that it seemed unnecessary to attempt to retrace it again, and it

is not the purpose of this study to treat in detail the evolution of such

ideas. A succinct summary will indicate the stages through which natural law

concepts have passed since the time of the Greeks.


The distinction between the laws made by man and laws which are in

accordance with nature or of divine origin may be traced in the works of

many Greek writers.[4]


Throughout much of Greek thought there was a contrast between fusiV (or

phusis) -- a process of growing in the physical sense, and nomoV (or nomos)

-- man's formulation of rules regarding such growth.[5] Early Greek

philosophers speculated chiefly about the physical universe, but the

Sophists directed attention toward the state and its relations to

individuals.[6] With the Sophists the man-made nomoi were likely to be

contrasted with the universal laws emanating from the gods.[7] Sophocles,

who refers at various times to the notion of higher laws, has Antigone say,

in defence of the charge that she had wilfully disobeyed the king's orders:


    "Nor deemed I that thy decrees were of such force, that a
    mortal could override the unwritten and unfailing statutes of
    heaven. For their life is not of today or yesterday, but for all
    time, and no man knows when they were first put forth."[8]


The distinction between natural law, which is universal and divine, and

positive law, which is local and human, is attributed to Hippias by Plato in

the Protagoras.[9] As politics and ethics were to the Greeks nothing more

than two phases of the same formula it was to be expected that chief

interest would be manifested in the ethical phases of the natural law

concept. The Greek idea of law being primarily "a coherent interpretation

and reasoned revision of custom" it was inevitable that principles and rules

of reason should predominate in this interpretation.[10]


Aristotle put the distinction between fundamental and ordinary laws into a

standard formula which has greatly influenced subsequent legal thought. To

Aristotle justice was either natural, as in accordance with nature, and

hence universal; or local and conventional, as applicable to a particular

place.[11] The higher law, as Aristotle conceived it, was unwritten,

universal, eternal and immutable, and in accordance with nature. He divided

law into that which is common, being in accordance with nature and in force

everywhere, and that which is peculiar to each separate community. When an

advocate was pleading a cause and found the positive law was against him,

Aristotle suggested that he might then appeal to the law of nature as

rendering the act void.[12] Thus a basis was laid in philosophic thought for

a dualism between the customary, natural, and universal in law, and the

local, conventional, and ordinary enactments of a separate group of men. It

was this dualism to which mediaeval thinkers recurred when they sought to

contrast the natural and divine laws with the civil laws of a particular

time and place, and to which later jurists have turned when some standard

was sought to test the value or efficacy of existing positive laws.


The Greeks perceived rather vaguely the ideal of fundamental laws as now

understood and they instituted a unique plan for the guardianship of such

laws. This was in the form of an action against the proponent of a measure

or an action to secure annulment of the act. If the action was instituted

within one year of the enactment of the law, proceedings could be brought

against the proponent of the measure, but if instituted later the process

applied only to the annulment of the law. The action might be brought "for

infringement of legal rules, neglecting forms of procedure or some

regulation bearing on the legislative process."[13] In their efforts to

establish a rule of law based on the ancient customary rules the Greeks

regarded certain laws of such permanence that it was a matter of serious

public concern to change them.[14] The idea of the sovereignty of law was

one of the fundamental principles of Greek thought;[15] it prevailed widely

during the Middle Ages; and it was transmitted to modern times in the form

of theories of the supremacy of law or of the reign of law.


Though the Greeks were among the first to formulate ideas of natural law the

Romans made more use of such theories and put their views along this line

into more enduring forms. The first indications of the application of this

concept are to be found in the work of the praetors. In the development of a

law relating to the commercial dealings between citizens and aliens, where

formerly only the principle of bona fides or good faith prevailed, the

praetor peregrinus gradually built a legal system based on reason and common

sense.[16] The praetor, by means of the edict and through his right to

refuse an action worked out an equitable law -- the jus gentium -- which

tended to displace the rigors of the jus civile.[17] It was in this

connection that the doctrine of jus naturale became associated with the

growth of the Roman law. Though jus naturale was seldom used in this period

of Roman law the term served to give sanction to the jus gentium as a

universal system of law which was gradually superseding the jus civile.[18]

Thus principles of natural law or natural justice found their expression in

the hands of the judge and the practical administrator rather than in the

writings of political philosophers. It is interesting to see that at times

when legal thinkers attached little weight to such principles they formed

convenient sources for the extraction of new legal ideas by those who found

the law too harsh and too formalistic in its applications.


As the Roman law developed into a coherent system the three main sources of

its growth were legislation, administrative edicts, and juristic reasoning.

It was in juristic reasoning that natural law concepts were extensively

used, for the authority of the opinions of the jurists in their responses

depended upon the reasonableness of their comments.


As a basic concept for a jus gentium or universal law, natural law was

extensively applied in connection with the Stoic philosophy and with the

application of Stoic principles in the Roman law.[19]


Zeno, the founder of Stoicism, has a remarkable passage extolling natural

law as the eternal and universal law of God governing and directing all

things. The Stoics emphasized the ethical side of Aristotle's conception of

natural justice and considered it as a guiding principle immanent in the

universe. This immanent principle was reason and its expression was natural

law.[20] To Cicero, who became an advocate of Stoic doctrines, the law of

nature became the source and limit of all rights.[21] The best exposition of

Cicero's view is as follows:


Of all these things respecting which learned men dispute there is none more

important than clearly to understand that we are born for justice, and that

right is founded not in opinion but in nature. There is indeed a true law

(lex), right reason, agreeing with nature and diffused among all,

unchanging, everlasting, which calls to duty by commanding, deters from

wrong by forbidding.... It is not allowable to alter this law nor to deviate

from it. Nor can it be abrogated. Nor can we be released from this law

either by the senate or by the people. Nor is any person required to explain

or interpret it. Nor is it one law at Rome and another at Athens, one law

today and another hereafter; but the same law, everlasting and unchangeable,

will bind all nations and all times; and there will be one common lord and

ruler of all, even God, the framer and proposer of this law.[22]


To Cicero civil laws were merely the application of this eternal natural

law. He also emphasized the natural equality of men in contrast with the

Aristotelian theory of inequality and thus foreshadowed one of the

interesting ideas of the Roman jurists. The Ciceronian conception of the law

of nature was to exert a formative influence on legal thought for the

succeeding centuries, but it was modified in its transmission by the form

into which the concept was put by the Roman jurists and incorporated in the

Digest and Institutes of Justinian. The Roman lawyers accepted the Greek

conceptions of natural justice and natural law and applied them as a means

of legal reform. To these conceptions may be traced some of the significant

ideas of the Roman law relating to equity. Gaius considered the jus naturale

as virtually equivalent to the jus gentium, which was recognized through

reason as a body of principles, universal and equitable in their

applications.[23] For him natural law was a body of principles recognized

through the reason as useful and just.


Ulpian and other Roman jurists seemed vaguely to distinguish between the jus

naturale and the jus gentium, the former partaking more of the primitive and

instinctive rules applicable to all life, and the latter, of the

conventional rules of mankind at a given time and place.[24] Thus the later

Roman jurists regarded slavery as contrary to the jus naturale, since men by

the law of nature are born free and equal,[25] but as sanctioned by the jus

gentium. By the time of Justinian the jus naturale had come to mean a body

of ideal principles which men could rationally apprehend and which included

the perfect standards of right conduct and of justice.[26] The compilers of

the Institutes attempted to discriminate between the rules and instincts

common to animals -- the jus naturale; rules common to all mankind -- the

jus gentium; and the particular rules of a community -- jus civile.


This classification, though merely suggested by Roman commentators, was

followed with scrupulous care by certain mediaeval jurists.[27] Later

civilians, like the older jurists, used natural law vaguely and sometimes in

an ambiguous way, referring perchance to rules arising from animal

instincts, to a common law created by man and corresponding to the jus

gentium, or in Christian thinking to the laws of the Bible. But from some

statements in Justinian's Institutes Carlyle concludes that "by the sixth

century the phrase was certainly taking that meaning which it has throughout

the Middle Ages and later -- that is, that the jus naturale means that body

of principles of justice and reason which men can rationally apprehend, and

which forms the ideal norm or standard of right conduct and of the justice

of social institutions."[28] All were agreed that natural law was immutable

and not subject to change by civil enactments. It is well to note that two

ideas which become prominent in the later stages of the growth of natural

law concepts, namely, a primitive state of nature and, arising therefrom, a

natural freedom and a natural equality, are the peculiar results of Roman

legal thought in the Lower Empire. It was not until the mediaeval period,

however, that the philosophy of natural law was given a dominant place in

legal thinking.


2. Natural Law in the Middle Ages. A significant development of the concept

of natural law is to be found in the Middle Ages, when the theories of

Cicero and of the Roman jurists were adapted to the teachings of

Christianity. In the writings of the philosophers and of the jurists of this

period the concept of natural law was uppermost. The theory gained in

significance by its association with the concept of a state of nature which

had been recognized by some of the later Roman jurists.[29]


Primary consideration was given at this time to divine laws or to what were

regarded as the eternal laws of the universe, over which man had no control.

But subordinate to these divine and eternal laws was the law of nature. That

the theory of natural law was given an important place in early Christian

thought may be gathered from the writings of Origen, St. Ambrose, and St.

Jerome. Referring to a passage of St. Paul (Rom. ii, 12-14) they spoke of

natural law as equivalent to the law of God and as universal in contrast

with the written laws made by man.[30] But it was Isadore of Seville who

formulated a view of natural law which through the Decretum of Gratian

became a part of the Canon Law. He recurred to the analysis of Ulpian and

the Roman jurists and classified law as jus naturale, jus civile, and jus

gentium with this difference, that jus naturale became the common law of

nations without any reference to animal instincts.[31] In other respects he

followed closely the Roman doctrines of the Code and the Institutes and thus

gave these doctrines a primary position in mediaeval legal thought.


Gratian introduced a distinction which became basic in the Canon Law --

natural law was identified with divine law and human law with custom; the

jus gentium and the jus civile were included under the latter.[32] "To the

mediaeval canonist, then, as to the Fathers," says Carlyle, "the jus

naturale is identical with the law of God, it is embodied in the 'law and

the Gospel,' for it represents the general moral principles which God has

implanted in human nature, and it is, in its essential character,

immutable." It is true that it is set aside by some of the legitimate

institutions of society, but this is to be explained as a necessary

accommodation to the corrupt state of human nature, and is justified by the

ultimate purpose of setting forward the principles of the jus naturale. The

jus naturale is to the canonists the norm by which any law or institution

must be justified.[33]


The great philosopher of the Middle Ages, Thomas Aquinas, distinguished the

eternal and divine laws as forming a part of the universe and as emanating

from God, from natural laws which were the result of the participation of

man as a rational creature in applying to human affairs the eternal law by

which he distinguished between good and evil. To Aquinas the particular

rules of the lex naturalis were not immutable. As rational laws designed for

human ends, they were subject to change as human conditions varied.[34]


The mediaeval churchmen invariably identified nature and reason with a

personal God and law and rights emanated from his will. Following the method

of Thomas Aquinas, the current divisions of law were: divine, natural, and

positive.


Mediaeval jurists usually accepted the tripartite division of law, suggested

by Roman thinkers, into natural law, law of nations, and civil law. Through

commentaries on the Institutes, such as that of Azo, the Roman

classification was applied to the peculiar conditions of the Middle Ages. In

the main they used the phrase jus naturale as meaning a body of principles,

which may be rationally comprehended and which are immutable. In due course

the jus gentium was thought of as the customary law of mankind and the jus

civile as the customs of a particular community.


Mediaeval legal doctrines were based essentially on superior legal concepts

which regarded law in its origin as of equal rank with the state and as not

depending on the state for its existence. The idea persisted for centuries

that the end of the state is the attainment of justice and that civil

authorities act legitimately only when they follow the principles of

justice. Mediaeval thinkers believed that it was the purpose of the state to

realize the ideas of law and "it was never doubtful that the highest Might,

were it spiritual or were it temporal, was confined by true

limitations."[35]


Customs as well as enactments in order to be valid in mediaeval times were

expected to be reasonable, which for the standards of that day meant in

harmony with divine reason. Estimates of reasonableness were made by a

triple standard applied with varying degrees of effectiveness: (a)

revelation or the laws regarded as given directly from God; (b) church law,

as embodied in the papal decrees or the canonical codes; and (c) natural

law, conceived as common to the natural sentiments of man.


As strengthening the mediaeval concept of the law of nature as law, it is

important to recognize that in this age there was little legislation in the

modern sense. Enactments were usually designed to affirm existing rules or

customs or to remedy abuses in administration.[36] To the mediaeval jurists

and theologians, with such exceptions as St. Augustine and St. Gregory, law

was an expression of the principles of justice and all governmental agencies

were subservient to these principles. So important was this factor in

mediaeval life that to understand legal thought it is regarded necessary to

disregard the ordinary conception of a sovereign, the commands of whom are

considered as law.[37] Civilians thought of law, not as the creation of

human will, but as the application of principles or customs.


Along with the almost universal belief in the divine origin of political

power and with the insistence on unlimited obedience to civil rulers because

their authority came from God, there was a growing demand that for kings to

be assured obedience they must rule justly and according to law.[38] Such

political theorists as John of Salisbury and Althusius developed the

distinction between a king who ruled legitimately according to law and a

tyrant, who was guided by his individual whims.[39] A theory of the election

of rulers was advocated which would render it possible to depose a tyrant.

In the theory of the election of the ruler and in the requirement that he

govern justly lay the germs of the later notion of a social contract, as the

foundation of civil government.


There was prevalent at this time a conception of an inflexible code,

emanating from the divine will interpreted and applied through the light of

reason, and from this conception came the doctrine that the higher laws of

reason or of nature controlled the lower laws or enactments of man.

Sometimes a distinction was made between certain immutable principles and

rules derived therefrom, which were subject to change.[40]


In practice natural law might be referred to as a guide to interpretation or

in certain instances it might be appealed to where no rule of law had been

declared. All laws in conflict with natural law, it was urged, must be

considered void.[41]


A change in viewpoint preceding the period of the Reformation may be

illustrated by William of Ockham's classification of natural law as


    (a) Universal rules of conduct dictated by natural reason.


    (b) Rules which would be accepted as reasonable without
    any positive law. 


    (c) Rules which are arrived at by deduction from the
    precepts of the law of nature and are liable to change by
    positive enactments.[42] 


Rules of the third class were eventually referred to as the secondary laws

of nature.


3. Theories following the Reformation. Not until after the Reformation were

philosophers able to detach natural law theories from ideas of God and to

find their source in an impersonal human reason. This detachment was

hastened and the doctrine of natural law was given wider currency through

the writings of Albertis Gentilis[43] and of Hugo Grotius.


Spanish jurists in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, antedating the

work of Grotius,[44] formulated a theory of a supreme and immutable law of

nature, changeless by God himself and based on "a state of nature antecedent

to the state of corruption, and thus affording the type of perfection for

all actual societies."[45] The mediaeval theological concept of the law of

nature had its culmination in the philosophy of Saurez wherein the law of

nature became an inflexible code willed by God and interpreted by reason.

All enactments civil or religious which contravened this law were ipso facto

void.[46] The Spanish jurists also fostered the belief in the natural rights

of man, which it was the duty of the state to protect. These rights were

thought to arise from a natural condition of equality in which the faculties

inherent in men were to have a free opportunity for development.[47]


To Grotius, who put in a form which became more popular the theories of

Vittoria, Suarez, and Gentilis, the emphasis was placed on natural right,

which was "the dictate of right reason, indicating that any act, from its

agreement or disagreement with the rational nature has in it moral turpitude

or moral necessity; and consequently that such act is forbidden or commanded

by God, the author of nature." Grotius distinguished the law of nature,

which was unalterable even by the Deity, from positive law and from the law

of nations[48] and divided it into divine rules ordained by God and rules

prescribed by man.[49] He and his successors made use of the law of nature

theory in formulating the basic principles of international law,[50] and for

a long time natural law and the law of nations were thought of as closely

related.


Building on natural law as a source and sanction of legal rules mediaeval

jurists laid the basis for the concept of inborn and indestructible rights

belonging to the individual as such. Roman thinkers, such as Seneca, had

suggested that men in their natural state were free and equal.[51] The

Church Fathers accepted this theory and tried to explain the differences and

inequalities in human conditions as due to the fall of man and the

consequent conditions of sin. Doctrines of freedom and equality were made an

integral part of the law of nature by the canon lawyers. With the

development of the sense of individual personality which became a feature of

Christian thought during the Middle Ages and was fostered by church

reformers, similar ideas were considered a part of an individual's right

and heritage. To ecclesiastical thinkers men were equal in the eyes of God;

to the anti-clericals they were equal in the eyes of men.[52]


In the natural law of this period lurked the germ of revolution, for on the

basis of these precepts the whole structure of the state was subjected to

criticism from the rationalist point of view. Catholics vied with

Protestants in formulating a philosophic background for limiting the powers

of the state.[53] To both, the primary rules of natural law were above all

earthly rulers. The law of nature used by the church to support the Catholic

morals and faith was found to be a convenient weapon to oppose the church in

setting over against canonist decrees the rules of life discovered by human

reason. In the conflict between the Empire and the Papacy, then, both

disputants made frequent use of the law of nature.


Mediaevalists agreed on the existence of natural law; they differed merely

as to its force and effectiveness. To some a statute or an executive act

which violated natural law was void; to others, interested either in the

claims of kings and princes to be sovereign in the civil domain or in the

idea of popular sovereignty, natural law comprised guiding principles,

directive only in the processes of lawmaking.


At the same time that men were engaged in discovering new grounds for

limiting political authority, an ingenious Frenchman, following the lead of

the Italian, Machiavelli, was formulating a theory of sovereignty which was

destined to leave small place for the laws of nature. Recognizing a

condition wherein the state as represented by an absolute king accountable

only to God was claiming omnipotent authority, Jean Bodin developed a theory

of sovereignty suitable to the times. To him the sovereign must be absolute

and can be fettered by no human laws. He admitted that there were superior

laws of morality and religion to which princes were bound but for breaches

thereof they were accountable to God alone. Thus Bodin furnished the broad

outlines of a theory which was accepted and elaborated upon by Hobbes,

Spinoza, and Austin. Later developed by modern schools of legal philosophy

it ultimately weakened the respect for, and largely replaced the law of

nature theories of mediaeval times.[54]


"Natural law," "natural rights," and "natural justice," during most of the

Middle Ages, were terms which were often used interchangeably. Thomas Hobbes

undertook to distinguish between jus naturale as a natural right and lex

naturalis as natural law. To him a natural right was a liberty possessed by

every man in a state of nature, of doing what seemed best for the

preservation of his existence. Natural law, on the other hand, was a body of

principles or restraints which were devised by reason to make life secure.


The philosophy of Bodin, Hobbes,[55] and Spinoza tended to discredit the old

natural law ideas and to make the state the sole source of law. They

repudiated the legal significance of the "idea of natural law which aimed at

finding a higher written law, above the rule promulgated by the state, to

which this rule must accommodate itself so far as it aims to be, not a mere

command of force, but an ordinance of justice."[56] They were formulating a

basis for a doctrine of state omnipotence which was eventually to become one

of the dominant dogmas of modern political thought.


Samuel Pufendorf followed Grotius in separating the law of nature from

theology and in regarding most of the law of nature as the dictate of right

reason determining what is right and wrong in human conduct. The natural

rights philosophy was put into its most systematic form in the works of

Pufendorf.[57] Foremost in his system were the natural rights of the

individual, independent of society and of the state, arising from a

condition similar to Seneca's primitive state of nature. The law of nations

was regarded merely as a fragment of natural law. There was the foundation

here for what has been called "the unruly emphasis on rights" which

culminated in the French declaration of 1789.


Locke regarded the law of nature as a body of rules for the conduct of men

in their natural condition. Reason, Locke considered as the interpreter of

this law; equality, its fundamental condition. Conceiving men as existing in

a state of nature Locke constructed his doctrine of natural rights which

belong to man in the pre-political state. These rights were life, liberty,

and property.[58] Legislatures were bound to rule, in his judgment,

according to the law of nature and to carry on their functions by fixed and

general laws rather than by arbitrary decrees; and laws which transgressed

certain fundamental principles were not laws "properly so-called."[59] There

seems to be a warrant here for the opinions of American justices that acts

of the legislature which are arbitrary, though not expressly prohibited, may

nevertheless be void because not "legislative in character." Locke's ideas

relating to the social compact, government under the law of nature, popular

sovereignty, the right of revolution, and natural rights superior to the

government and civil laws, were to reappear in constitutions, laws, and

judicial decisions in phrases adapted to American legal thinking.


Thus the dualism of Aristotle had taken definite form. There was an

immutable law which was of divine origin or the product of right reason, but

whatever its source it was common to all men and universal. And there were

positive enactments which were made by man to meet the contingencies of the

moment. The two systems were in constant conflict -- one a perfect and

rational order and the other an imperative and positive one.[60]


Natural law, emanating from the divine will or from divine reason, consisted

only of certain basic principles. Positive law elaborated this natural law

and through practical reason adapted it to the ordinary activities of life.

Differing from the idealistic interpretations of the concept in Greece and

in Rome natural laws were conceived as norms and positive laws that were not

in accord with the natural law were unjust and therefore had no validity,

though the means to prevent their enforcement were not always at hand. Thus

a criterion was available to measure, in a theoretical way at least, the

validity of civil enactments.[61]


4. Types of Natural Law Ideas in Ancient and Mediaeval Times. It is

difficult to classify the various types of natural law theories which

prevailed in ancient and mediaeval times, but it seems essential to

undertake a tentative classification.


With the early Greeks natural law was law in accordance with nature in the

physical sense, similar to the laws of the natural sciences in modern

terminology. Such a meaning of the laws of nature has been seldom referred

to since the time of the Greeks, though it has had counterparts in Ulpian's

laws common to all animals, in the eternal laws of Aquinas from a quite

different setting, and in a curious medley of ideas in the nineteenth

century, when natural law comprised a resume of ideas relating to the

physical universe, of moral and ethical concepts, and of legal doctrines and

principles.


Natural law was also considered as divine in origin and either comprised

rules given to man by the Deity or his representatives or consisted of

divine law from which principles of right and justice might be deduced by

man's reason. This source of natural law only incidentally mentioned by the

Greeks became to the theologians of the Middle Ages its main origin and

sanction. Following the authoritative presentation of this view by Thomas

Aquinas and other mediaeval theologians it has continued as the accepted

view of Catholic jurists and of others who have chosen to emphasize the

religious factors in the processes of lawmaking. Believers in this type of

natural law may be found in all countries wherein the philosophy and

traditions of the Middle Ages are fostered by religious and ethical

agencies.


The Greeks also set a standard for a natural law of an idealist type --

comprised of universal and immutable principles apprehended chiefly by

philosophers and jurists. It was a law which reasonable creatures were

everywhere bound to obey. Positive laws to have validity emanated from the

ideal natural laws. This type of natural law was closely related to the

current ideas of religion and morality and became prominent in Stoic

political thought. During the Middle Ages it was conceived as an absolute

law of reason which on account of its rational basis binds all reasonable

beings.


Differing in certain respects from the immutable natural law of the Stoics,

a type of natural law was formulated by ancient and mediaeval thinkers which

was comprised of rules or principles of law and justice, divorced partially,

at least, from divine origins. These were sometimes referred to as the

unwritten laws ingrained in the hearts of men. Such principles were used by

the praetors and jurists in rendering decisions which were just and

equitable, and in adapting the rigid formulas of the jus civile to form the

jus gentium. It was this kind of natural law -- principles of common law

recurring among different nations -- on which international law and certain

parts of developing public law were based in the sixteenth century. It is a

type which is always present in the practical applications of the law where

it is molded to accord with advancing notions of morality in human conduct.

Stripped of some of its immutable characteristics, its modern use may be

found in the principles of reasonable conduct applied in English law and in

the authority accorded the judges in certain European countries to fall back

on principles of reason and justice to fill gaps in the law. Continental

jurists also make frequent use of the rationalist form of natural law to

measure the efficacy of existing positive enactments. It thus becomes the

prototype for a "natural law with a variable content." The main trend of

ancient and mediaeval theories of natural law, as Pollock suggests, was

rationalist and progressive in its implications.


There was also a natural law arising from an original and primitive state

of nature from which men derived natural rights -- such as rights of

equality and freedom. To the mediaevalists this state of nature corresponded

to the condition of men before the origin of sin. Sometimes these rights

were regarded as an inheritance of the individual from his birth and of such

significance that it was the prime duty of the state to protect them. The

Reformation encouraged the tendency to consider such rights as natural and

as belonging to the individual as such. It remained for the English, French,

and American philosophers to make them the foundation of civil government.


Natural law was also conceived as a theoretic foundation for axiomatic

truths from which a system of positive law could be deduced. From this

viewpoint the lex naturalis existed prior to the formation of the state and

from it directly or indirectly came all legal rules.


It would be a mistake to think that the different types of natural law were

either clearly defined by ancient and mediaeval writers or were formulated

in such a way as to be readily differentiated. Most of the ideas relating

to natural law, then as since, were vague and theories often involved a

confusion of ideas which make it almost impossible to attempt any

classification of views. Certain trends are evident, however, which may be

indicated. And, above all, it is apparent that, owing to the continual

efforts to contrast the natural and the conventional, the ancient and

mediaeval periods furnished rich soil for the germination of natural law

concepts.


Natural law theories had passed through a cycle from the ideal and

philosophical form of the Greeks and Romans to a standard, presumedly

derived from divine sources, which the mediaeval canonists used as a

criterion to measure the validity of the acts of civil and secular rulers,

and thence to a series of rationalist concepts forming a basis for

international law and for other branches of civil law.[62] As an ideal not

wholly divorced from its divine connotations natural law was not

infrequently called upon to measure the reason, necessity, or convenience of

the beginnings in the way of modern legislation. The cycle was barely

completed when a new turn in legal and political speculation changed the

course of natural law thinking and gave a marked impetus to the emphasis

upon certain higher law concepts. As the new meaning accorded to these

concepts resulted from the social and political developments in England, in

America, and in France, it is necessary to trace briefly the course of the

development of natural law doctrines in these countries.




1. For sketches of the origin of the higher law ideas in relation to "the

law of nature," see John W. Salmond, "The Law of Nature," Law Quarterly

Renew, XI (April, 1895), 121; James Bryce, "The Law of Nature," Studies in

History and Jurisprudence, II, 556; and Sir Frederick Pollock, "The History

of the Law of Nature," Journal of the Society of Comparative Legislation, II

(1900), 418-433, and Essays in the Law (London, 1922), chap. 2. Reprinted in

Columbia Law Review, 1 (January, 1901), 11. See also Guilio de Montemayor,

Storia del diritto naturale (Naples, 1911).


2. Among the most common ideas involved in the word "natural," when used in

such phrases as "natural justice," "natural right," and "natural law" are:

rational; reasonable; in accordance with nature; in agreement with ancient

customs; just; equitable; divine, or in accord with the will of God; ideal,

as differentiated from the actual; appropriate; and, necessary. For a

summary of the various ideas involved in the term "natural" in this

connection, see B F. Wright, Jr., "American Interpretations of Natural Law,"

in American Political Science Review, XX (August, 1926), 542, 543.


3. For an account of the evolution of Greek ideas relating to natural law,

consult E. Burle, Essai historique sur le développement de la notion de

droit naturel dans l'antiquité grecque (Trevoux, 1908). Cf., especially, for

natural law ideas of Sophocles, of Socrates, and of Plato.


4. See Burle, op. cit., beginning at chap. 2. The Pythagoreans taught that

"law ought to be in conformity with nature and it will be if it is made in

the image of natural law which attributes to each according to his merit"

(ibid., p. 86). For the views of the Sophists see ibid., pp. 103 ff. Greek

philosophers, it is observed, constantly referred to an eternal law, the

reason of a supreme being, and absolute and immutable law, which it was the

duty of the public authorities to recognize and enforce in defining the

relations and duties of human beings. In the Socratic philosophy an act

which resulted in injustice had only the appearance of a law (ibid.; p.

157).


5. John L. Myres, The Political Ideas of the Greeks (New York, 1927), p.

270. For reference to the antithesis between the two concepts, see Ernest F.

Barker, Greek Political Theory: Plato and His Predecessors (London, 1918),

pp. 64 ff. See also Gilbert Murray, "The Stoic Philosophy," in Essays and

Addresses (London, 1921), pp. 96, 97.


6. "The principal problem examined by the Sophists in regard to

jurisprudence was how far the basic laws of society can be regarded as

ingrained in the nature of things, and how far they are merely artificial

establishment." Sir Paul Vinogradoff, Outlines of Jurisprudence, vol. II,

The Jurisprudence of the Greek City (London, 1922), p. 26. Vinogradoff

thinks the contrast between fusiV and nomoV may be traced to Demokritos

(ibid., pp. 26 ff.).


7. Xenophon, Memorabilia, 4. 4. 19; Walter Eckstein, Das antike Naturrecht

im sozial philosophischer Beleuchtung (Wien und Leipzig, 1926), chap. 11.


8. Sophocles, Antigone, pp. 450 ff.


9. Barker, op. cit., p. 64.


10. Cf. Myres, op. cit., p. 47; Eckstein, op. cit., chaps. 2, 3.


11. Nicomachean Ethics, 7; Burle, op. cit., chap. 14. There is, Aristotle

maintained, a natural law anterior to the positive laws and from which the

latter take their origin. To render a political order stable there must be

administered in it a justice independent of arbitrary rules or of human

enactments and superior to every individual interest (ibid., pp. 178 ff.;

Bryce, op. cit., pp. 567, 568; Salmond, op. cit., p. 127).


12. Rhet. 1375, a, 27; Bryce, op. cit., p. 567; Eckstein, op. cit., chap. 5.


13. Vinogradoff, Jurisprudence of the Greek City, p. 138.


14. Cf. also G. M. Calhoun, "Greek Law and Modern Jurisprudence" in

California Law Review, XI (July, 1923), 308, and D. Goodell, "An Athenian

Parallel to a Function of our Supreme Court," in Yale Review, II (May,

1893), 64.


15. See Plato, The Laws; also Ernest Barker, op. cit., chap. 15. To Plato

the rule of law meant that every authority in the state was exercised under

a code of laws which was definitely established and which was fundamental.

In the Republic and the Politicus Plato rejected to a certain extent this

idea of the sovereignty of law.


16. Sohm's Institutes, 3d ed., trans. by J. C. Ledlie (London, 1907), pp. 64

ff.


17. Ibid., p. 79.


18. W. W. Buckland, A Textbook of Roman Law from Augustus to Justinian

(Cambridge, 1921), p. 54.


19. W. W. Buckland, A Manual of Roman Private Law (Cambridge, 1925), pp. 28

ff. The Romans, it is observed, were influenced "by the Stoic conception of

life according to nature with its corollary of a natural law -- rules of

conduct implanted in man by nature. This notion of a jus naturale,

principles intuitive in man, his very nature, and capable of universal

application appears frequently in Roman sources. Occasionally it is declared

to be a principle on which all law rests, but the habitual attitude of the

Roman lawyers is different: jus naturale is the ideal to which it is

desirable that law should conform, but it was not really at any time a test

of the validity of a rule of law." Cf. also Buckland, A Textbook of Roman

Law from Augustus to Justinian (Cambridge, 1921), pp. 53 ff; R. W. and A. J.

Carlyle, A History of Medieval Political Theory in the West (New York and

London, 1903), I, 36 ff.; M. Voigt, Die Lehre vom jus naturale, aequum et

bonum und jus gentium der Römer (Leipzig, 1856), secs. 52-64 and 89-96; and

Theodor Kipp, Geschichte der Quellen des römischen Rechts, 4e ed. (Leipzig,

1919), pp. 14 ff.


20. For an analysis of the original Stoic concepts of a "law of right

reason" see Burle, op. cit., pp. 399 ff., and Eckstein, op. cit., chap. 7.


21. Cicero was, of course, not presenting original ideas but was putting

into current phraseology some of the commonplace political ideas of the

time. "The theory of natural law is to Cicero the form of the theory of

justice in society, and it is also the groundwork upon which the whole

structure of human society rests." Carlyle, op. cit., I, 6.


22. De Legibus II, 4, 10; Carlyle, op. cit., I, 3 ff.; cf. Salmond, op.

cit., pp. 127 ff. and Bryce, op. cit., pp. 568 ff.


23. "That law which any people establishes for itself is peculiar to

itself, and is called the civil law (jus civile), as being the particular

law of the state (jus proprium civitatis). But that law which natural reason

has established for all men, is observed by all peoples alike and is called

the law of nations (jus gentium), as being that which all nations use." From

Introduction to Commentaries of Gaius. Carlyle, op. cit., I, 37 ff.


24. Ibid., pp. 39 ff. Pollock thinks that Ulpian's distinction was not

generally understood by the Roman lawyers of his day and that its

incorporation into the Digest and the Institutes gave it a currency quite

beyond its intrinsic merit. Cf. Appendix to Maine's Ancient Law (New York,

1906), pp. 399, 400, and Essays in the Law (London, 1922), pp. 36-38.


25. Digest 1, 1, 4. On the relations between the jus naturale and jus

gentium in Roman law see Pollock, "History of the Law of Nature," in Essays

in the Law. By the Roman lawyers, Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus, men

are considered by nature free and equal. Quod ad jus naturale attinet, omnes

homines aequales sunt. 1.17. 32. Cum jure naturali omnes liberi nascentur.

Dig. 2. 1. 4; also 2. 5. 4. Cf. Carlyle, op. cit., I, chap. 5; and Albert

Vaunois, De la notion du droit naturel chez les romains (Paris, 1884),

especially chaps. 1, 2.


26. E. D. Dickinson, The Equality of States in International Law (Cambridge,

1920), pp. 16, 17. For reference to the Greek origin of the phrase in

Justinian's Digest, that this is law, to which it is proper that all men

conform (Digest, 1. 3. 2), see John L. Myres, op. cit., pp. 309 ff.


27 Carlyle, op. cit., II, 28 ff. For opinions holding that imperial

rescripts contrary to natural law are void, see ibid., pp. 32, 33. The

Greeks and the Romans seldom conceived of legal rights inhering in the

individual and hence they did not formulate notions of natural rights. On

this distinction, see J. Walter Jones, "Acquired and Guaranteed Rights,"

Cambridge Legal Essays (London, 1926), pp. 223 ff.


28. Carlyle, op. cit., I, 74, 75.


29. An original conception of a primitive state of nature is found in the

writings of Seneca. Carlyle, op. cit., I, 23 ff.


30. For extracts from these writers, see Carlyle, op. cit., I, 104, 105.


31. Carlyle, op. cit., I, 106 ff. Cf. also, Heinrich Singer, "Das

Naturrecht im Codex iuris canonici," Archiv für Rechts- und

Wirtschaftsphilosophie, XVI (1922-23), 206-215. Dr. Singer observes that the

authors and contributors of the Codex iuris canonici were instructed to

state the law so as to agree with the principles of natural law. An effort

was made to reconcile the jus divinum or revealed law with jus naturale or

rules resulting from the rational processes of man. Ibid., pp. 209 ff.


32. Carlyle, op. cit., II, 28, 98, 102, 105.


33. Ibid., II, 113; also Pollock, Essays in the Law, p. 40.


34. Summa Theologiae, 1, 2, q. 91, art. 2 and q. 93, art. 1. The theories of

Thomas Aquinas are based to a considerable extent upon the doctrines of

predecessors in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries whose works are usually

neglected. For the contributions of some of these men consult Martin

Grabmann, "Das Naturrecht der Scholastic von Gratian bis Thomas von Aquin,"

Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie, XVI (1922-23), 12-53.

Alessandro Bonnucci also traces the scholastic philosophy of natural law in

La derogabilita del diritto naturale nella scholastica (Perugia, 1906).


Rufinus was one of the first to suggest that jus naturale was "a certain

quality implanted in mankind by nature, which leads men to do what is good

and to avoid what is evil." Carlyle, op. cit., II, 103, 107.


35. Otto Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Ages, trans. by F. W.

Maitland (Cambridge, 1922), pp. 74ff.; cf. p. 172 for note by Maitland on

the theories of natural law in the Middle Ages. "Men supposed," says Gierke,

"that before the State existed the Lex Naturalis already prevailed as an

obligatory statute and that immediately or mediately from this flowed those

rules of right to which the State owed even the possibility of its own

rightful origin. And men also taught that the highest power on earth was

subject to the rules of Natural Law. They stood above the Pope and above the

Kaiser, above the Ruler and above the Sovereign People, nay, above the whole

Community of Mortals. Neither statute nor act of government, neither

resolution of the People nor custom could break the bounds that thus were

set. Whatever contradicted the eternal and immutable principles of Natural

Law was utterly void and would bind no one. The mediaeval theory declared

'that every act of the Sovereign which broke the bonds drawn by Natural Law

was formally null and void.' ... As null and void, therefore, every judge

and every other magistrate who had to apply the law was to treat, not only

every unlawful executive act, but every unlawful statute, even though it

were published by the Pope or Emperor." Ibid., pp. 75, 84. Cf. also,

Carlyle, op. cit., I, 174; III, 32, 128; and Gierke, Johannes Althusius und

die Entwickelung der naturrechtlichen Staats-theorien, 3d ed. (Breslau,

1913), chap. 6.


36. C. H. McIlwain, The High Court of Parliament and its Supremacy (New

Haven, 1910), pp. 43, 46, and "Magna Carta and Common Law" in Malden, Magna

Carta Commemoration Essays, pp. 140, 141. See also, Theodore F. T.

Plucknett, Statutes and their Interpretation in the First Half of the

Fourteenth Century (Cambridge, 1922), pp. 165 ff.


37. Carlyle, op. cit., III, chap. 3.


38. "Any form of government is right and just," said Aquinas, "in which the

rulers seek to promote the common good, but not otherwise." A. J. Carlyle,

"The Political Theories of St. Thomas Aquinas," Scottish Review, XXVII

(January, 1896), 126, 141.


39. For an exhaustive analysis of the theories of Althusius and of the

"Monarchomachs," consult Gierke, Johannes Althusius. The whole view of the

Vindiciae contra Tyrannos, says Laski, "is built on the assumption that it

is the duty of the magistrate to represent the popular idea of right."

Harold J. Laski, A Defence of Liberty against Tyrants: A translation of the

Vindiciae contra Tyrannos by Junius Brutus (London, 1924), pp. 47, 48.


40. In the Middle Ages, says Maitland, "God Himself appeared as being the

ultimate cause of Natural Law. This was so, if, with Ockham, Gerson,

D'Ailly, men saw in Natural Law a Command proceeding from the Will of God,

which command therefore was righteous and binding. It was so, if, with Hugh

de St. Victor, Gabriel Biel and Almain, they placed the constitutive moment

of the Law of Nature in the Being of God, but discovered dictates of Eternal

Reason declaring what is right, which dictates were unalterable even by God

Himself. Lastly it was so, if, with Aquinas and his followers, they (on the

one hand) derived the content of the Law of Nature from the Reason that is

immanent in the being of God and is directly determined by that Natura Rerum

which is comprised in God Himself, but (on the other hand) traced the

binding force of this law to God's Will." Gierke, Political Theories of the

Middle Ages, p. 172.


41. Thus Baldus claimed that on the authority of the law of nature neither

the Emperor nor the Pope could validate the taking of usury. For interesting

efforts to justify slavery and the ownership of property though contrary to

the law of nature see Carlyle, op. cit., I, chaps. 10, 12, 16 and II, Pt. I,

chaps. 4, 5, Pt. II, chaps. 5, 6. See also, Gierke, Johannes Althusius, pp.

272 ff.


42. Goldast, Monarchia, II, 932 and Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle

Ages, pp. 172, 173. For the distinction between principal and secondary

rules of the law of nature, see ibid., p. 175; also, Johannes Althusius, pp.

273, 274.


43. To Gentilis, who with Grotius may be credited with the formulation of

systematic rules of international law based largely on the law of nature,

natural law comprised "such rules of justice as would govern men as moral

and responsible beings, living in society independently of human

institutions -- in other words, in a 'state of nature.'" De legationibus,

II, 18, and Coleman Phillipson in Great Jurists of the World (Boston, 1914),

pp. 119, 120.


44. Edited by Ernest Nys (Washington, 1917). Cf. works of Francisco di

Vittoria, De Jure Belli and De Indis (1557).


45. William A. Dunning, Political Theories from Luther to Montesquieu (New

York, 1905), pp. 132 ff.


46. Ibid., pp. 13 ff. "There was also a philosophic, deductive law of

nations before Grotius, resting upon the same foundations as the natural law

of the schoolmen, and cultivated particularly by the Spanish moralists,

especially by Francisco Vittoria and his followers." General Survey of

European Authors (Continental Legal History Series), p. 412. For theories of

a state of nature and of an original compact, cf. Suarez, De Legibus, III,

4, and Mariana, De Rege, I, 1, 2, 8.


47. Roscoe Pound, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (New Haven,

1922), pp. 82, 83.


48. Professor Dickinson, referring to the fact that the natural law

theories of Grotius are often misunderstood, claims that "Grotius presented

a less comprehensive discussion of natural law than either Suarez before him

or Pufendorf who came after." The Equality of States in International Law, p.

43. The law of nature which these men found, Pollock observes "was no mere

speculative survival or rhetorical ornament. It was a quite mediaeval

theory. What is more, it never ceased to be essentially rationalist and

progressive. Modern aberrations have led to the widespread belief that the

law of nature is only a cloak for arbitrary dogmas or fancies." Essays in

the Law, p. 32.


49. Cf. De Jure Belli ac Pacis, Book I, chap. 1.


50. For indications of the use of the doctrine of natural law and natural

rights by jurists and text writers in formulating principles of

international law, see Grotius, op. cit. (1672); Pufendorf, De Jure Naturae

et Gentium (1672); Burlamaqui, Principes du droit naturel (1758); Rutherford,

Institutes of Natural Law (1754-56). The natural law doctrine that contracts

are binding was in Grotius' opinion a limitation on the authority of

sovereigns. Grotius, op. cit., Book III, chap. 24.


51. Referring to the ancient origin of the idea of equality, Professor

Radin observes that "the East gave to Rome both the practical fact of

inequality, fixed into unescapable ordines and regulated by the needs of the

state, and the corrective ideal of a perfect city of equals living in

accordance with a Law of Nature." "Roman Concepts of Equality," Political

Science Quarterly, XXXVIII (June, 1923), 288.


52. "Every one in a state of grace," thought Wycliffe, "has real lordship

over the whole universe." De Civili Dominio (ed. by R. L. Poole), pp.

xxii-xxiv.


53. Harold J. Laski, op. cit., Introduction, and Pollock, Essays in the Law,

p. 50. For the way in which the leaders of the Reformation built on the

political ideas of the church theologians, such as the theory of the social

contract, the sovereignty of princes, etc., see Jean Brissaud, The History

of French Public Law, trans. by James W. Gamer in Continental Legal History

Series (Boston, 1915), p. 536. With the exception of Bodin, Hobbes, and

Bossuet, he notes, most political writers followed the theories of natural

law and attempted to justify political power on the basis of the idea of

justice.


54. See William S. Holdsworth, History of English Law, IV (London 1922-25),

190 ff., and Dunning, op. cit., chap. 3. Cf. Gierke, Johannes Althusius, pp.

299 ff., on the doctrine of Staatsraison, which tended to weaken the

limitations on the state attributed to divine and natural laws.


55. Despite his positivist tendencies Hobbes regarded natural law as eternal

and immutable. Leviathan, chap. 15; cf. Pollock, Essays in the Law, pp. 59,

60.


56. General Survey of Events, Sources, Persons and Movements in Continental

Legal History, Continental Legal History Series (Boston, 1912), p. 415.


57. On Pufendorf and the development of the law of nature, consult Coleman

Phillipson's account in the Great Jurists of the World, pp. 311 ff.; also

Gierke, Johannes Althusius, pp 300 ff.


58. John Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Government, Book II, sec. 6. "The

state of nature has a law to govern it, which obliges everyone: and reason,

which is that law, teaches all mankind, who will but consult it, that being

all equal and independent, no one ought to harm another in his life, health,

liberty, or possessions."


59. John Locke, op. cit., chap. 11. "These are the bounds which the trust,

that is put in them by the society and the law of God and nature, have set

to the legislative power of every commonwealth, in all forms of government.

First: They are to govern by promulgated established laws, not to be varied

in particular cases, but to have one rule for rich and poor, for the

favorite at court, and the countryman at plough. Secondly: These laws also

ought to be designed for no other end ultimately but the good of the people.

Thirdly: They must not raise taxes on the property of the people without the

consent of the people, given by themselves or their deputies.... Fourthly:

The legislative neither must nor can transfer the power of making laws to

anybody else, or place it anywhere but where the people have." Ibid., chaps.

11, 18, and Discourses Concerning Government, III, sec. 11. John Neville

Figgis, The Divine Right of Kings (2d ed, Cambridge, 1922), p. 242, "The

more closely Locke's treatise is studied, the more clearly will it be seen

that it is an attack directed far more against the idea of sovereignty, than

against the claims of absolute monarchy."


60. Cf. J. Castillejoy Duarte, "Kohler's Philosophical Position," Appendix

to Kohler, The Philosophy of Law, trans by Adalbert Albrecht in Modern Legal

Philosophy Series (Boston, 1914), XII, 335.


61. Cf. J. Castillejoy Duarte, "Kohler's Philosophical Position," XII, 352,

353. "The exponents of the law of nature are not always at one in every

particular, but their fundamental conception is that 'Nature' represents

the supreme, unifying, controlling power manifesting itself in the universe

at large; and that 'Reason' is a special aspect of this principle looked at

from the point of view of man and the operation of his mental and moral

faculties. In so far as men are men they possess common elements; and in

their political and social life these elements inevitably emerge and are

recognizable in custom and law. Hence the substratum of this law is thought

to be of necessity established by the universal guiding force, personified

as nature. Such natural law represents the permanent portion of human law in

general, and it is prior and superior to positive legislation, which is only

a supplement thereto demanded by changing circumstances in different

localities. Conventional justice may well elaborate or extend its

applications, but must not alter its essential content or violate its

spirit." Coleman Phillipson in Great Jurists of the World, p. 311.


62. Georges Davy, Le droit, l'idéalisme et l'expérience (Paris, 1922), pp.

41 ff.


                    CHAPTER II


           ENGLISH HIGHER LAW DOCTRINES


THE traditional view of English legal historians was that in English law

there are relatively slight traces of the influence of the Roman law or of

its mediaeval offshoot, the canonical codes. It was taken for granted,

therefore, that the ancient and mediaeval concepts of natural law, though

occasionally referred to by English text writers and judges, were never

accepted in any authoritative way as principles of English law. Recent

investigations in English legal history have modified to some extent the

traditional views regarding the acceptance of Roman law principles and have

tended to indicate some important connections between the main currents of

continental legal thought and the emerging common law of England.[1] And we

are now assured that one of the main connecting links between the two legal

systems was the doctrine of the law of nature or law of reason of ancient

and mediaeval times.


1. Natural Law Ideas and English Doctrines relating to Fundamental Laws. In

the processes by which Anglo-Saxon and Norman customs were transformed into

law, may be traced the growth of ideas relating to a superior law in

England. Authorities do not agree, however, as to the significance of higher

law concepts in the development of English law. Certain authors maintain,

with Professor McIlwain, that customary laws with no assignable beginning

and accepted as a rule without question, in the course of time acquired a

character of inviolability; and whether this inviolability be the result or

the cause of the preservation of these customs, the feeling has somehow come

into existence that there is a law fundamental and unalterable, and rights

derived from it indefeasible and inalienable. The content of the law may not

be definite, -- in England it was always far from definite, -- but the idea

has lodged itself in men's minds as a formative principle, and once lodged

it colors everything.[2]


This idea though vague and indefinite in outline was at times, they assert,

a significant force in the development of law in mediaeval England,[3] and

as a result of it certain principles of mediaeval customary law were thought

to be beyond the power of Parliament to change, and were likely to be

identified with the law of nature.[4] A few provisions of Magna Carta were

occasionally referred to as fundamental and immutable.


William E. Holdsworth,[5] William S. McKechnie,[6] Edward Jenks,[7] and L.

O. Pike[8] have questioned the great claims made for Magna Carta as a

charter for constitutional government and have emphasized that the barons

who forced the King's signature to the document "were guided by class

interests and aimed at reaction and anarchy rather than at legality and

progress." Vinogradoff[9] thinks that these historians fail to explain the

reasons for the great influence of the document on the national life of

England and why it became the watchword of English legalism. He believes

that the feudal interpretation of the Charter fails to take into account

sufficiently that certain provisions tended to impress upon all the

necessity of the appreciation of the rule of law in ordinary legal relations

and to carry over this idea from the class justice of the feudal lords to

the common law of the growing commonwealth.[10] At least there are some

vague general statements which appear to consider Magna Carta in the nature

of a superior law.[11]


Whether or not these ancient customs and the written provisions of the Great

Charter had the characteristics of fundamental laws which were not subject

to change by statutes is a controversial matter which need not be determined

here. It will suffice to note that as a result of a careful study of the

Yearbooks Mr. Plucknett concludes that the examples which Professor McIlwain

cites to sustain his contention that there were fundamental laws in England

in the mediaeval period "afford no support for the thesis of a supreme,

fundamental law."[12] Whatever conclusion may be arrived at in this

controversy there is substantial agreement among the authorities that not

infrequent use was made of the concept of natural law. Mr. Plucknett regards

the instances of such use, which he discovered in the fourteenth century, as

rather loose and vague references to custom, to conscience, or to the

colloquial sense of the unreasonable.[13] Perhaps the difference in

interpretation of these legal phenomena may be due in part to the point of

view of the investigator just as many American legal historians find no bona

fide traces of natural law doctrines in the legal decisions of the American

courts and others discover many illustrations of the applications of these

doctrines in the opinions of the judges.


The use of the term "law of nature" was quite sparing[14] and seems to have

been avoided in the development of equity. More frequent applications of the

term may be found in the beginnings of the law merchant.[15]


If natural law terms were not adopted in the beginning of English equity

procedure, generous use of the ideas involved therein was made by the

chancellors. The common lawyers of the thirteenth and early fourteenth

centuries according to Holdsworth included under the term "equity"


    such ideas as abstract justice and analogy. The ecclesiastical
    chancellors, on the other hand, based their equity on the
    more restricted idea that the court ought to compel each
    individual litigant to fulfill all the duties which reason and
    conscience would dictate to a person in his situation. Reason
    and conscience must decide how and when the injustice
    caused by the generality of the rules of law was to be cured.
    They were the executive agents in the work of applying to
    each individual case those dictates of the law of God and
    nature, upon which the ecclesiastical chancellors considered
    equity to rest.[16]


Maitland believed that there was a more direct and insistent use of the law

of nature ideas in the development of equity.[17]


2. Natural Law and the Doctrine of the Supremacy of the Law. The evolution

of English ideas relating to a higher law was intimately bound up with the

emerging concept of the supremacy of law. From the dominant idea of

mediaeval thinkers that law should be supreme, and superior to the state

itself, English judges evolved the peculiar English doctrine of the

supremacy of the law, which bound even the King.[18] Bracton, for instance,

who made use of the Roman concept of natural law, regarded the King as

subject to law but did not suggest any effective remedy for a breach of law

by the King.[19] However, the courts of law at this time were regarded as

possessing certain political functions on which Professor Holdsworth

comments as follows:


    The law was a rule of conduct which all members of the
    state, rulers and subjects alike, were bound to obey, the
    whole conduct of government consisted in the enforcement
    of the law, and in the maintenance of the rights and duties to
    which it gave rise. It was a necessary consequence of this
    theory of government that the courts should possess political
    functions; for they existed not merely to do justice as
    between private persons, but also to see that the law itself
    was not arbitrarily infringed or altered by the king or any
    other person.[20]


The doctrine that there were superior principles of right and justice which

acts of Parliament might not contravene was asserted and defended vigorously

and effectively by Lord Coke in his controversy with the Stuart Kings.[21]

In the well-known case of Dr. Bonham, wherein the Royal College of

Physicians attempted to impose a fine for illegal practice of medicine, Coke

asserted that it was an established maxim of the common law that no man can

be judge in his own case. And he continued: "It appears in our books that in

many cases the common law will control acts of Parliament and sometimes

adjudge them to be utterly void; for when an act of Parliament is against

common right or reason, or repugnant or impossible to be performed, the

common law will control it and adjudge such act to be void."[22] A number of

cases were cited in support of this dictum.[23] Concerning this opinion

there have been many disputes. Supporters of Coke have tried to show that

the opinion with the precedents upon which it is based is an essentially

accurate reflection of the situation in England at the time when the

principle of the supremacy of law was winning its way over the tendencies

toward the establishment of an absolute monarchy.[24] On the other hand,

historians have endeavored to prove that the cases on which Coke based his

theory of the supremacy of the common law courts do not bear the

construction which he gave to them. Most English legal authorities agree

that there is no specific case on record in which an English court of

justice has directly overruled or disregarded the plain meaning of an act of

Parliament.[25] In England the mediaeval doctrine that law is above the

state, which meant that there was a fundamental law which could not be

changed, came to mean primarily the supremacy of law which Parliament could

change at will. The dictum of Coke in Bonham's case that courts may refuse

to enforce an act of Parliament when it is "against common right and

reason," or "repugnant, or impossible to be performed," Holdsworth considers

as founded on little mediaeval authority. The cases cited by Coke, he

thinks, amount to little more than that the courts will interpret statutes

strictly.[26] Even when the supremacy of Parliament was recognized there

were few who would have admitted that Parliament possessed unlimited powers.

Even Sir Francis Bacon, who took the side of the King against Coke in his

assertions of common law supremacy admitted the superior force of the law of

nature.[27] But the theoretical limits conceived as binding Parliament lost

much of their significance when this body asserted its authority over the

King and the courts.[28]


Recognizing that in the first few centuries after the establishment of

Parliament there were doubts whether private acts could be passed which were

judicial in character, such as bills of attainder, it was contended that in

Henry VIII's reign all such doubts were removed and "the judges were obliged

to admit that these acts, however morally unjust, must be obeyed."[29]

Whatever effects Coke's attempt to set up a superior and fundamental law may

have had, the Revolution of 1688 marked the abandonment of his doctrine as a

practical principle of English politics.[30]


It is necessary to distinguish between the idea of an appeal to a

fundamental law, when the appeal is primarily in the nature of a criticism

and finds its chief sanction in the ancient right to resist arbitrary

authority by revolutionary methods, and an appeal to a fundamental law which

the courts must hold as binding in order to protect citizens from arbitrary

authority. The appeal to a fundamental law as embodying superior principles

of right or of equity is a common method of resisting injustice and accounts

in part for the extreme pretensions of Coke. It was in this connection that

the assertive chief justice set about to revive interest in Magna Carta as a

fundamental charter of liberties.[31] After a period of comparative neglect

the Charter was rendered popular by its use as a weapon to check the

extensive prerogatives claimed by James and Charles. Coke, Hampden, Eliot,

and Pym gave an interpretation to long-forgotten clauses of Magna Carta that

supported their partisan views of constitutional reform. The Great Charter,

McKechnie observes, "as enshrined in the imaginations of the parliamentary

leaders of the Puritan Rebellion was, to a great extent, the creation of

Coke's legal intellect." So great was this creative effort of Coke and his

followers that a contrast may well be made between two Great Charters --

one, the original feudal charter; the other, the seventeenth-century

charter, as it came to be accepted by the political leaders, the judges and

lawyers, and the majority of the people of England.[32]


A middle ground between the pretensions of Coke, that both the King and

Parliament were limited by a common reason and superior principles of

justice of which the common law courts were the ultimate interpreters, and

that of Pollock, Holland, and Holdsworth, to the effect that no cases are on

record in which the will of the King and of Parliament were thwarted by the

courts, resting their opinion on a higher law basis, probably comes nearer

to stating the actual situation in England. Even if it be true, as is

claimed, that there is no case on record in which the clearly expressed will

of the King and of Parliament were really checked by the courts there were

instances in which the courts, interpreting the common law changed the

meaning of statutes, refused to give them the effect intended, or to apply a

rule of his majesty in council until the King, Lords, and Commons joined in

an unmistakable mandate, which the courts reluctantly at times conceded it

was their duty to obey. Short of such mandates clearly and unequivocally

expressed there was a wide realm in which the courts applied the basic

principles of reason of the common law and were seldom interfered with

either by the King or by Parliament.[33] Moreover, the frequent

confirmations or reaffirmations of Magna Carta served to impress upon the

public mind that enshrined therein were fundamental principles upon which

the superstructure of the English constitution might arise. Coke's

reiteration of these principles served to strengthen the basic doctrine of

the supremacy of the law.


It was Coke's version of the supremacy of the common law, as an

exemplification of rules of reason and of justice, which the courts must

enforce even above the King and Parliament, that served as a convenient

argument when American justices were confronted with the demand that limits

must be placed on legislative powers to safeguard individual rights and

privileges.[34]


Blackstone in his Commentaries gave a version of natural law which, through

the popularity of his work, was given wide currency. "Man, considered as a

creature," he said,


    must necessarily be subject to the laws of his Creator....
    This will of his maker is called the law of nature.... This law
    of nature, being co-eval with mankind, and dictated by God
    himself, is of course superior in obligation to any other. It is
    binding over all the globe, in all countries, and at all times; no
    human laws are of any validity, if contrary to this; and such
    of them as are valid derive all their force and all their
    authority, mediately and immediately, from this original....
    Upon these two foundations, the law of nature and the law
    of revelation, depend all human laws; that is to say no human
    laws should be suffered to contradict these ... nay, if any
    human law should allow or enjoin us to commit it, we are
    bound to transgress that human law, or else we offend both
    the natural and the divine.[35]


He placed these precepts in the realm of moral restraints by later admitting

that no authority could prevent Parliament from enacting laws contrary to

them. With the supremacy of Parliament generally accepted the references to

superior natural laws become less frequent.


3. Evidences of Natural Law Ideas in Judicial Decisions. The efforts to

predicate a basis for a fundamental law, which were gradually brushed aside

as Parliament gained ascendency over the other departments of government,

are by no means the only attempts to apply the ancient and mediaeval

concepts of natural law in England. Sir Frederick Pollock has indicated the

inaccuracy of the prevailing view that English law was comparatively free

from the influence of natural law doctrines.[36] When Roman and canon law

doctrines came into disrepute in England Pollock observes that the law of

nature terminology was frowned upon and gradually dropped, only, to be

restored in common law terminology in the words "reason" and "reasonable."

Due to a natural aversion to Continental ideals and to the influences of

church law and of Roman law it became the English practice to speak of

reason in preference to the mediaeval concept of the law of nature.[37]

Natural justice or reason which the common law recognizes and applies does

not differ from the law of nature which the Romans identified with jus

gentium and the mediaeval jurists accepted as being divine law revealed

chiefly through man's natural reason.[38]


Pollock's summary of the extensive ramifications of the doctrine of

reasonableness or the English version of natural law deserves to be quoted:


    Reasonable price and reasonable time are among the most
    familiar elements in our law of contract. Oftentimes no more
    definite instruction can be given to a jury than to award
    reasonable damages. "Natural reason and the just
    construction of the law," as Blackstone said, have given us
    the various applications of the common counts, extending to
    the whole field of what we now call quasi-contract. In Lord
    Mansfield's hands the principles of natural equity were an
    enchanter's wand to call a whole new world of justice into
    being. The test of what a reasonable man's conduct would
    be in the circumstances governs our modern law of
    negligence and underlies those branches of it which have
    been specialized into groups of definite rules. Almost in our
    own time a simple and wholly untechnical conception of the
    same kind has been developed into the doctrine of estoppel
    "in pais," perhaps the most powerful and flexible instrument
    to be found in any system of civil jurisprudence.[39]


Since the Middle Ages the law of nature or its offshoot, the law of reason,

has been an important factor in the development of equity, of the law

merchant, and of the law of nations.[40] Principles of natural justice are

also recognized and applied today in cases where the courts review the

exercise of quasi-judicial powers by administrative boards, committees, or

commissions.[41]


One need not seek far in English case law to find impressive examples of the

use of the doctrine of reason or reasonableness, though the law of nature

connotations of these phrases may be inadvertently or purposely

concealed.[42]


The law of nature as "the living embodiment of the collective reason of

mankind" has, indeed, been adopted by the common law in substance if not in

express terms.[43] Despite the persistent applications of natural law

concepts in English law certain English jurists frequently refer to the

philosophy of law as comprehended under Naturrecht as a German product, and

criticize such thinking as "a mere system of elaborate trifling."[44]


4. Types of Natural Law Theories applied in English Law. It is apparent that

natural law concepts of one kind or another served various purposes in

English legal history. First, there was in mediaeval times an identification

of the term "natural" with the "customary" rules of the common law. The

importance attached to these natural or customary rules, the origins of

which were unknown, gave an element of certainty and permanence to the

emerging system of the common law, and encouraged the belief that certain

laws were fundamental. As the courts were the prime agencies in the

application of these rules it encouraged the recognition of the supremacy of

the law as interpreted by the justices.


Second, the doctrine of the supremacy of the law was given a prominent place

in the conflict between the King and the barons when resistance to the King

was supported by reference to the fundamental immemorial rights of

Englishmen -- essentially a form of appeal to a higher law. The assertion of

the idea that there was a law above the King and above Parliament as that

body gained in prominence, despite the differences of opinion regarding its

significance, became a vital principle in the growth of English

constitutionalism. It encouraged a more definite recognition of the

distinction between ordinary law and fundamental law. As a means of

supporting the revolt against arbitrary rulers the concepts of natural law

and natural justice were revolutionary and idealistic.


Third, the theory that law is of divine origin and that such rules as accord

with this law are natural and valid was inherited from Continental European

thought and was accepted by some English lawyers and jurists until the bonds

with the Roman church and the mediaeval canonists were severed. As in

Blackstone's Commentaries, the theory may be repeated at times with little

reference to its practical importance in English law.


Fourth, law of nature ideas were the sources from which the common law

judges derived their notions of rules of reason and natural justice whereby

they aimed to rationalize the legal processes. In this role these ideas

became active and progressive principles of legal growth. They assisted in

establishing close relations between legal logic and practical experience.

The growth of the common law in an inductive, experimental, and pragmatic

manner was conditioned by the famous rule of reason, which prevented the

rigid and archaic procedure and rules of the system from remaining long in

force when they were not in accord with social and economic conditions. The

manifold appearances of the rule of reason in Anglo-American law bear

witness to the fact that natural law doctrines are not ignored or discarded

in the jurisdictions which are subject to this law. But differences in

terminology have tended to obscure the continuous applications in English

law of natural law concepts which play an important rôle in Continental

legal systems.


5. Differences between the Anglo-American and the Continental Legal Points

of View. The fact that in Continental systems of law two words are in use

for the ideas comprehended in the English word "law" differentiates certain

phases of legal thought of Continental nations in contrast with that of

Anglo-American countries. Two sets of words to express two ideas of law are:


                 Latin     jus         lex
                 German    Recht[45]   Gesetz
                 French    droit       loi
                 Italian   diritto     legge
                 Spanish   derecho     ley



Though the two terms are not always clearly distinguished, lex is the term

which commonly designates written enactments or rules and jus[46] refers to

those rules which are just or inherently right or equitable. To the Romans

jus naturale comprised the eternal principles of justice, as understood and

appreciated by the human reason; but in the Middle Ages, as we have seen,

the jus naturale frequently became the lex naturalis, or positive enactments

proceeding from God, which were considered superior to all human laws.


When law was based largely on custom and on the application of traditional

rules, and legislation was comparatively rare, the lex or loi was regarded

as the embodiment of reason, for customs and traditions to be valid were

expected to be reasonable. Later the distinction between droit and loi was

more clearly drawn. In modern terminology la loi is a declaration of the

will of the sovereign upon an object of common interest,[47] and droit is

the aggregate of precepts or laws (lois) governing the conduct of man toward

his fellows, the observance of which it is possible, and at the same time

useful, to assure by way of external coercion. Thus with a term to

characterize the enactments, usually in writing, to which men are expected

to conform and the rules or ideas of justice which are to guide and control

civil conduct, it is possible to differentiate between the ordinary

conventional laws of a time and place and the underlying rules and

principles which form the very groundwork of the legal structure. The terms

droit or Recht[48] combining the ideas of a rule of civil conduct and a

principle of justice, necessarily mingle law and morals in juridical

speculation, whereas with a single term -- law -- English jurists have been

inclined to divorce law and ethics.


"To this difference of language, and to the consequent difference in the

tone of juridical speculation," Mr. Salmond thinks,


    we may attribute, more than to any other single cause, the
    acceptance on the Continent and the rejection in England of
    that which the French call droit naturel, and the Germans
    Naturrecht.[49] It follows that our language can supply no
    equivalent for these terms, for they combine ethical and
    juridical significations in a manner not permitted to English
    speech. To express the ethical meaning we must use the
    terms natural right or natural justice; while the juridical
    meaning is expressed by the terms natural law or the law
    of nature. For a full equivalent for the French and German
    expressions, we may resort to the corresponding Latin jus
    naturale, which possesses the same twofold meaning, being
    either justitia naturalis or lex naturae.[50]


The differences in terminology and points of view are likely to be

exaggerated, for whether or not separate words be used for definite written

enactments and for rules of right or principles of justice the results in

legal thinking do not vary greatly on this account. The fact that writers in

Europe give a great deal more attention to legal speculations and that the

schools of droit naturel or Naturrecht have produced elaborate and

influential treatises is due rather to a different approach to philosophy

and to speculative thought than to variations in terms. The Englishman's

effort to divorce morals and law is, of course, not successful and his vain

attempts to repudiate natural law thinking have failed to conceal the

substratum of rationalizing in accordance with well-known natural law

connotations. The obvious methods of suppression of natural law concepts are

but a reflex of a type of mind which depreciates rationalizing and

philosophizing at the same time that new ideas and new institutions are

being molded in accordance with the assumptions and preconceived notions of

particular schools of philosophic thought.[51] Englishmen are less prone to

formulate the speculative ideas which are the warp and woof of their social

fabric and they have been masters in the application of theories which,

however, have been thought to be more acceptable because they were believed

to be concealed.[52]


It was in the United States and in France, however, that different types of

natural law concepts were to take shape. Higher law ideas were soon to

become in these countries the source and sanction for portions of private

and public law.




1. C. H. McIlwain, The High Court of Parliament and its Supremacy (New

Haven, 1910). Sir Frederick Pollock thinks "there is a real link between the

mediaeval doctrine of the law of nature and the principles of the common

law. It is given by the use -- correct in both systems, though constant,

indeed exclusive in the Common Law, and rather sparing in the Canon Law --

of the words 'reason,' and 'reasonable.'" Essays in the Law, p. 57; see also

Holdsworth's A History of English Law, II, 133 ff. for a modern

interpretation of the adoption of Roman law ideas in English law.


"English as well as Continental jurists and judges," says Professor H. D.

Hazeltine, "were under the influence of doctrines which ascribed the jus

divinum and the jus naturale the quality of immutability and rendered the

man-made positive law opposed to them null and void. Bracton writes under

the influence of these doctrines; and the early common lawyers treat the

common law itself as the embodiment of the jus naturale in the guise of

'reason.'" Preface to Theodore F. T. Plucknett, Statutes and their

Interpretation in the First Half of the Fourteenth Century (Cambridge,

1922), p. xxiii.


2. C. H. McIlwain, op. cit., pp. 51, 52. See also Sir Paul Vinogradoff,

"Magna Carta Chapter 39," Malden, Magna Carta Commemoration Essays, p. 85.


3. McIlwain, op. cit., p. 53. McIlwain continues: "There is a fundamental

law which binds a king and beyond which he may not go. The principle has

persisted through all changes.... Men may not always have been clear as to

what particular rights or liberties were guaranteed by the fundamental law,

but as to the existence of such a law there was no doubt, and any act that

violated it was in a true sense felt to be no law." Ibid., pp. 57, 63. For

the use of the term "common law" as signifying in a real sense a fundamental

law, cf. McIlwain, "Magna Carta and Common Law," in Magna Carta

Commemoration Essays (London, 1917), pp. 122 ff. and 175 ff. This judgment

is not in accord with the opinions of a number of English legal historians,

who regard the theories of a fundamental law, which is superior to the King

and to Parliament, as having little evidence to substantiate them, so far as

the actual operation of the law in England is concerned.


4. McIlwain, The High Court of Parliament and its Supremacy, p. 99.

Expressing the view that the omnipotence of the British Parliament, on which

English jurists have usually built their theories of sovereignty, is really

exceptional, Sir Frederick Pollock says: "The omnipotence of Parliament was

not the orthodox theory of English law, if orthodox at all, even in Holt's

time. It was formally adopted, and then not without lip-service to natural

law, in Blackstone's Commentaries. Sir Thomas Smith had asserted it plainly

enough two centuries before Blackstone; but he spoke the mind of the Tudor

councillors of state, not the judges and serjeants. Down to the Revolution

the common legal opinion was that statutes might be void as 'contrary to

common right' -- an insular version, as I have pointed out elsewhere, and

generally received natural law." "A Plea for an Historical Interpretation,"

Law Quarterly Review, XXXIX (April, 1923), 165. See also the Expansion of

the Common Law (London, 1904), p. 123.


5. A History of English Law, II, 207 ff.


6. Magna Carta (New York, 1915).


7. "The Myth of Magna Carta," The Independent Review, IV (1904-05), 260 ff.


8. Constitutional History of the House of Lords (London, 1894).


9. Sir Paul Vinogradoff, "Magna Carta Chapter 39," Magna Carta Commemoration

Essays, p. 79.


10. Vinogradoff, op. cit., pp. 84, 95.


11. Cf. citations in Rodney L. Mott, Due Process of Law (Indianapolis,

1926), chap. 3.


12. Op. cit., pp. 26-31, 35, 36. For a critical analysis by the same author

of Coke's broad claims for the existence of a fundamental law in England,

see also "Bonham's Case and Judicial Review," Harvard Law Review, XL

(November, 1926), 30.


13. Op. cit., pp. 35, 36.


14. See Fortescue, De Natura Legis Naturae and De Laudibus Legum Angliae,

chap. 16, and Calvin's Case, 7 Co. Rep. 121. Holdsworth finds an occasional

use of the term "law of nature" in the Yearbooks and rather frequent

references to the idea that law must accord with reason, Appendix II,

Holdsworth's History of English Law, II, 602.


15. Cf. Malines, Lex Mercatoria (1656), p. 311, and Sir John Davis,

Concerning Impositions (1656), chap. 3. Pollock, Essays in the Law (London,

1922), pp. 53 ff.


16. Op cit., V, 216.


17. "On the whole, my notion is that with the idea of a law of nature in

their minds, they decided cases without much reference to any written

authority, now making use of some analogy drawn from the common law and now

some great maxim of jurisprudence which they borrowed from the canonists or

the civilians." F. W. Maitland, Equity, p. 9.


18. Holdsworth, op. cit., II, 131, 195, 196. Professor Adams speaks of "the

idea that there existed a body of understood, more or less definitely

formulated rights which the king was bound to observe," as a "guiding and

creative principle" of the English constitution. George Burton Adams, The

Origin of the English Constitution (New Haven, 1920), p. 157.


19. De Legibus el Consuetudinibus Angliae, III, 9, 2, fol. 107 b and

Holdsworth, II, 252, 256. Bracton copied with slight changes his account of

jus naturale from Azo, who in his edition of the Institutes, follows

Ulpian's classification. See Professor Maitland's Selections 8, Selden

Society's Publications (London, 1895), p. 33. A passage of the Roman code

indicated that it was the duty of the Emperor to acknowledge that he was

bound by law, Code 1. 14, 4. This idea was accepted by Azo and through him

was incorporated in Bracton's De Legibus et Consuetudinibus Angliae, II, 16,

3. See also Carlyle, A History of Mediaeval Political Theory in the West,

III, 34 ff., for Bracton's theory of limits on the king's authority.


20. Op. cit., IV, 169. The author refers to two striking examples of

mediaeval courts which actually exercised political powers, namely, the

Justizia of Aragon and the Parlement of Paris. "The supremacy of the law was

a theme on which Coke was never tired of dilating. In fact, it would not be

going too far to say that it was the view of all the leading lawyers,

statesmen and publicists of the Tudor period." Ibid., pp. 201, 202.


21. See Bonham's Case, 8 Co. 118a, b; Plucknett, "Bonham's Case and Judicial

Review," Harv. Law Rev., XL, 30; also C. G. Haines, The American Doctrine of

Judicial Supremacy (New York, 1914), pp. 25 ff.


22. 8 Co. (C.P. 1610) 114a and 2 Brownl. (C.P. 1610) 255, 265.


23. Tregor's Case Y. B. Pasch, 8 Edw. III, 26; Fitzherbert, Annuitie 41. For

a thorough analysis of these cases, consult Plucknett, Statutes and their

Interpretation in the First Half of the Fourteenth Century (Cambridge,

1922), pp. 66-70 "and Bonham's Case and Judicial Review," Harv. Law Rev.,

XL, 35 ff. Cf. also Holdsworth, op. cit., V, 428, 454, 491 ff.


24. Cf. views of Sir Henry Hobart in Day v. Savadge, Hobart, 85 (K. B. 1614)

and Lord Holt in City of London v. Wood, 12 Modern 669, 687 (Mayor's Court,

1701).


25. Pound, "Common Law and Legislation," Harv. Law Rev., XXI (April, 1908),

391. "We find," says Pollock, "a series of dicta, extending to the early

part of the eighteenth century, to the effect that statutes contrary to

'natural justice' or 'common right' may be treated as void. This opinion is

most strongly expressed by Coke, but like many of his confident opinions, is

extra-judicial. Although Coke was no canonist, we may be pretty sure that it

was ultimately derived from the canonist doctrine prevailing on the

continent of Europe. In England it was never a practical doctrine." The

Expansion of the Common Law, pp. 121, 122. He claims that no case is known

in fact, in which an English court of justice has openly taken on itself to

overrule or disregard the plain meaning of an act of Parliament. First Book

of Jurisprudence (3d ed, 1911), p. 264, and Essays in the Law (London,

1922), p 41. This view of Pollock is confirmed by J. G. Holland, who states

that "these dicta, though approved of by Lord Holt in London v. Wood, appear

never to have been followed in practice." The Elements of Jurisprudence

(12th ed., New York, 1917), pp. 37, 38.


Plucknett notes that this judgment needs to be slightly modified so as to

account for the few instances in which courts refused to apply acts regarded

as impossible to carry out or absurd in their consequences, Harv. Law Rev.,

XL, 36 ff.


26. Holdsworth, op. cit., II, 441-443. This view is supported by F. W.

Maitland, who thinks that the precedents cited by Coke do not bear him out.

The Constitutional History of England (Cambridge, 1909), p 301. From this

slim foundation, Plucknett observes, Coke developed a theory all his own --

to the effect that there was a superior body of rules which bound the King

and Parliament. The subsequent results of Coke's ideas are traced in

"Bonham's Case," Harv. Law. Rev., XL, 49 ff. This article should be

consulted for an analysis of the cases reported by Coke and those in which

his views were approved.


27. "Our law is grounded upon the law of nature.... For as the common law is

more worthy than the statute law, so this law is more worthy than them both"

Bacon, Works (ed. by Spedding, Ellis, and Heath), XV, 202 ff.


28. Holdsworth explains the merging of the supremacy of law with the concept

of parliamentary supremacy, as follows:


"But when the Act of Parliament had acquired this authority, the last

remnants of the idea that there might be fundamental laws, which could not

be changed by any person or body of persons in the state, necessarily

disappeared. It was obviously difficult to assign any limits to the power

of the Acts of a body which had effected changes so sweeping as those

effected by the Reformation Parliament. I do not forget that Coke sometimes

writes as it he believed in the supremacy of a law which even Parliament

could not change But it would, I think, be a mistake to lay too much stress

on isolated statements of this kind. In the first place, Coke was often

inconsistent because he had the mind of an advocate, and therefore often

allowed himself to be carried away by the argument which he was urging at

the moment. In the second place, he was so thoroughly steeped in mediaeval

law that he sometimes reproduces ideas which he himself would have admitted

to be archaic. In the third place, he is often writing and thinking of the

supremacy of the existing law, and not of the question whether Parliament

was competent to change it. When Parliament is not sitting it is the

existing law, as interpreted by the judges, which is supreme; and when, as

in the seventeenth century, the different component parts of the Parliament

cannot act together, the same result ensues. In the Fourth Institute, when

he is dealing specifically with the powers of Parliament, and in other

passages, he admits its supremacy freely and fully.


In the sixteenth century, therefore (whatever may be true of earlier

periods), it is clear that the supremacy of the law, taught by Bracton and

the Yearbooks, has come to mean, not the supremacy of an unchangeable law,

but the supremacy of a law which Parliament can change. The supremacy of the

law is coming to mean the supremacy of Parliament. That the lawyers never

placed any difficulty in the way of this evolution was a fact which had

large effects upon the future development, both of the constitution and of

the common law." Op. cit., IV, 186, 187.


29. Holdsworth, op. cit., IV, 185. "It was only in England that the powers

of Parliament had come to be regarded as the main security for the supremacy

of the law; for it was only in England that the lawyers, by freely admitting

the legislative supremacy of Parliament, had gained the support of

Parliament and the nation for the mediaeval doctrine of the supremacy of

law." Ibid., p. 189.


30. On the tendency of Coke to assume the rôle of a strenuous advocate in

the causes which enlisted his interest, on his lack of consistency in

relation to such matters as the supremacy of the common law, and on his

uncritical use of authorities, see Holdsworth, op. cit., V, 474 ff; also

Plucknett, "Bonham's Case," Harv. Law Rev., XL, 58, for citation of cases

recognizing the supremacy of Parliament.


31. For an analysis of Coke's ideas relating to a fundamental law, see R. A.

MacKay, "Coke -- Parliamentary Sovereignty or the Supremacy of the Law,"

Michigan Law Review, XXII (January, 1924), 215.


"In every government there must be Somewhat Fundamental, Somewhat like a

Magna Carta, which should be standing, be unalterable.... That Parliament

should not make themselves perpetual is a Fundamental. Of what assurance is

a law to prevent so great an evil, if it lie in the same legislature to

un-law it again? Is such a Law like to be lasting? It will be a rope of

sand." Cromwell's Speech of September 12, 1654.


32. W. S. McKechnie, "Magna Carta (1215-1915)" in Malden, Magna Carta

Commemoration Essays (London, 1917), p. 12. McKechnie thinks that the

inaccurate eulogies of Coke and Hampden rendered a great service to the

cause of constitutional government. Ibid., p. 19.


33. Plucknett, Statutes and their Interpretation in the Fourteenth Century,

Part II.


34. Cf. The American Doctrine of Judicial Supremacy, chap. 2 and Plucknett,

"Bonham's Case and Judicial Review," Harv. Law Rev., XL, 61 ff.


35. I, 41-43. See also, Hooker, The Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity, Book III,

chap. 9.


36. "The History of the Law of Nature," Journal of Society of Comparative

Legislation, II (1900), 418, and Columbia Law Review, I (Jan., 1901), 11.

Cf. also Pollock, The Expansion of the Common Law (London, 1904), pp.

107-138. "The term 'law of nature,' or natural law, has been in use in

various applications ever since the time of the later Roman Republic. Their

variety and apparent diversity have tended to obscure the central idea which

underlies them all, that of an ultimate principle of fitness with regard to

the nature of man as a rational and social being, which is, or ought to be

the justification of every form of positive law. Such a principle, under the

name of reason, reasonableness, or sometimes natural justice, is fully

recognized in our own system, but the difference in terminology has tended

to conceal the similarity from English lawyers during the last century or

more." Pollock, "The History of the Law of Nature," Col. Law Rev., p. 11.


37. Christopher St. Germain, Doctor and Student, Dial., 1. chap. 5. St.

Germain aimed to popularize the canonist conception of equity and to define

its relations to the common law, and he exercised a great influence on the

development of modern English equity. Holdsworth, op. cit., V, 266 ff.


38. "The Common Law is pictured invested with a halo of dignity, peculiar to

the embodiment of the deepest principles and to the highest expression of

human reason and of the law of nature implanted by God in the heart of man,"

Figgis, The Divine Right of Kings, pp. 228, 229. "Common Law is the perfect

ideal law; for it is natural reason developed and expounded by the

collective wisdom of many generations." Ibid., p. 220.


39. The Expansion of the Common Law, p. 108, also Pollock, Essays in the

Law, pp. 63, 68, 69.


40. The Expansion of the Common Law, pp. 108-113. Pollock speaks of this law

of nature or law of reason as a "pervading ideal, of which it would be

hardly too much to say that it is the life of the modern Common Law," ibid.,

p. 109.


41. Pollock, Essays in the Law, p. 70 See Local Government Board v. Arlidge

(1913) 1 K. B. 463; (1914) 1 K. B. 160; (1915) A. C. 120. In the Arlidge

Case administrative proceedings which did not accord the injured party a

hearing or an opportunity to see the record on which the decision of the

officers had been rendered were held valid. The first trial in the Court of

King's Bench resulted in the approval of the administrative action. The

failure to grant a hearing or to permit an examination of the records, the

Court of Appeal held to be contrary to the principles of natural justice on

which the English common law is based. See especially, opinion of J. Vaughn

Williams, Rex v. Local Government Board (1914) 1 K. B. 160, 176. By the

House of Lords this decision was reversed on the ground that the acts of

Parliament expressly authorized such administrative proceedings and did not

provide in these instances for review by the courts. Lord Shaw disapproved

of the ground on which the Court of Appeal based its judgment. He observed:

"In so far as the term 'natural justice' means that a result or process

should be just, it is harmless though it may be a high-sounding expression;

in so far as it attempts to reflect the old jus naturale it is a confused

and unwarranted transfer into the ethical sphere of a term employed for

other distinctions; and, in so far as it is resorted to for other purposes,

it is vacuous." Local Government Board v. Arlidge (1915) A. C. 120, 138.

Lord Moulton also objected to the use of the phrase "contrary to natural

justice" in this connection, ibid., 150. Cf. also Sir Paul Vinogradoff, Yale

Law Journal, XXXIV, 68, and decisions and remarks in the cases of Scott v.

Scott (1913) C. 417, 176 (an action for the nullity of a marriage in which

proceedings were conducted in camera) and of Chester v. Bateson (1920) 1 K.

B. 829 (interference with rights of citizens through ministerial orders

under the Defence of the Realm Act).


42. Cf. Pollock, The Expansion of the Common Law, pp, 123 ff. A few

applications of law of nature concepts may be cited: Certain decisions

relating to the validity of the procedure of foreign courts when judgments

had been rendered without notice or through fraud made use of the phrase

"contrary to natural justice." For example, Lord Ellenborough said: "It is

contrary to the first principles of reason and justice that either in civil

or criminal proceedings, a man should be condemned before he is heard."

Buchanan v. Rucker (1807) 1 Camp. 63, 66. For a criticism of this language

of Ellenborough as no more than declamation, see J. Blackburn in Schibsby v.

Westenholz (1870) L. R. 6 Q. B. 155, 160.


Bramwell B. "It this were the case of a judgment obtained by reason of

untrue statements contained in an affidavit in a foreign court where the

procedure is contrary to natural justice, then we might refuse to give

effect to that judgment.... If the proceedings be in accordance with the

practice of the foreign court, but that practice is not in accordance with

natural justice, this court will not allow itself to be concluded by them."

In Crawley v. Isaacs (1867) 16 L. T R. 529, 531.


Mellish, L. J. "It was always held that a foreign judgment could be

impeached at law as contrary to the principles of natural justice, as, for

instance, on the ground of the defendant having had no notice of the foreign

action, or not having been summoned or of want of jurisdiction, or that the

judgment was fraudulently obtained." In Ochsenbein v. Papelier (1873) L. R.

8 Ch. 695, 700.


"Our common-law system consists in applying to new combinations of

circumstances those rules of law which we derive from legal principles and

judicial precedents; and for the sake of attaining uniformity, consistency

and certainty, we must apply those rules, where they are not plainly

unreasonable and inconvenient, to all cases which arise." Justice James

Parke in Mirehouse v. Rennell (1833) 1 Cl. & F. 527, 546.


A modern illustration of the application of the old doctrine of natural

rights is made by Justice Farwell when in giving judgment on certain rights

involved in underground water courses he remarks: "The foundation of the

right as stated throughout all the cases is jus naturae [citations to a

number of cases follow] ... I have come to the conclusion, therefore, that

jus naturae is used in these cases as expressing that principle in English

law which is akin to, if not derived from, the jus naturale of Roman law.

English law is, of course, quite independent of Roman law, but the

conception of aequum et bonum and the rights flowing therefrom which are

included in the jus naturale underlie a great part of English common law;

although it is not usual to find 'the law of nature' or 'natural law'

referred to in so many words in English cases." Bradford Corporation v.

Ferrand (1902) 2 Ch. 655, 661, 662. Cf. Lord Mansfield's reference to

obligations of justice and equity in Moses v. Macferlen (1760) 2 Burr. 1005,

1012 and opinions of Baron Martin in Freeman v. Jeffries (1869) L. R. 4 Ex.

189, 199 and Justice Buller in Master v. Miller (1791) 4 T. R. 320, 342.


Justice Parker, referring to the custom that a mortgage on the real estate

of a married woman might be executed by her husband without having been

acknowledged by her, said "It is quite clear that for a custom to be good it

must be reasonable or, at any rate, not unreasonable. The words 'reasonable

or not reasonable' imply an appeal to some criterion higher than the mere

rules or maxims embodied in the common law, for it is no objection to a

custom that it is not in accordance with these rules or maxims.... A custom

to be valid must be such that, in the opinion of a trained lawyer, it is

consistent or, at any rate, not inconsistent, with those general principles

which, quite apart from particular rule or maxims, lie at the root of our

legal system.... 'Custom,' as it is put in Needier v. Bishop of Winchester

(Hob. 220, 225) 'must not deprive the law of nature.' Lawyers of today do

not refer to the law of nature as freely or confidently as lawyers did

centuries ago, but, translated into modern phraseology, I think this means

that a custom ... must be according to the principles of our common law."

Johnson v. Clark (1908) 1 Ch. 303, 311, 312.


43. In British India the law of nature has been used as a device to aid in

the introduction of English legal ideas The judges are instructed in

various Indian provinces to act "according to justice, equity and good

conscience." Pollock, Essays in the Law, p. 70 and Expansion of the Common

Law, pp. 132 ff.


44. W. G Miller, The Law of Nature and Nations in Scotland (Edinburgh,

1896), p. 5.


45. The German Recht is never quite our "right" or quite our "law" says

Maitland in his introduction to Political Theories of the Middle Ages by

Otto Gierke, p. lxiii. Closely related to the German Recht is what is

called by Ihering the Sittlichkeit, "the system of habitual or customary

conduct, ethical rather than legal, which embraces all those obligations of

the citizen which it is 'bad form' or 'not the thing' to disregard." See

Lord Haldane, "Higher Nationality: A Study in Law and Ethics," American Bar

Association Reports, XXXVIII (1913), 393. Though there is no word in English

which exactly expresses the meaning of Sittlichkeit, it is sometimes

translated as "social ethics."


46. "There is nothing in the Greek language exactly corresponding to the

Latin jus. The Roman term cannot be translated by nomoV, which is mainly

used for statutory law -- lex. Nor is to dikaion an equivalent, for it

signifies "the just." ... These phraseological peculiarities point to the

highly important fact that the Greeks regarded law primarily as the

embodiment of justice." Vinogradoff, Jurisprudence of the Greek City, p. 19.


47. Laurent, Principes du droit civil français, vol. I, sec. 2, also

Baudry-Lacantinerie, Precis de droit civil, vol. I, sec. 1.


48. "Recht is 'right and law' -- the law looked at not merely as courts

enforce it, but also with reference to what the courts are seeking to

attain through the judicial administration of justice." Pound, Law and

Morals, pp. 84, 8s.


49. It may be observed that the German terms Recht and Naturrecht include

only a portion of good conduct, the remainder being covered by Tugend,

Sittlichkeit, and Moralität. In France, droit and droit naturel are opposed

to moralité.


Sir Frederick Pollock speaks of the Continental schools of jurisprudence as

either ethical or historical. "By the ethical school I mean ... those

authors who throw their main strength on investigating the universal moral

and social conditions of government and laws, and expounding what such

government and laws are or ought to be, so far as determined by conformity

to those conditions. This is the nearest account I can give in few words of

what is implied in modern usage by the terms law of nature, droit naturel or

Naturrecht." An Introduction to the History of the Science of Politics, p.

110.


50. "The Law of Nature," Law Quar. Rev., XI (April, 1926), 121.


51. "English lawyers are not, and never have been ready," says Professor

Holdsworth, "to receive and use as the basis of their reasoning the theories

of legal and political philosophers." Some Lessons from our Legal History

(New York, 1928), p. 109.


52. Generalizations, often assumed and followed without any definite

formulation, are likely to form the major premises of judicial reasoning.

For some interesting examples of this type, cf. H. Rottschaefer, "Legal

Theory and the Practice of the Law," Minnesota Law Review, X (April, 1926),

382. Mr. Rottschaefer notes that not only are such generalizations subsumed

in much judicial thinking but similar generalizations serve as a background

for those who criticize legal rules.



                  CHAPTER III


    AMERICAN AND FRENCH NATURAL LAW DOCTRINES


BY THE time political theories and customs were taking definite shape in the

American Colonies the characteristic ideas relating to natural law in

England and in Continental Europe had been introduced into the environment

of a pioneer rural civilization. But before the transmission took place a

change in emphasis was under way which was accentuated under the peculiar

conditions prevailing in America.


1. Transition from Natural Law Doctrines to Theories of Natural Rights. When

the standard works of Gentilis, Grotius, Pufendorf, and Burlamaqui aimed to

present the basic principles of the public and private law of Europe natural

law doctrines were generally approved. As the importance of the canon law

declined the doctrines were limited in their applications and, in certain

countries, except for their use as critical standards to oppose the

arbitrary and dictatorial policies of princes and kings, they were sparingly

used in the practical operation of the law. But all branches of the law were

subjected to natural law influences.


The original concepts of natural law, however, were to undergo a marked

transformation, when the Reformation leaders, following Roman and mediaeval

authorities, gave great significance in political and religious matters to

the rights and liberties of the individual. Instead of natural law or rules

of superior validity jus naturale was translated into a theory of natural

rights -- qualities inherent in man which it was the duty of the state to

protect. Grotius was one of the foremost mediaeval thinkers to find a source

of natural rights in certain inherent qualities belonging to the individual.

These rights, which were sanctioned by natural law, might be discovered by

human reason.[1] Montesquieu and the Physiocrats in France and English

philosophers also formulated theories of natural rights as inherent in the

individual, with certain formulas derived therefrom designed to limit all

public authorities.[2] Moreover, the distinction suggested several centuries

earlier that rulers were bound not only by the primary laws of nature but

also by certain fundamental secondary natural laws which were expressed in

positive laws, was formally enunciated.[3]


One of the popular writers of the eighteenth century, who based his

political philosophy on rights inherent in the individual, was Vattel,

whose volume on The Law of Nations appeared in many editions, French,

English, and German.[4] As a representative authority Vattel's views, as

well as those of Grotius, Pufendorf, and Burlamaqui, were extensively

studied and followed during the formative period of American law. Vattel,

who was a follower of Frederic von Wolff, began to translate Wolff's work,

Jus Naturae Methodo Scientifica Pertractatum, and to render it available to

the public and the result was that he put the doctrines of Wolff into such

form that a relatively new and popular treatise was prepared.


To Vattel, it was regarded as settled on the basis of natural law "that

liberty and independence belong to man by his very nature, and that they

cannot be taken from him without his consent." Moreover, "the whole Nation,

whose common will is but the outcome of the united wills of the citizens,

remains subject to the laws of nature, and is bound to respect them in all

its undertakings.... We must therefore," he continued, "apply to nations the

rules of the natural law to discover what are their obligations and their

rights; hence, the law of Nations is in its origin merely the law of Nature

applied to Nations."


Vattel regarded this law immutable as being founded "on the nature of

things," and particularly "on the nature of man" and hence he thought,

"nations can not alter it by agreement, nor individually or mutually

release themselves from it."[5] Vattel aided in the movement to establish

written constitutions, as the foundation of public authority. He maintained

that the fundamental laws enacted by the nation itself are not subject to

change by the legislature. The distinction between fundamental and ordinary

law was clearly drawn,[6] and American legal authorities soon began to make

practical applications of the distinction.


With the writings of Grotius, Pufendorf, Wolff, and Vattel attention was

directed to a state of nature -- a golden age which existed at the beginning

of society in which the laws of nature, as affecting the relations of

individuals and of communities, predominated.[7] These laws of nature were

of the immutable type, and it was not long before jurists and politicians

began to think of man as emerging from this state of nature with a panoply

of rights belonging to him as an individual. Political and economic

conditions in Europe and in America were taking the shape which gave vital

and legal force to the emerging concept of the natural inherent and

inalienable rights of man.[8]


2. American Theories of Natural Law and of Inalienable Rights. In the

process of transplanting fundamental law notions to the American Colonies,

conditions were favorable not only to the reception of higher law theories

but also to their incorporation as basic doctrines of public and private

law. The colonists brought with them many of the current ideas of the common

law as the foundation of their legal arrangements. But the law was as a rule

applied by those untrained in the technical procedure and rules of the

English system. Statutes applicable to local conditions were frequently

lacking. Courts and judges found themselves called upon to make law for the

occasion with little else to guide them except the Bible, the precepts of

natural law or natural justice, and the community sentiment of what ought to

be right and just. Under such circumstances appeals were frequently made to

natural law or to allied concepts.


The pioneer rural conditions in which most of the colonists lived encouraged

self-reliance not only in their economic and social conditions but also in

their political ideas. Dependent for the most part upon their own efforts

for a livelihood, they also had to assume a large share of responsibility in

protecting individual and community rights. With the organized evidences of

government far removed from the ordinary activities of life it was customary

to place a high value on the assertion and protection of individual personal

rights. Moreover, the normal methods of making and enforcing law tended to

give special value to doctrines of natural law. Under the primitive

conditions which prevailed, natural rights and natural law were regarded

either as identical or as merely two phases of the same concept. Having

theoretically, at least, adopted the rules and principles of the common law

the prevailing English views as to the supremacy of the law were accepted.

And the higher law doctrine as later announced by Blackstone gave sanction

to the belief that certain laws were superior to all civil enactments.[9]

The judges in the Colonies frequently indicated their belief in the natural

laws, which were considered true laws, and legislation was thought to be

binding only in so far as it was an expression of these laws.[10]


The process of the transmission of natural law theories to the new

environment was hastened by the appeal to higher law ideas by the leaders of

the revolt against Great Britain and by the philosophic trend of the

eighteenth century to place uppermost in the political sphere the natural

rights of the individual.[11]


The popularity of the concepts of natural rights and of natural law was

greatly increased when they were espoused by the leaders of the American and

French Revolutions. The American Revolution not only came first but also

resulted in a more specific formulation of natural rights as inherent in the

individual. James Otis, Samuel Adams, John Adams,[12] Thomas Paine, Patrick

Henry, and Thomas Jefferson[13] made frequent use of the natural rights

doctrine to support the right of rebellion against the arbitrary exercise of

governmental powers. The Declaration of Independence gave a standard formula

for the use of advocates of the doctrine in the dictum that men are "endowed

by their Creator with certain unalienable rights, that among these are Life,

Liberty, and the pursuit of Happiness." Many of the Revolutionary patriots

believed with Thomas Dickinson that liberties do not result from charters;

charters rather are in the nature of declarations of pre-existing rights.

They are founded, John Adams claimed, "in the frame of human nature, rooted

in the constitution of the intellectual and moral world."[14] Until the

adoption of the Declaration of Independence it was customary to regard these

rights as having their sanction in the British Constitution.[15] "The law

of nature and the law of revelation are both divine; they flow, though in

different channels from the same adorable source," said James Wilson. In the

course of his law Lectures he frequently extolled the instinctive or

intuitive faculties whereby man arrived at principles of right and

justice.[16]


The doctrine of the freedom and equality of men in their natural state, such

as that described by Seneca and formulated into a dogma of mediaeval

thought, was translated into a principle of political action. Governments,

to justify their existence, were to be measured by the security they

furnished for the natural principles of freedom and of equality.


Concepts of law in North America in the eighteenth and in the early

nineteenth centuries were molded and, in considerable part, determined under

the influence of the prevailing doctrine of inalienable rights and this idea

gave a peculiar turn to all legal thinking. The law of the Colonies, the

public papers and charters of the Revolutionary period, and the first

written constitutions with specific enumeration of certain natural and

inalienable rights, bear witness to the conviction that such rights were

thought to exist, and that governments were designed primarily to preserve

them.[17] Legislative enactments contrary to natural law or natural justice

were regarded as ipso facto void and it was declared to be the duty of all

persons to resist their enforcement. The view of the English philosopher

that "that which is not just is not law and that which is not law ought not

to be obeyed,"[18] was not infrequently taken as the starting point in the

application of legal rules. Moreover, the belief in natural law and in

inalienable rights aided materially in giving support to the courts when

they were asserting the right to declare void enactments which interfered

with these natural rights or contravened the express terms of written

constitutions.[19]


The natural law philosophy, as a background for legal thinking, which was a

part of the heritage of Western Europe and of America in the eighteenth

century, was extensively used in America, where it was transformed into

laissez faire individualistic dogmas under frontier methods of administering

justice. It was also identified with the immemorial rights of Englishmen as

declared by Coke and Blackstone. Into the philosophical mold of Grotius,

Pufendorf, Burlamaqui, and Vattel was injected some of the characteristic

ideas of Coke's Second Institute and of Blackstone's Commentaries and there

was created a unique form of natural law, supposed to be universal in its

applications.[20]


American political and legal theorists made use of every phase of natural

law thinking. Judges with little legal training and with a scarcity of law

books, when precepts from the Bible were not applicable, turned to natural

law as a convenient symbol for the divine sanction of laws, after the

fashion of the mediaeval canonists. To Paine and Jefferson, as with certain

Greek thinkers, there was a disposition to recur to the deistic emphasis

upon the laws of nature and to associate the concept with underlying

principles of natural phenomena. Others identified the rights of nature with

the rights of Englishmen. Though not so well known, Coke's appeal to natural

law and to the higher reason of the common law was called upon by legal

advocates when attacking obnoxious acts of the colonial legislatures, just

as higher laws were appealed to in resisting the arbitrary acts of the King

or of Parliament. The appeal to natural rights and natural law as a

justification for the right of revolution was one of the chief features of

the formative period of American institutions.


Natural law was also conceived as an ideal to which all just laws must

conform,[21] as from the viewpoint of certain Greek and Roman jurists, and,

in this sense, it was a convenient doctrine to temper the arbitrary features

of a system of strict legal rules. It thus became an instrument of legal

growth. Conceptions of a state of nature wherein men enjoyed natural freedom

and equality conditioned the thinking of most of the Revolutionary leaders

and through them a principle was announced which has proved to be one of the

most insistent and fertile concepts of American legal thought, namely, that

each individual is entitled to the equal protection of the laws.


Assuming a state of nature antedating organized political life wherein man

was possessed of inherent and inalienable rights arising from the laws of

nature, and basing government on a social compact resulting from this

condition, there was formulated in the representative American constitution

a group of rights belonging to the individual and of such superior sanctity

that political society was formed primarily to preserve them. Out of a state

of nature and emanating from the laws of nature arose the familiar

inalienable rights which were superior to the state itself and, in fact,

above all forms of political or social control. The theory of natural

rights, which is the characteristic American interpretation of natural law,

became the foundation for the concept of limited government which gained

such a strong foothold in the United States. It gave the theoretical basis

for the American doctrine of civil liberty which set the rights of the

individual against the government and insisted on the formulation of limits

on all forms of political authority.[22]


Thus the democratic ideas of the monarchomachs and of the representative

theorists of England and of Continental Europe were made more concrete and

more directly applicable to human affairs. It seems strange that this

revival of the general acceptance of ideas of natural law and natural rights

should have preceded by only a few decades a marked decline of the belief in

natural laws of superior sanctity. Before considering the causes for this

decline, it is necessary to trace briefly a similar revival of ancient

superior law notions in France.


3. French Natural Law Concepts. The French system of law, arising as a

direct development from the Roman law, was molded in its transmission

through mediaeval channels in the light of the Roman and mediaeval concepts

of natural law. Each variety of the concept characteristic of these periods

had advocates in France. The divine sources and sanctions of natural law

were particularly emphasized by French jurists of the Catholic faith. When

human reason was given an important rôle in discovering natural law, it was

in France that this rationalized natural law found many interpreters. The

French attitude was well stated by Guizot, who said: "Any action, or any

authority of man over man is legitimate only if it is in accord with reason,

justice and truth, which are based on the law of God."[23] It was not until

the modern period that mediaeval canon law, with its natural law principles,

and local customs, often arising from similar sources, were replaced by laws

emanating from a king or assembly. Fostering ideas of permanence and

uniformity amidst the variations in the customary law and in the diversities

of the provincial practices the natural law theories were looked upon as a

factor of unity; and those favoring a united France became devoted exponents

of the law of nature philosophy.[24]


When the French kings in their conflict with the Papacy fell back on the

practices of the Roman imperialists, they asserted principles of political

supremacy which were destined to weaken the controlling force of natural

law. Bodin, as we have seen, became the philosopher of royal absolutism and

he relegated natural law to principles which were merely a guide to the

king's conscience. To those bent upon establishing an unlimited political

sovereign, superior natural laws were an obstacle to be obliterated. But

higher law ideas were too well established in the legal background of French

thought to be entirely discarded. Moreover, the efforts to make of the king

a ruler without limits on his authority soon brought an inevitable reaction

in which natural law ideas again came to the forefront. The economic and

political conditions of the Ancien Regime prepared the way for the French

Declaration of the Rights of Man.


Prior to the French Revolution the Physiocrats advocated the doctrine of

natural rights. There is, in effect, observed Quesnay, above positive laws,

a body of laws, sovereign, immutable, and inviolable. Legal rules which

conform to this body of laws are valid; those which are contrary thereto are

void.[25] The natural rights of the individual, they contended, comprised

three species of property. "First, the property of his person which includes

the right to use all his faculties, and hence the right to labor; Second,

movable property which consists of the results of his labor; Third, landed

property."[26] To the Physiocrats laws were rules of justice and morality;

they were not made by men but were merely discovered. They believed that

certain laws, especially those relating to liberty and property, were

essential to the social order and that only ordinances to carry out such

laws could be made by legislatures or executives.[27] The essence of the

Physiocratic doctrine was laissez faire in character, or to the effect that

"economic law might be depended upon to bring about the best good of men and

nations, if governments kept their hands off."[28] They insisted that

governmental action ought to be restricted within the narrowest limits and

individual activity ought to have every possible opportunity for expression

-- a doctrine which has left its impress on many of the aspects of American

legal thinking. But in certain respects the ideas of the Physiocrats, as

those of their predecessors, tended to favor state absolutism.


The French kings of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries sought to

assert complete control over the social and political life of the nation.

Bossuet, the defender of this regime, followed Bodin and Hobbes and based

the origin of all governments on force.[29] Emerging doctrines of

nationalism gave encouragement to the assertion of principles of state

absolutism. The doctrine of individual rights as a basis to check the

public powers had not yet impregnated French legal thought. Mediaeval

doctrines of a superior natural law, however, served to give a sanction to

the assertion of a theory of individual natural rights. Extreme instances

of the use of arbitrary authority by the kings were paving the way for

resistance sanctioned again by appeals to higher laws. Political theories

often take their peculiar forms because of attempts on the part of those

interested to defend a cause. And in this case Protestants and Catholics

following theories earlier formulated in Europe advocated limits on royal

authority in the interest of the people.


Though the old French parlements performed in the main judicial functions as

courts of the king over which he presided and whose judgments he might

reverse, the natural division of powers which resulted led to the assumption

of a share of the political powers by these bodies.[30] To them was accorded

the duty of registering the royal edicts and in doing so they began to

question the validity of the acts of the king or of his agents. As early as

1648 the parlements had proclaimed the necessity of "a legal order" and as a

basis for such an order proposed certain fundamental laws or fundamental

principles which were so essential that the king could not change them.[31]

"Thus there appeared in an absolute monarchy, by the simple fact of the

separation of powers, an organ of resistance and of control. The parlement,

recruited from the higher middle class, claimed to be the guardian of the

fundamental laws of the kingdom and considered itself as a moderating power

designed to curb the excesses of royal absolutism."[32] A convenient

vagueness in the term "fundamental laws" encouraged the members of the

parlements to intervene on behalf of the people whenever a favorable

opportunity occurred.[33] If need be the king could in the end secure his

way by arresting and banishing the leaders of the parlements, but these

bodies regarded themselves as mediators between the king and the people and

served to keep before the public a belief in fundamental laws which the king

could not change.[34]


Some of the cahiers issued preceding the French Revolution in resisting

certain decrees frankly based their protests on the doctrine of fundamental

and superior laws.[35] These mild protests accomplished little toward

checking the tendencies in the direction of royal absolutism. But they

strengthened the insistence on higher law ideas which were soon to find

expression in the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen.


Just as the leaders of the American Revolution appealed to the doctrine of

natural and inalienable rights, so those who directed the French Revolution

recognized as a fundamental truth the existence of similar rights.[36] A

controversy has ensued among scholars as to whether the draftsmen of the

French declaration were guided by the doctrines of Montesquieu and of

Rousseau as well as of their predecessors or by the previous American

declarations.[37] Whatever may be the merits of the claims of the partisans

on each side it was the French Declaration which heralded to the world the

great principles of natural and inalienable rights which were considered

superior to all governments and which it was the prime duty of all

democratic states to protect.[38] The doctrine of natural rights again based

on the natural and necessary laws of a state of nature was made the very

cornerstone of a political system. Differing from the major portions of the

bills of rights of the American constitutions, which were comprised mainly

of some of the hard-won privileges which Englishmen had acquired in

centuries of conflict with their rulers, the French provisions were rather

in the nature of vague theories or platitudes which had little practical

meaning to the Frenchmen of the time. Similar theories were, of course,

included in the Declaration of Independence and in certain provisions of the

state constitutions.


Though the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the political and social

philosophy involved therein left a permanent impression upon European

thought, the conservative reaction which followed the French Revolution

brought into disrepute natural and inalienable rights concepts which were

regarded akin to ideas of violence and terrorism. It became unpopular in

certain quarters to support the law of nature doctrines or to appeal to

higher laws than those promulgated by the rulers. But Roman law principles

and various ideas connected therewith were conducive to the continuance of

natural law doctrines. And during the nineteenth century many treatises

appeared, the object of which was to adapt natural law phrases prevalent in

codes and in the customary legal terminology to the peculiar conditions of

the time. Various schools of legal philosophy continued to be protagonists

of natural law theories when in political circles these theories were

regarded as exploded vagaries. To the efforts to keep alive natural law

doctrines attention will be directed later. But these efforts for the time

being seemed to be obscured by the persistent influences designed to

discredit natural law theories.


4. The Decline of the Natural Rights Philosophy. As the enthusiasm waned

which fostered eighteenth-century political radicalism in America and in

France and the radical movement came into disrepute in all countries it

became popular to discredit the natural rights thinking. To the conservative

leaders who took charge of the political destinies of the European nations

after the French Revolution the inalienable rights doctrine was "an

invitation to insurrection and a persistent cause of anarchy."[39] And when

the reaction from the practices and the political philosophy of the American

and the French Revolutions gained ascendency in the United States one of the

chief objectives was to discredit Thomas Jefferson and the tenets of the

Declaration of Independence.[40] Both in politics and in religion,

conservatism was in control, and men were disposed to welcome theories which

made for social stability.[41] It is well to note that it was the

politicians who were seeking greater political authority and those who were

inclined to support absolutism in government who were chiefly concerned in

the repudiation of natural rights and related natural law theories. Local

justices in the application of the law to concrete cases and the people

generally clung to natural law concepts long after they were thought to be

repudiated in high political circles.


The anti-natural rights doctrine, according to Mr. Becker, became the

accepted creed of all those who wished to be classed neither with the

reactionaries nor the revolutionists, those liberal-conservatives and

conservative-liberals who realized that they lived in a changing world but

ardently prayed that it might not change too rapidly.


To prevent the world from changing too rapidly, nothing is more effective

than to look with admiration on the past.[42]


A combination of factors tended to discredit the natural rights doctrine.

Politically the doctrine was used to justify not alone political democracy

but also the free right of the people to change their governments -- namely,

as a sanction for the right of revolution.[43] When the right to revolt led

to the Reign of Terror and its aftermath the political reaction that

followed in Europe placed the stamp of disgrace on the much-heralded

doctrines of the revolutionary period.[44] Michel finds that the reaction

against the individualistic doctrines of the French Revolution was fairly

complete by 1825. French political thought with the exception of small

groups had turned away from the belief in natural rights, anterior and

superior to the state. Rights were the result of laws and laws came from a

state or political power with supreme authority. Public powers were limited

only by the personal God of De Bonald or the Absolute of Hegel, but the

sovereign alone was to be judge of the nature of these limits.[45] The

attack on eighteenth-century individualism was encouraged and strengthened

also by the economic doctrines advocated by Saint Simon and his followers.

There is no place in his system for the idea of rights but instead of rights

he directs attention to interests.


In America the conservative reaction which followed the periods of the

Revolution and of the Confederation did not so quickly discredit the natural

rights philosophy of the Declaration of Independence, but the defenders of

this philosophy grew fewer in number while the critics and opponents

increased.[46] Some authors, Dr. Wright observes,


    like Chipman, Hurlbut, Lieber, and Gerrit Smith, retain
    almost unchanged the traditional American theory that the
    basis of all laws and of all rights is to be found in the
    immutable truths taught by nature and to be learned by men
    through the use of reason, conscience, and the revealed
    work of God. Others, like Calhoun, Brownson, Fitzhugh,
    and Hildreth, discard the idea that there are certain
    inalienable rights derived from nature, although in every case
    holding that there are basic laws or principles which underlie
    all government and all of the social and economic
    relationships of men.[47]


He finds only one writer, Thomas Cooper, who attempts to refute the whole

natural law theory.[48]


In England the natural rights theories were attacked also quite vigorously

by the Social-Utilitarians who repudiated the foremost eighteenth-century

political theories and made social utility the test of political

institutions. Bentham, one of the leaders of this school, lent the weight of

his influence against the natural law doctrines. For the idea that men had

rights by nature which the sovereign was compelled to respect Bentham felt

great contempt, nor did he have any confidence in the effort to place

limitations on the supreme authority in a state.[49] "To maintain," says

Bentham, "that there is a natural right and to impose it as a limit to

positive laws, to say that law cannot go against natural right, to

recognize, in consequence, the right which attacks law, which overturns and

annuls it, is at once to render all government impossible and to defy

reason."[50] He and his associates could see no limits to the sovereign

power except restraints through the judgment of those in whom this power was

reposed.


The historic method which grew in favor in history and in politics admitted

that rights were founded in nature but identified nature with history and

affirmed that the institutions of any nation were properly but an expression

of the life of the people. By a change in the definition of nature the

former concepts were made the basis for anti-revolutionary philosophies.


Historians such as Ranke[51] and Renan,[52] the philosopher, Hegel,[53] and

the sociologist Auguste Comte[54] also joined the ranks of those who sought

effectively to dispose of the ideas of natural rights superior to man-made

regulations. And the historical school of jurists led by Savigny repudiated

the eighteenth-century doctrines of natural rights and of a law of nature.

To this school law existed independently of the state. It was the creation

of the national consciousness or the spirit of the people and was evidenced

by their customary habits. It was merely the function of the state to

discover and enforce these customary laws.[55] Rights do not belong to man,

as such, Savigny maintained, they are the result of positive laws. And

positive laws, like language, morals, social and religious institutions,

develop through the customs, habits, and traditions of a people. And with

the aid of the historical jurists the older concepts of the law of nature

and of natural rights were to give way to legal ideas as an outgrowth of

history. Law was conceived as the unfolding of ideas of right through the

customs and traditions to which people give obedience.[56] The philosophic

forces at work in this development are suggestively characterized by Justice

Cardozo, who observes that


    the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries put their faith in
    Nature, and "their dominant philosophy was that of natural
    law." Preordained and immutable were the patterns to which
    conformity was due. The nineteenth century put its faith in
    unconscious and undirected growth; and Nature dethroned
    as an exemplar, was made to yield place to History. "None
    of the nineteenth-century interpretations will hear of an
    element of creative activity of men as lawyers, judges,
    writers of books, legislators. They have nothing to say about
    juristic endeavors to reconcile or harmonize or compromise
    overlapping claims by creative reason or an inventive
    process of trial and error. They think of the phenomena of
    legal development as events, as if men were not acting in the
    bringing about of every one of them." In the thought of this
    school, law is in the grip of forces stronger than itself, which
    shape the path of its advance.[57]


Thus the historical school of jurisprudence set about to destroy all

vestiges of the ideas of natural law or natural rights.[58]


The natural rights philosophy received its most direct blow from the jurist

John Austin and his successors who founded the analytical school of

jurisprudence, and the advocates of the German theory that the state is the

sole source and sanction of law, such as Ihering, Laband, and Jellinek. The

Austinians conceived as the essence of the state a sovereign -- a supreme,

irresistible, absolute, and uncontrolled authority. The rules made or

sanctioned by this authority were laws -- all other rules were merely

customs, habits, or moral practices. Questions relative to justice and to

the aims of the law were consigned to the domain of positive morality.[59]

Thus much of public law was denied the status of law, and the familiar

dogmas of natural law and of inalienable rights were utterly repudiated. To

the followers of Austin the attack upon natural rights, so far as such

rights are accorded legal significance, is one which must be continued

until no trace of the concept is left. Similar views were advocated by the

supporters of the Macht Politik in Germany.[60]


Many factors and influences combined, therefore, to discredit political

theorizing based on the doctrine of natural rights until it was referred to

as "an exploded theory no longer believed in by any one of note."[61]


Natural law was absorbed as a feature of American public and private law at

a time when the theories on which such a law was based were declining in

Europe. The decadence of natural law concepts which affected the political

circles mainly and which was characteristic of the decades in the middle of

the nineteenth century in most European countries had its counterpart in the

United States in somewhat narrowing the scope of the law of nature thinking

and in giving the term a rigidity which tended to support the existing legal

order. It was under these conditions that the courts fostered the gradual

acceptance of some principles of natural law in the public law of the United

States.




1. See De Jure Belli ac Pacis, Book I, chap. 1.


2. Recognizing that the formulation and classification of the inborn and

indestructible rights of the individual belonged to a later stage in the

growth of the theory of natural law, Gierke observed that mediaeval thought

was filled with such ideas. Political Theories of the Middle Ages, p. 81;

cf. also, Gierke, Johannes Althusius, pp. 107 ff. It is obvious that to

attribute the origin of the theory of natural rights to the Protestant

revolt is incorrect. Cf. David G. Ritchie, Natural Rights: A criticism of

some political and ethical conceptions (3d ed., London, 1916), p. 6.


3. Gierke, Johannes Althusius, p. 175. For the effort to distinguish between

immutable laws which do or do not admit of exceptions, see Domat, The Civil

Law in its Natural Order, trans. by Wm. Strahan (2d ed., London, 1737), I,

64.


4. M. de Vattel, Le droit des gens ou principes de la loi naturelle

appliques a la conduite et aux affaires des Nations et des Souverains (ed.

of 1758) reproduced in the Classics of International Law, edited by James

Brown Scott and published by the Carnegie Institution of Washington (1916).


5. Vattel, The Law of Nations, III, 3, 4. Professor Reeves thinks that the

"impress of the law of nature upon the American ideas of the law of nations

seems upon the whole not to be great." His view is apparently influenced by

the tendency of American lawyers to depreciate natural law ideas. J. S.

Reeves, "The Influence of the Law of Nature upon International Law in the

United States," American Journal of International Law, III (1909), 547.


6. The Law of Nations, III, chap. 3.


7. Cf. Introduction by Albert de Lapradelle, in Vattel, op. cit.. III,

viii. John Milton claimed, in the Gangreana, that "all men are by nature the

sons of Adam, and from him have legitimately derived natural propriety

[property], right and freedom. By natural birth all men are equally and

alike born to like propriety, liberty and freedom."


8. One reason why Englishmen have given less consideration to natural

rights, it is claimed, is that they have regarded their liberties as due to

acquired rights rather than to natural rights. To them the concept

"natural" became identical with the term "traditional." Jones, Cambridge

Legal Essays (Cambridge, 1926), p. 228.


9. According to the classical natural law theory prevalent in colonial

times all positive law was "a reflection of an ideal body of perfect rules

demonstrable by reason, and valid for all times, all places and all men.

Positive legal precepts got their validity from their conformity to these

ideals" Pound, "The Theory of Judicial Decision," Harvard Law Review, XXXVI

(May, 1923), 802.


10. P. S. Reinsch, "Colonial Common Law," Select Essays in Anglo-American

Legal History, I, 376, 413; Professor Reinsch observes that "the analytical

theory of Hobbes, making positive law independent of moral considerations

and basing it on a sovereign will, was not accepted at that time. The law of

God, the law of nature, was looked upon as the true law." For citations of

representative colonial opinions see B F. Wright, Jr , "Natural Law in

American Political Theory," Southwestern Political and Social Science

Quarterly, IV (December, 1923), 202, 206. Cf. for example, John Wise, "A

Vindication of the Government of New England Churches" -- a

pre-revolutionary treatise based on the natural law doctrines of Pufendorf.


11. Professor McIlwain maintains that the colonists based their argument for

freedom from control by Parliament, first on their charters; second, on the

contention "that the English constitution, founded on natural law, was a

free constitution, guaranteeing to all its subjects wherever they might be

the fundamental rights incident to free government"; and third, on a

"non-constitutional appeal to natural law, no longer as a part of the

British constitution, but as the rights of man in general." The American

Revolution. A constitutional interpretation (New York, 1923), p. 152.


12. John Adams thought there were "rights antecedent to all earthly

government -- Rights, that cannot be repealed or restrained by human laws --

Rights, derived from the great Legislator of the Universe." Works, ed. by C.

F. Adams (Boston, 1865), III, 449. See also Otis, The Rights of the British

Colonies Asserted and Proved, pp. 11, 16.; Wells, Life of Samuel Adams

(Boston, 1865), I, 16-23, 70-77; and Thomas Paine, The Rights of Man.


13. For Jefferson's views, see Writings (Ford's ed.), V, 147, 329; VI, 87,

88, 102, 517; VII, 172, 406.


It was asserted that colonial rights were based on "the immutable laws of

nature, the principles of the English Constitution and the several charters

or compacts." Journals of the Continental Congress, ed. by Ford (Washington,

1004), I, 67.


James Otis in his argument against writs of assistance relied on natural

rights and fundamental law. Cf. The Rights of the British Colonies; also C.

H. McIlwain, op. cit., and my article "The Law of Nature in State and

Federal Judicial Decisions," Yale Law Journal, XXV (June, 1916), 617, 623.


Jefferson in the Declaration of Independence in qualifying the inalienable

rights used the English formula "life, liberty and the pursuit of

happiness." The Virginia constitution asserted that: "All men are by nature

equally free and independent, and have certain inherent rights, of which,

when they enter into a state of society, they cannot, by any compact,

deprive or divest their posterity; namely, the enjoyment of life and

liberty, with the means of acquiring and possessing property, and pursuing

and obtaining happiness and safety." Constitution of Virginia, June 12,

1776.


The right to revolt was characterized in the Massachusetts declaration as

"incontestable, unalienable and undefeasible."


14. See B. F. Wright, Jr , "American Interpretations of Natural Law,"

American Political Science Review, XX (Aug. 1926), 524 ff.


15. Samuel Adams, Writings (ed. by H. A. Cushing, 1904), I, 65. "The

primary, absolute, natural rights of Englishmen as frequently declared in

acts of Parliament from Magna Carta to this day, are personal security,

personal liberty, and private property." Wells, Life of Samuel Adams, I,

75-77.


16. Works (ed. by Andrews), 1, 106, 117, 124. Wilson expressed the current

opinion among lawyers and judges during the Revolutionary period when he

wrote: "The law of nature is immutable; not by the effect of an arbitrary

disposition, but because it has its foundation in the nature, constitution,

and mutual relations of men and things."


17. Jefferson believed that the "will of the majority is in all cases to

prevail, but that will to be rightful, must be reasonable; that the

minority possess equal rights, which equal laws must protect, and to violate

would be oppression" Legitimate restraints on the rule of the majority were

inalienable rights and the laws of reason. Works, VIII, 2. When Secretary of

State and President, Jefferson continued to apply doctrines of natural right

and natural law. "The evidence of this natural right [expatriation], like

that of our right to life, liberty, the use of our faculties, the pursuit

of happiness, is not left to the feeble and sophisticated investigations of

reason but is impressed on the sense of every man." The Writings of Thomas

Jefferson (ed. by H. A. Washington), VII, 73. He also defended the right of

navigation on the Mississippi on the broad ground of the law of nature and

of nations.


18. Sydney, Discourses Concerning Government, Book III, chap. 11 See also,

Pound, "Comparative Law in the Formation of American Common Law," Acta

Academiae Universalis Jurisprudentiae Comparativae (1928), I, 183 ff.


19. The American Doctrine of Judicial Supremacy, pp. 18 ff., and D. O.

Wagner, "Some Antecedents of the American Doctrine of Judicial Review,"

Political Science Quarterly, XL (December, 1925), 561 ff.


20. Pound, "The Theory of Judicial Decision," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI, pp.

804, 805. Hamilton identified the common law and natural law. Works (ed by

Lodge), VIII, 421.


In the disputes between the English political leaders and the colonists of

America, Dr. Wright notes that those "who had read the orations of Cicero,

the writings of Grotius and Vattel, Pufendorf and Burlamaqui, Locke and

Blackstone, who had listened to sermons upon the eternal supremacy of the

laws of God or had perused the arguments of the deists found in such

philosophy controversial weapons suited to their needs" See, "American

Interpretations of Natural Law," Amer. Pol. Sci. Rev, XX, 526 And he

observes, "In the writings of all of the most influential theorists of the

time the concept of a superior law of nature, from which are derived the

basic rights of men, holds a very prominent place."


21. Natural rights and natural law, as an ideal form of the actual law were

in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries "guides to lead growth into

definite channels and insure continuity and permanence in the development of

rules and doctrines." Pound, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (New

Haven, 1922), p. 44.


22. "The constitutional doctrine of the seventeenth and eighteenth

centuries, working with the tools of natural law, erected constitutional

limitations into legal obligations founded on unimpairable contract, gave a

vis coactiva to constitutional limitations, enforceable if necessary by the

right of resistance, and posited for every state an implied constitution

founded on the natural law rights of the individual and having as much force

as a written constitution." Edwin M. Borchard," Government Responsibility in

Tort," Yale Law Jour., XXXVI (April, 1927), 794.


23. See, F. P. Guizot, Works, V, 60, 399, 519, and Histoire des origines du

gouvernement représentatif en Europe (Brussels, 1851), II, Lecture X.


24. Voltaire referred to natural laws and natural rights which have a

fundamental and immutable character. Oeuvres Completes, (new ed., Paris,

1883). In speaking of intolerance and natural law he wrote: "Natural law is

that law which nature has indicated to all men." XXV, 39. At another time he

referred to rights as never being established only by necessity, or force,

or custom. XV, 452.


25. Quesnay, Traité du droit naturel, chap. 5, p 376. A dictum to which the

Physiocrats referred was: "Ex natura jus, ordo et leges, ex hominare

bitrium, regimen et coercitio."


26. William A. Dunning, Political Theories from Luther to Montesquieu, p.

59.


27. Cf. Henry Michel, L'ldée de l'état (2d ed , Paris, 1896) 17 ff.


28. Ibid., p 62. For the natural law doctrines of the Physiocrats see

Quesnay, Traité du droit naturel (1765), L'ordre naturel et essential des

sociétés politiques (1767). Physiocrates, Par. I, 41 and Par. II, 445.


29. Henry Michel, op. cit., pp 4 ff.


30. Glasson, Parlement de Paris et son rôle politique.


31. A. Esmein, Cours élémentaire histoire du droit français (11 ed., Paris,

1912), pp. 582 ff., and V. Marcaggi, Les origines de la déclaration des

droits de l'homme de 1789 (2e ed., Paris, 1912), p. 85. Marcaggi observes

that the history of the états généraux (States-General) is replete with

illustrations of the assertion of the rights of man in opposition to the

rights of the state.


32. Jean Brissaud, A History of French Public Law, trans. by James W. Gamer

in Continental Legal History Series (Boston, 1915), p. 447.


33. V. Marcaggi, op. cit. p., 98. The remonstrance of March the 4th, 1776

cited the fundamental rule of natural law which protects the rights of

person and property. Ibid., p. 101.


34. Jean Brissaud, op. cit., pp. 448 ff.; Esmein, op. cit., pp. 595 ff.


35. Marcaggi, op. cit., chap. 8.


36. Article I of the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen,

states that "Men are born and remain free and equal in rights. Social

distinctions may be founded only upon the general will." "The aim of all

political association is the preservation of the natural and indefeasible

rights of man. These rights are liberty, ownership, security, and

resistance to oppression." See also article I of the Declaration of Rights

of 1793. See Robert Redslob, Die Staatstheorien der franzosischen

nationalversammlung von 1789 (Leipzig, 1912).


The extent to which the ideas of the Declaration of Rights are based upon

the political philosophy of Grotius, Pufendorf, Burlamaqui, and Vattel,

concerning the natural equality and freedom of the individual, the right to

own and use property, the liberty of conscience, and the consent of the

people as the source of government, is considered by Marcaggi, op. cit., pp.

109 ff.


37. Sir Paul Vinogradoff regards the French declarations as only "the last

consequences of a movement which is preeminently English and American." Yale

Law Jour., XXXIV, 65. George Jellinek defended the thesis that the impetus

for the French Declaration was given by Rousseau and its prototype was the

American Declaration of Independence. The Declaration of the Rights of Man

and of the Citizens, trans. by Max Farrand (New York, 1901). For reply to

Jellinek, see Boutmy, Annales des sciences politiques, July 15, 1902. See

claim that the Declaration of Rights comes from Rousseau, Paul Janet,

Histoire des doctrines politiques (2d ed.), II, 612 and Tchernoff, Revue du

droit public (1903), II, 96. For denial of this claim cf. Léon Duguit, "The

Law and the State," Harv. Law Rev., XXXI (Nov. 1917), 27 ff. See also E.

Doumergue," Les origines historiques de la Declaration des droits de l'homme

et du citizen," Revue du droit public, XXI (1904), 673; and Fritz Klovekorn,

Zur Entstehung der Erklärung der Menschen und Bürgerrechte (Berlin, 1910).


38. Jellinek, op. cit., p. 88. Marcaggi deals fully with different phases

of this controversy. He concludes that the Declaration of 1789 was

essentially a French product -- the French Declaration presenting an

interpretation, philosophic in character, of superior laws, universal and

immutable, whereas the English and American bills of rights were traditional

and practical in character. Jellinek declares that "whatever may be the

value or worthlessness of its general phrases it is under the influence of

this document that the conception of the public rights of the individual has

developed in the positive law of the states of the European continent." Op.

cit., p. 2.


39. Carl Becker, The Declaration of Independence (New York, 1922), pp 256,

257. Edmund Burke styled the French Constitution of 1793 a "digest of

anarchy."


40. At the time of the adoption of the federal Constitution, Professor

McMaster states that "we see that very scanty recognition seems to have been

given to the equality of men, or to their inalienable rights to life,

liberty and the pursuit of happiness." John Bach McMaster, The Acquisition

of Political, Social and Industrial Rights of Man in America (Cleveland,

1903), p. 40.


41. Becker, op. cit., p. 258. The chief object at this time was "to make

terms with political democracy without opening the door to social upheaval."

Ibid., p. 238.


Eighteenth-century natural law developed anti-social tendencies by making

the individual conscience the ultimate arbiter of political and legal

obligations. Cf. Pound, Law and Morals (2d ed.), 88, and Justice Wilson's

dictum that "The consent of those whose obedience the law requires ... I

conceive to be the true origin of the obligation of human laws." Works

(Andrew's ed.), I, 192. David G. Ritchie set about in an extensive treatise

to demolish the theories of natural rights. "I had a certain fear," he

wrote, "that in criticising that famous theory I might be occupied in

slaying the already slain. Recent experience has, however, convinced me that

the theory is still, in a sense, alive or at least capable of mischief. ...

The real significance of the appeal to nature is, in the first place, the

negative element in the appeal, it is an appeal against authorities that

had lost their sacredness, against institutions that had outlived their

usefulness." Natural Rights: A Criticism of some Political and Ethical

Conceptions (London, 1895), IX, 13.


As is the case with other opponents of the doctrine the gist of Ritchie's

argument centers about the use of the terms "natural" and "necessary" and

some who refuse to accept his version of the use of these terms regard his

criticism as largely futile and overdrawn. For instance, A. Inglis Clark

believes that Ritchie's work contains "the materials for a perfect defense

of the doctrine which it was written to confute." "Natural Rights," in The

Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, XVI (1900),

221.


42. Becker, op. cit., p. 266.


43. Justice Wilson, an exponent of natural rights theories, believed that

"no exterior human authority can bind a free and independent man." Works

(Andrew's ed.), I, 192; cf. also, Letters of Jefferson, Writings (Ford's

ed.), V, 115-124; X, 37, 42-45.


44. For English reactionary views, see H. J. Laski, English Political

Thought from Locke to Bentham, pp. 243-256 and for the reaction of the

historical school of jurisprudence, consult Savigny, Vom Beruf unserer Zeit

für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft (1814).


45. Michel, op. cit., pp. 164-168.


46.Professor Becker thinks "the political ideas which in the United States

discredited the doctrines of the Declaration of Independence were similar in

essentials to those which in Europe had already deprived the Declaration of

the Rights of Man of its former high prestige." The Declaration of

Independence, p. 256.


47. "American Interpretations of Natural Law," Amer. Pol. Sci. Rev., XX,

536; see also Wright, "George Fitzhugh on the Failure of Liberty,"

Southwestern Pol. and Soc. Sci. Quar., VI (December, 1025), 219.


48. "American Interpretations of Natural Law," Amer. Pol. Sci Rev., XX.,

537.


49. William A. Dunning, op. cit., p. 217.


50. Works, 1, 136. "The founders use this phrase [natural law] as if there

were a code of natural laws, they appeal to these laws, they cite them, they

literally oppose them to the laws of the legislators, and they do not

perceive that these natural laws are of their own invention." Bentham, in

Principles of Legislation, Part I, XIII, 46. Cf. chapter by Michel on "La

reaction en Allemagne et en Angleterre," pp. 134 ff.


Sir Frederick Pollock charges Bentham with being a follower of a form of

Naturrecht which is "no more congenial to the positive law which lawyers

discuss and administer than that of Ahrens or Kant." Science of Politics, p.

111.


For Burke's criticism of the French theories of the rights of men consult

his Reflections on the French Revolution (1790).


51. Cf. Friedrich Meinicke, Die Idee der Staatsräson (2d ed. Berlin, 1925),

pp. 468, 480; also Renan, L'Avenir de la science.


52. Renan believed that the individuals who insisted on natural or inherent

rights were rarely able to appreciate them if guaranteed protection by the

state, and he thought the needs of society should take precedence over

individual rights. Op. cit., p. 357, and Questions contemporaines, p. 477;

cf. also, Philip G. Neserius, "The Political and Social Philosophy of

Renan," Southwestern Pol. and Soc. Sci. Quar. VIII (June, 1927), 40, 41.

Natural rights or rights belonging to the individual were to be replaced by

"the right of reason to govern humanity and by rights which are the result

of history."


53. Grundlegung der Philosophie des Rechts, secs. 104-114; Reyburn, Hegel's

Ethical Theory, pp. 118-121; Michel, op. cit., pp. 154 ff. Hegel repudiated

the ideas of a state of nature and of natural rights resulting therefrom. He

believed that the ultimate sanction of a state's power is force and that the

prince or sovereign cannot be bound by a higher law.


54. "No man has any rights properly called. No one possesses any other right

than that of always doing his duty." Comte, Politique positive, II, 361.


55. Vom Beruf unserer Zeit für Gestezgebung und Rechtswissenschaft (1814),

pp. 5 ff., and System des heutigen Romischenrechts, sec. 7. Consult also

followers of Savigny, G. F. Puchta, Kursus Institutionem and F. J. Stahl,

Die Philosophie des Rechts (Heidelberg, 1854).


"Glorification of the positive law that is, to the disparagement of the

natural law that ought to be, is characteristic of the reaction that has

followed the rationalistic liberalism of the Age of Enlightenment. It may

be that this positivism is largely due to the expansion of modern industry

and commerce which has caused lawyers to be more concerned with the

protection of private economic interests than with the larger issues of

social well-being. In any case it is true that since the French Revolution,

authoritarian reactionaries like De Maistre, romantic historicists like

Savigny, idealizers of the actual like Hegel, utilitarians like Bentham,

and positivists like Comte, have all united to heap scorn on the old liberal

doctrine that men can and should change law to conform to their idea of

natural law or justice." From Morris R. Cohen, "Positivism and the Limits of

Idealism in the Law," Columbia Law Review, XXVII (March, 1927), 237.


56. Cf. Pound, Law and Morals, 2d ed., pp. 15-25. Dean Pound observes that

"the historical jurist merely gave us a new natural law on a new basis."

Ibid., p. 21.


57. Review of "Interpretations of Legal History," by Pound, Harv. Law Rev.,

XXXVII (December, 1923), 280.


58. R. Saleilles, "Ecole historique et droit naturel d'après quelques

ouvrages recents," Revue trimestrielle de droit civil, I (1902), 80 ff.


59. See John Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence, 5th ed., edited by Robert

Campbell (London, 1885), I, 86, 178; II, 567 ff.


"The whole or a portion of the laws set by God to men is frequently styled

the law of nature, or natural law; being, in truth, the only natural law of

which it is possible to speak without a metaphor, or without a blending of

objects which ought to be distinguished. But, rejecting the appellation Law

of Nature as ambiguous and misleading, I name those laws or rules as

considered collectively or in a mass, the Divine Law, or the Law of God."

Ibid., 1, 86. Austin regarded the laws of God as laws In the proper sense

because they were commands. I, 89, 175, 183, 338; also, Vinogradoff,

Historical Jurisprudence, I, 115 ff.


60. Duguit, "The Law and the State," Harv. Law Rev., XXXI (November, 1917),

126 ff.


61. George Lawrence Scherger, The Evolution of Liberty (New York, 1904), p.

11.



                     PART II


 THE ACCEPTANCE OF NATURAL LAW OR SUPERIOR LAW
 CONCEPTS IN THE PUBLIC LAW OF THE UNITED STATES


                    CHAPTER IV


    JUDICIAL CONSTRUCTION OF IMPLIED LIMITS ON
               AMERICAN LEGISLATURES


1. Denial of the Application of Natural Law Concepts. Despite the recognized

use and importance of natural law phrases in American law in colonial and

revolutionary times, and the continual reference to such phrases in judicial

decisions, it is frequently asserted that in the United States there have

been merely isolated attempts to formulate a doctrine of natural law or

natural rights.[1] Following the customary habit of English legal

authorities of depreciating the importance of natural law theories in the

growth of English law, legal writers in the United States insist that such

theories have been of no practical significance in the evolution of American

law. Except for its unavowed use in the applications of the rule of reason

of the common law, the natural rights doctrine, after the enthusiasm of the

revolutionary period had waned, was most frequently invoked by judges in

those cases which involved the validity of legislative acts, tested by the

terms or standards of written constitutions. The orthodox legal view,

therefore, is that there is no case in which the courts have held an act

invalid or refused to enforce a law because regarded as contrary to natural

law, except when such a law was in conflict with an express constitutional

provision.[2] The doctrine of natural rights then is regarded as of mere

academic importance and not of vital concern in the application of actual

positive law in America. Others admit that the natural law concept served a

useful purpose in the formative period of American constitutional law but

claim that the term has now been consigned to "the museum of juristic

relics."[3] An example of the prevailing view today is as follows:


    They [natural rights] are, and by right ought to be, dead ...
    and yet, while in this country only old judges and hopelessly
    antiquated text-book writers still cling to this supposedly
    eighteenth century doctrine, on the Continent the doctrine of
    natural law has been revived by advanced jurists of diverse
    schools.[4]


Most lawyers and jurists in the United States are inclined to agree with

John W. Salmond that "as far as secular science is concerned, the history of

the doctrine of natural law is for the most part a chapter in the history of

human error." Notions of law and of obligation are, he thinks, "in the

sphere of natural right, but mocking and misleading echoes." Natural law can

be used by philosophers only to refer to principles of right.[5] Political

scientists have joined the lawyers in attempting to discard the use of

concepts of natural law.[6]


It is usual to insist that natural law theories are false historically and

untenable philosophically because they confound the actual and the ideal.[7]

The cavalier manner in which these theories are disposed of may be

illustrated by the following extract:


    When we come to a general philosophy of law, writers are
    still chopping the old worthless chaff of what they call the
    analytical or the historical or the jus naturale school, which
    have been the work of men not lawyers. They go on
    classifying, reclassifying, subdividing and resubdividing the
    writers upon legal philosophy and their conceptions, which
    have never had the slightest influence on the actual
    development of law. Kant's or Hegel's philosophies of law
    which are merely philosophies of right, the term used
    ambiguously, -- this pale moonshine of metaphysics which
    never had scientific reality, -- or theories of the divine origin
    of law or of its historical growth, or dicta of the school
    which bases law not on what it is, but on some assumed
    power that created it, are still the stuff of which legal
    philosophical dreams are made. We have the tangled
    metaphysics of Kohler, the rigid, logical deductions of the
    French or the practical makeshifts of the English seeking to
    do duty as legal philosophy.


    What has always been needed is scientific study. That study
    asks for facts and facts alone, unclouded by hasty
    generalizations.[8]


2. Natural Law Theories in the Formative Period of American Law. Some years

ago I traced in a brief summary the prevalence of the ideas associated with

the doctrine of natural rights and natural law in the public law of the

United States.[9]


It was then indicated that those who imagine natural law theories may be

consigned to the "museum of juristic relics" fail to comprehend, or to give

due consideration to, one of the characteristic and significant phases in

the development of American public and private law. Numerous instances were

cited indicating the persistence in American judicial opinions of doctrines

of natural rights and of natural laws which were regarded as limiting the

exercise of all public powers. It was shown that, in the decisions of the

courts in the United States, there were frequent reassertions of the old

doctrines of natural rights or of natural laws despite many criticisms of

these doctrines and in the face of repeated assertions that there were

neither natural rights nor natural laws. And that at the time when some of

the significant ideas embodied in the old doctrine were slowly being

discarded they were given new vigor by incorporating them with more

extensive implications in a new meaning derived from the phrase "due process

of law." Merely a brief consideration can be given to the background of the

natural rights philosophy in American judicial reasoning.[10]


The terms "natural right" and "natural justice," which were in common use by

lawyers and judges in colonial and revolutionary times, were not entirely

discarded when the Declaration of Independence and its philosophy began to

lose repute. Higher law concepts were made use of freely to strengthen the

belief in the efficacy of written constitutions, to support the developing

practice of the courts of reviewing legislative acts to test their

conformity with these constitutions, and to assist in the judicial

construction of implied limits on legislative powers. They were applied

especially to construe limits favorable to the protection of vested contract

and property rights. In developing the principle that vested rights should

be protected, whether or not written provisions of laws or of constitutions

required, Justices Paterson, Chase, Marshall, Story, Kent, and others made

extensive use of the theories of natural and inalienable rights.[11]


Natural law theories influenced various branches of private law, as it was

accepted and developed in the Colonies and later when separate state

governments were set up. Just as Pollock indicates in his summary of the

concealed applications of these theories in English law, common law ideas

embodying the rule of reason were made an integral part of the American

legal practice. In fact, the application of such ideas was more extensive

and persistent in the United States because of the necessity of applying

principles of justice and of reason in adapting English law to American

conditions and in supplementing defects in legislation, where conditions

were rapidly changing. It is not within the scope of this study to enter

into the details of these extensive uses of natural or higher law concepts,

as they were interwoven into various branches of private law. Attention will

rather be directed to the acceptance of the superior law philosophy in the

development of implied limits on the activity of legislatures, and in the

interpretation of the general terms of written constitutions. The natural

law philosophy, which was extensively applied in the formative period of

American law, soon after it came into disrepute was covertly restored and

became the most prolific source of limitations on the legislatures both of

the states and of the nation. So far as public law is concerned

opportunities for the use of higher law doctrines occurred chiefly in

connection with the review of legislative acts by the courts, and especially

in that phase of review in which the justices aimed to discover implied

limits on legislative powers. Hence, it is to this phase of the acceptance

of higher law notions in American constitutional law to which primary

consideration will be given.


3. Higher Law Theories as a Sanction for the Establishment of the Review of

Legislative Acts by Courts. As a sanction for the moral and legal notions of

a period there are what has been termed "postulates of legal thought,"

usually taken for granted and seldom critically examined.[12] Some such

postulates or fundamental conceptions alone can account for the importance

attached by the American colonists to written instruments, as fundamental

charters of political organization, and to the correlative idea that judges

were charged with the duty of serving as intermediaries to preserve these

charters for the benefit of the people, as against actual and anticipated

attacks by the other departments of government. At this time, it was

generally taken for granted, in the first place, that there were natural

rights inhering in the individual as such which governments could merely

discover and preserve but could not legally curtail. All governmental powers

were to be carefully scanned to determine whether these individual rights

were not unduly interfered with. Second, there was a notion that some of the

important relations and powers of government should be defined in a

fundamental act or constitution, and such a constitution was considered as

having a superior sanctity. It is remarkable to see how soon after their

adoption the first written constitutions were looked upon with reverent awe.

Third, since the preservation of individual rights and privileges often

involved the application of legal terms developed largely by the courts and

since the fundamental written charter also embodied numerous phrases of

legal significance, there was a prevalent desire to turn to the courts as

authoritative interpreters of the fundamental law. Especially was this true

since the judges had gained prestige at times in resisting the arbitrary

acts of either kings or parliaments.


The general acceptance of these postulates or assumptions accounts for the

relatively few critical analyses of the arguments of the courts in favor of

the doctrine that it was their duty to review legislative acts. Such

postulates go far to explain not only why so few men are on record as

opposed to the assumption of extraordinary powers of a quasi-legislative

nature by the judiciary with no express grant to warrant it, but also why

such reasoning as that of John Marshall in the case of Marbury v. Madison

was not critically analyzed and its weaknesses pointed out for more than a

decade.


The reasons for the adoption of the American doctrine of constitutional law

as defined by John Marshall were as follows:


    1. The Constitution is a law of superior obligation and
    consequently any enactments contrary thereto, which are
    ipso facto void, must be held invalid.


    2. The courts must exercise this power in order to uphold
    the terms of a written constitution or, in other words, a
    written constitution necessitates the exercise of this power
    by the judiciary.


    3. The oath of judges to support the Constitution requires
    that justices follow the Constitution and disregard the
    statute.


    4. The phraseology of the Constitution warrants the exercise
    of such authority by the judges.


It may readily be shown, as was done by Justice Gibson in 1825,[13] that not

one of the above reasons in any way explains or justifies the use of this

extraordinary power by the judiciary. First, if the Constitution is a law of

superior obligation, on what ground does the court insist that its judgment

on the meaning of the Constitution is superior to that of the legislature

which has enacted the law? Second, is such a power necessary to uphold the

terms of a written constitution? If so, why do many constitutions deny to

the courts this extraordinary power, or why is such authority frequently

considered as not within the scope of judicial functions? With regard to the

oath in support of the Constitution, all officers, including the members of

the legislature, the judges, and the executive take the same oath. Why does

the oath of the judges give them authority to revise or condemn the

judgments made by coordinate departments?


Why should a legislative act passed in due form, following all the laws of

procedure, be held as never having been passed or ipso facto void? Is it not

presumptuous to assume that the bona fide acts of any one department may be

declared by another to be of no avail? In fact, as indicated by Justice

Gibson, every argument in favor of this doctrine begins by assuming the

whole ground in dispute. The unexpressed reason for the conclusions of Chief

Justice Marshall was that he and his associates of the Federalist Party

distrusted popular assemblies and executives who might be controlled by

public opinion.


Underlying principles, then, on which the American theory of a written

constitution was based are as follows:[14]


First, a distrust of legislative power. It was generally thought, at the

time that American constitutions were formed, that the legislative authority

ought to be restricted and that special precautions should be taken to

protect the people against legislative domination.


Second, the protection of the minority. To protect the minority against the

danger of oppressions by majority rule was another purpose which the

founders of the American government set about to accomplish in the process

of constitution-making. It was thought by Madison and others that the merits

of the federal Constitution lay in the fact that it secured the rights of

the minority against "the superior force of an interested and overbearing

majority."


Third, the protection of property rights. A third principle underlying the

process of constitution-making was the belief that property was a sacred

right, which it was the supreme function of the government to preserve and

protect. Thus the major premise in drafting written instruments as a source

of governmental action was a distrust in legislatures. Popular assemblies

might interfere with the rights of property and contract and might not

respect the liberties of the individual, and the prime object of the

government was to protect such liberties. These assumptions or prevailing

beliefs were predicated to a considerable extent upon the eighteenth-century

notions of natural rights and upon laws of nature which were thought to be

indispensable to the social compact.


The original idea of those who favored the judicial review of legislative

acts seems to have been to preserve the independence of the courts as

against the other departments of government, and to protect these

inalienable personal and property rights.[15] There were at this time

comparatively few limitations on legislative powers even when written

constitutions were adopted. Some of the first state constitutions, like the

present British North America Act of Canada, contained no bills of rights

and few, if any, general phrases from which limitations on legislative

powers might be construed.


The significance of the judicial review of statutes in the United States is

due not only to the increasing tendency to restrain legislative powers by

express restrictions but also to a large extent to the development of the

superior law philosophy as a warrant to secure implied limits on

legislatures and to certain related concepts which have made this power an

effective means of exercising a censorship over legislative acts.[16]


Among the limitations and restrictions used as tests to determine the

validity of legislative acts,[17] resulting from the application of higher

law doctrines are: implied limits on legislative powers growing out of the

nature of the social compact, the fundamental principles of a free

republican government, or the spirit of a written constitution based on

popular sanction; limits designed to protect vested rights; and the

extension of the meaning of the "due process of law" and "equal protection

of the law" phrases from a limitation on executive authority only to a

restriction on legislative powers.[18] These limitations have been enlarged

by giving greater force to the separation of power theory, and by

interpreting the "due process of law" and the "equal protection of the law"

phrases into a general rule of reason to measure the validity of all

legislation.


Written constitutions, containing a separation of power principle and some

express limits on legislative powers, might have been regarded chiefly as

guides to the political departments of the government and to the electorate,

as is customary in Europe. But through the adoption of the practice of

judicial review of legislation, coupled with the development of implied

limitations judicially enforced, written constitutions came to be regarded

as rigid enactments containing superior and immutable laws and principles to

which all legislative acts must be held to conform. From a mere political

guide binding on the conscience of officers the written constitution became

a convenient device by which individuals in the settlement of their private

rights could bring the government itself to the bar of justice and require

it to justify its acts, according to judicially construed standards of

fairness and reasonableness.


Judicial review, then, as originally adopted, would have had relatively

slight influence on the American government and politics, just as is the

case in most foreign countries which have adopted this practice, but for the

development of these implied restrictions arising from a revised version of

natural law theories. The justices extended judicial censorship over

legislative acts and, in effect, adopted Coke's idea of the supremacy of the

courts over the other departments of government in applying the general

doctrine that constitutional grants of power were to be interpreted

according to the maxims of Magna Carta and the principles of the common law,

and that legislatures were limited by superior laws, both express and

implied.[19]


4. Limits on Legislatures resulting from the Nature of the Social Compact

and from the Nature of Free Republican Governments. The classic statement of

the theory that legislative power, independent of written constitutions, was

limited by the principles of republican government and of the social

compact, is found in the opinion of Justice Chase in Calder v. Bull, in

which he said:


    I cannot subscribe to the omnipotence of a state
    legislature, or that it is absolute and without control;
    although its authority should not be expressly restrained by
    the Constitution, or fundamental law, of the state. The
    nature, and ends of legislative power will limit the exercise
    of it. This fundamental principle flows from the very nature
    of our free Republican governments, that no man should be
    compelled to do what the laws do not require, nor to
    refrain from acts which the laws permit. There are acts
    which the Federal, or State, Legislature cannot do, without
    exceeding their authority. There are certain vital
    principles in our free Republican governments, which will
    determine and overrule an apparent and flagrant abuse of
    legislative power; as to authorize manifest injustice by
    positive law; or to take away that security for personal
    liberty, or private property, for the protection whereof the
    government was established. An Act of the legislature (for I
    cannot call it a law) contrary to the great first principles of
    the social compact, cannot be considered a rightful
    exercise of legislative authority. The obligation of a law in
    governments established on express compact, and on
    republican principles, must be determined by the nature of
    the power, on which it is founded. A few instances will
    suffice to explain what I mean. A law that punishes a citizen
    for an innocent action, or, in other words, for an act, which,
    when done, was in violation of no existing law; a law that
    destroys, or impairs, the lawful private contracts of
    citizens; a law that makes a man a judge in his own cause;
    or a law that takes property from A and gives it to B. It is
    against all reason and justice for a people to intrust a
    Legislature with such powers; and, therefore, it cannot be
    presumed that they have done it. The genius, the nature
    and the spirit, of our State Government, amount to a
    prohibition of such acts of legislation; and the general
    principles of law and reason forbid them. The legislature
    may enjoin, permit, forbid, and punish; they may declare
    new crimes, and establish rules of conduct for all its citizens
    in future cases; they may command what is right, and
    prohibit what is wrong; but they cannot change innocence
    into guilt; or punish innocence as a crime; or violate the
    right of an antecedent lawful private contract; or the
    right of private property. To maintain that our Federal, or
    State, Legislature possesses such powers, if they had not
    been expressly restrained, would, in my opinion, be a
    political heresy altogether inadmissible in our free
    republican governments.[20]


Justice Chase's emphatic defence of the theory of implied limitations on

legislative powers, resulting from the principles of the social compact and

of the spirit of a free republican government, was an obiter dictum.

However, as often occurs with opinions unnecessary to the disposition of a

controversy, it was a convenient expression of doctrines of superior

principles which future justices of like mind could cite as authority for

placing a curb on legislatures, at times disposed to tamper with existing

contract and property rights. Such a dictum served as a basis not only for a

doctrine favorable to the protection of vested rights, but also for a theory

of "fundamental principles" held by judges to be beyond legislative control.

Judicial construction of theories favorable to the protection of vested

rights against alleged harmful legislative acts, and the subsequent

development of Justice Chase's theory of "fundamental principles," which

judges are charged to protect, will be discussed later.


5. Construction of Limits on Legislatures to protect Vested Rights. A

significant phase of the implied limitations based on higher law ideas, held

to apply to legislative powers in American constitutional law, is the doctrine of the protection of acquired or vested

rights.[21] Though certain limits were suggested to the exercise of

political authority with respect to private property, particularly during

the Middle Ages,[22] the developing theory of legislative omnipotence of

princes or of legislatures supported the view that private property might be

taken freely for the public benefit. Eighteenth century individualism and

the natural rights philosophy that accompanied it again became the basis for

the insistence that state action which invaded private rights had to justify

itself. Thus arose the idea which was asserted in colonial and revolutionary

times that vested rights must be protected, regardless of whether express

enactments or constitutional limitations so required.[23] A not uncommon

opinion at this time was that the sole function of government was to protect

and preserve property rights.[24]


After the federal Constitution was put into operation, this view was

reaffirmed by Justice Paterson, who insisted that "the right of acquiring

and possessing property and having it protected, is one of the natural,

inherent and unalienable rights of man.... The preservation of property,

then, is the primary object of the social compact."[25] The Supreme Court of

North Carolina, also affirming the higher law doctrine, denied the power to

the legislature to dissolve a contract.[26]


When the doctrine of legislative supremacy even over individual rights of

property and contract prevailed, a few courts building upon the common law

maxim that statutes ought not in doubtful cases to be given a retroactive

operation laid down the doctrine as one of prime obligation that, in no

case, was a statute to receive an interpretation which brought it into

conflict with vested rights. So far as a statute did not impair vested

rights, it was good, but so far as it did, it was void, according to the

general principles underlying all constitutions.[27]


Though there are few federal cases in which the doctrine favorable to the

protection of vested rights on the higher law theories was affirmed prior to

1870, Chief Justice Marshall indicated his adherence to the doctrine as

early as 1803, when he observed "the government of the United States has

been emphatically termed a government of laws, and not of men. It will

certainly cease to deserve this high appellation, if the laws furnish no

remedy for the violation of a vested legal right."[28] Later he held that an

act of the legislature of Georgia, granting title to land was, so far as

rights vested under the grant were concerned, a contract which could not be

impaired by a subsequent act.[29] "I do not hesitate to declare," said

Justice Johnson in this case, "that a state does not possess the power of

revoking its own grants. But I do it on a general principle, on the reason

and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the

Deity."[30]


Prior to the date of this decision, leading exponents of Federalist policies

such as James Wilson, Alexander Hamilton, and John Marshall had formulated

as a principle of the party the theory of protecting vested rights of

property and contract, both by express and implied constitutional

limitations. They sponsored an independent judiciary, whose duty, they

argued, was to guard the fundamental law and to check all departments of

government so far as they might attempt to infringe vested rights.[31] The

theory of affording special protection to vested rights and of securing such

protection through limits defined in written constitutions and through

courts whose duty it was to guard these constitutions, was a Federalist

principle which continued in vogue long after the downfall of the Federalist

party.[32] It gained support from the liberal and democratic theories of

inalienable individual rights.


The doctrine that vested rights must be protected against legislative

attacks was greatly facilitated when the Supreme Court, speaking through

Chief Justice Marshall, held that the clause of the federal Constitution

prohibiting a state from impairing the obligation of contracts was intended

to restrain state legislatures from passing any law interfering with

"contracts respecting property, under which some individual could claim a

right to something beneficial to himself." The protection of this clause was

then held to apply to the property of corporations as well as to that of

individuals.[33]


More positive statements of the doctrine of judicial protection to vested

rights against attack by legislatures, independent of constitutional

limitations, was made by Chancellor Kent and Justice Story. When facing the

issue whether a statute could be given retroactive effect, Justice Kent

stated in unequivocal terms the theory of implied limitations on legislative

authority.[34] Basing his opinion squarely upon the natural law philosophy

of European writers such as Grotius, Pufendorf, and Bynkershoek, Chancellor

Kent held that the legislature can take private property for necessary or

useful public uses only when public necessity requires. To render the

exercise of the power valid, a principle of natural equity demands that a

fair compensation must, in all cases, be previously made to the individuals

affected. The limitation, he observed, "is admitted by the soundest

authorities and is adopted by all temperate and civilized governments, from

a deep and universal sense of justice."[35]


About ten years later, Kent reaffirmed these propositions,[36] emphasizing

the principle that the requirement of a public purpose was a true

constitutional limitation susceptible of judicial enforcement, and that

under the power of eminent domain the legislature could not transfer the

property of A to B without A's consent, unless it was clearly for a public

use nor without due compensation.[37] Kent admitted that there was one

limitation upon the general doctrine of the protection of vested rights,

viz., that property may not be used so as to create nuisances or become

dangerous to the peace, health, or comfort of the citizens. He developed,

therefore, the idea of the police power, which, in certain instances, may

override the rights and privileges of individual property[38] owners, but

the right of regulation and the ultimate power of prohibition, Kent

indicated, must be exercised according to principle of reasonableness, for

if the legislature should take private property for uses not clearly public

"such cases would be gross abuses of their discretion and fraudulent attacks

on private right, and the law would be clearly unconstitutional and

void."[38]


Thus Kent added the weight of his opinion as justice and his authority as

commentator to the view, which other justices had rather vaguely suggested,

that vested rights must be protected whether or not laws or constitutional

provisions so required. To the principle of just compensation in the

exercise of the power of eminent domain he added the requirement of public

use as a justification for the exercise of the power. Here were fundamental

principles for placing implied limits on legislatures. When, decades later,

parties imbued with nineteenth-century individualism, and corporations

seeking protection of their interests, brought pressure to bear on courts to

check what appeared to be meddlesome interferences with individual liberties

and property rights, these principles, closely related to the former

theories of natural law, were at hand to support the developing practice of

judicial review of legislative acts.


In the Supreme Court of the United States, Justice Story became the chief

exponent of the doctrine of implied limitations on legislative action, when

he claimed that a grant of title to land by the legislature was irrevocable

upon the principles of natural justice, upon the fundamental laws of every

free government, as well as under the Constitution of the United States.[39]

Subsequently this idea was reiterated in more explicit terms.[40] A number

of other justices, agreeing with Chief Justice Hosmer,[41] in the decades

following 1810, defended the principle of protecting vested rights, and held

that, independent of written constitutions, acts interfering with acquired

rights or impairing the obligation of contracts were void, for a fundamental

principle of right and justice inherent in the nature and spirit of the

social compact restrained and set bounds to the power of legislation, which

the legislature could not pass without exceeding its rightful authority.[42]


The state constitutions frequently did not prohibit the passage of

retroactive laws, but justices claimed such acts were nevertheless inhibited

because they were contrary to "fundamental principles" or "the nature of

free government" or "principles of the social compact" or "principles of

civil liberty" or "natural rights."[43]


The principle of protecting vested rights both by express and implied limits

on legislatures and of making it the duty of courts to hold void legislative

acts interfering with these rights continued to gain adherents after the

party which sponsored it had ceased to be a factor in the political life of

the nation. It was supported by a common belief that there was a higher law

and that there were immutable principles which, if legislatures attempted to

invade, would render their acts nugatory. But this higher law was seldom

resorted to, and courts rarely found it necessary to annul legislative

enactments on this or on other grounds.[44] Changes in political conditions

and in public sentiment combined to render of little avail the weakly

supported theory of protecting vested rights on the grounds of indefinite

superior principles.


6. The Main Purpose of the Establishment of Express and Implied Limits on

Legislative Powers. Constitutional limitations, as originally conceived and

as continued in the growth of American constitutional law, have been

regarded as self-imposed restrictions on the will of the people to check,

confine, and restrict the rule of the majority. Many of the founders of the

government in America agreed with Hamilton and Madison that it was necessary

to check "the overbearing rule of the majority."[45] In their opinion, there

could be neither justice nor stability in any system of government unless

some portion of it were independent of popular control. The Federalist party

under the leadership of Alexander Hamilton became the defender of this

faith. It was, from the beginning, observed Martin Van Buren, "the constant

aim of the late Federalists to select some department in our political

system and make it the depository of power which public sentiment could not

reach nor the people control."[46] The distrust of the capacity of the

masses to govern themselves was an underlying principle of the Federalist

viewpoint. Under no authority did they feel their interests to be safer than

under that which was subject to the judicial power, and in no way could

their policy be more effectively promoted than by taking power from those

departments of the government over which the people had full control in

order to concentrate it in that department over which they had practically

none.[47]


It was to carry out this purpose that the conservatives then and since have

demanded a judicial check on the other departments of government which

should operate under the guise of legal channels and which would prevent

popular control from seriously interfering with the interests desiring

special protection. Thus it became profitable for groups of interests to

combine, whose object was to control and influence the government and at the

same time to check and confine the growth of popular control. Among the

chief objectives of these groups were the following: to restrict the powers

of the state governments; to enlarge those of the national government; to

encourage a feeling of distrust of the capacity of the people to govern

themselves; to control the management of public affairs and to secure

special advantages to favored individuals and classes on the one hand, while

designedly opposing governmental interference in private pursuits of

individuals on the other. There was thus secured that effective combination

described by Fisher Ames of "the lovers of liberty and the owners of

property," supporting a practice whereby the courts were to act as sentinels

over constitutions to preserve vested contracts and property rights and

necessarily "to stay the arm of legislative, executive, or popular

oppression." [48] In the armor of devices to set limits to legislative

action the higher law philosophy was always available when express limits

were inconclusive and inapplicable. And it was called into service at this

time not as a progressive and liberal doctrine but as a conservative and

authoritarian principle.


7. A Reaction from the Federalist Doctrine of Limiting Legislative

Activities. When the Jeffersonian era of the first quarter of the nineteenth

century was followed by the wave of frontier democracy, which characterized

the Jacksonian epoch the general belief in the right of the people to rule

left little room for doctrines of immutable principles or higher laws which

were beyond governmental regulation. For several decades legislatures were

accorded a freedom in dealing with the lives, liberties, and properties of

individuals which would have shocked the founders of the American system of

government and would be regarded as untenable today. The bills of rights of

state constitutions were embellished with high-sounding phrases emblematical

of ideas prevalent in the Declaration of Independence and in other

eighteenth-century charters and documents but in practice little

consideration was given to these general phrases. Thus the insertion of an

elaborate clause requiring that governmental powers be carefully separated

into departments did not interfere with frequent intermingling of powers

among departments; and the provision that no person shall be deprived of

life, liberty, or property without due process of law was seldom used to

restrict political authority in favor of individual privileges. The

sentiment of the time was favorable to the expansion of governmental powers

rather than to a meticulous effort to find checks and limitations.[49]


But in a wave of reckless and extravagant conduct usually approved by the

people the legislatures sponsored all sorts of commercial projects and dealt

so freely with contracts and property rights that similar to the

conservative reaction, which inaugurated the federal system of government

under the Constitution and placed conservative doctrines in the state

constitutions, a second reaction followed calling for new limits to

legislative powers. Again the doctrines of natural rights and of immutable

laws were relied upon to place desired limits on governmental action. The

insistence on theories of popular sovereignty and some dangers believed to

follow from the rule of the people led lawyers and judges to question

whether an act of the legislature could not be declared void even if not in

conflict with some express provision of the constitution, and to seek for

other sanctions for the protection of vested rights through the

interpretation of implied limitations which would prevent too serious a

tampering with property rights.


8. The Return to the Former Natural Law Theories. Hence beginning in the

decade from 1850 to 1860 there was a return to the former doctrine of

natural rights and to the principle of implied limitations on legislatures

resulting from the nature of free government in order to check what then

seemed to be the reckless expenditure of money for the private advantage of

individuals. The courts of Massachusetts recurring to the dictum of Chief

Justice Parker[50] condemned legislative acts confirming conveyances and

proceedings in insolvency for the reason that vested rights were protected

by the inalienable rights, doctrine, and by the separation of powers and the

law of the land provisions of the state constitution.[51]


It was the courts of New York, however, which, building upon the principles

so ably defended by Chancellor Kent and becoming the champions of a new

individualism, led in the revival of the earlier doctrine of protecting

vested rights and of placing special implied limitations on legislative

powers.[52] In 1843 it was held that a statute which had been in force in

the state since 1772, authorizing a private road to be laid out over the

lands of a person, without his consent, was void. The law of land provision

of the state constitution was then held to import, when interferences with

individual rights and privileges were concerned, a trial according to the

course of the common law.[53] Holding void a law for the protection of the

property of married women, the court said, "the people of the state of New

York have never delegated to the legislature the power to divest the vested

rights of property legally acquired by any citizen of the state and transfer

them to another against the will of the owner."[54] This decision was soon

followed by another of even wider application, by which the courts held that

a prohibition act of the legislature of New York was void, because the act

substantially destroyed the property of intoxicating liquors vested in

persons within the state when the act took effect. Both upon the general

ground of implied limitations and upon the concept of due process of law, it

was contended that "when rights have been acquired by the citizen under the

existing laws, there is no power in any branch of the government to take

them away."[55]


The unique character of the reasoning of the New York court in placing

implied limits on the legislature is shown in the fact that similar statutes

in other states with approximately the same constitutional requirements

were, as a rule, held valid.[56]


The doctrine of affording judicial protection to vested rights, independent

of constitutional limitations, was soon to be absorbed in the phrase "due

process of law," commonly found in the state constitutions and introduced

into the Fourteenth Amendment as a requirement of all state legislation

which might interfere with the rights of life, liberty, or property. Its

application was also made more effective by bringing to its support the

principle of the separation of powers.[57] And certain implications of the

doctrine were soon formulated which widened its scope, namely, the

requirement of public use for eminent domain proceedings, and the

requirement of public purpose for taxation. Thus a step was taken of greater

significance than the adoption of written constitutions with certain

specific limitations on legislative powers and the acceptance of the

practice of judicial review of legislation to preserve these constitutions.

Numerous instances of foreign governments with written constitutions and the

correlative practice of judicial review of legislation give ample proof that

either or both of these features may have relatively slight effect in

restricting the scope of governmental powers. The doctrine requiring the

protection of vested rights alone would not have given judicial review its

present scope and significance. It was not until the extension of the

meaning of the term "due process of law," which took place from 1850 to

1890, that the scope and significance of judicial review of legislative

enactments was radically changed.


As a prelude to a general movement to return to the seemingly discredited

natural law theories the Abolitionists prior to the Civil War appealed to

natural rights and a higher law[58] as warranting a disregard of laws and

constitutional provisions. Abraham Lincoln based his argument against

slavery in the debate with Stephen A. Douglas on the dogma of the

Declaration that "all men are created equal" and deduced therefrom that for

one man to enslave another was contrary to the "sacred right of

self-government."[59] The attack on slavery was generally defended on the

principle of the "unalienable rights of all men to equal liberty"[60] -- a

recurrence to the type of natural law conceived as democratic and

progressive.


The tendency which after 1850 sought to protect vested rights against

encroachments by legislative acts or by popular majorities encouraged a

recurrence to the doctrine of inalienable rights and to the theory of higher

laws in order to change the due process of law clause from merely a check on

procedure in criminal matters to a limitation on the general scope of

legislative powers. For nearly twenty years the country was absorbed in the

throes of civil war and the conservative reaction which usually follows in

the wake of wars furnished fruitful ground for the seeds sown in the earlier

decades to take firm root. But another twenty years elapsed before the basis

was firmly laid for the modern revival of natural law ideas in American

constitutional law. These ideas have wrought a profound change in

constitutional concepts. They have followed lines only vaguely or indirectly

drawn during the first hundred years of constitutional development in the

United States. It is necessary to turn, therefore, to the process of

interpreting due process of law as a convenient phrase to convey natural law

ideas.




1. A. W. Spencer, "The Revival of Natural Law," Central Law Journal, LXXX

(May 7, 1915), 347.


2. Cooley, Constitutional Limitations (8th ed., 1927), pp. 341 ff. and

Robert P. Reeder "Constitutional and Extra-Constitutional Restraints," Univ.

of Penna. Law Rev., LXI (May, 1913), 441, 446. See comment of James B.

Thayer, that "it may be remarked here that the doctrine of declaring

legislative acts void as being contrary to the constitution, was probably

helped into existence by a theory which found some favor among our ancestors

at the time of the Revolution, that courts might disregard such acts if they

were contrary to the fundamental maxims of morality, or as it was phrased,

to the laws of nature. Such a doctrine was thought to have been asserted by

English writers, and even by judges at times, but was never acted on. It has

been repeated here, as a matter of speculation, by our earlier judges, and

occasionally by later ones; but in no case within my knowledge has it ever

been enforced where it was the single and necessary ground of the decision,

nor can it be, unless as a revolutionary measure." "The Origin and Scope of

the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law," Harv. Law Rev., VII (October,

1893), 129, 133, reprinted in Thayer, Legal Essays, I, 6, 7.


3. Manley O. Hudson, "Advisory Opinions of National and International

Courts," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVII (June, 1924), 970, 971.


4. Cohen, "Jus Naturale Redidivum," Phil. Rev., XXV (November, 1916), 761.

"Exploded as this notion may seem to us," says Mr. Isaacs, "it is certainly

in keeping with the philosophy of the eighteenth century." "John Marshall on

Contracts, A Study in Early American Juristic Theory," Va. Law Rev., VII

(March, 1921), 413.


For the expression of similar views with the observation that the natural

rights doctrine is academic and belongs to "jurisprudence in the air," see

John E. Keeler, "Survival of the Theory of Natural Rights in Juridical

Decisions," Yale Law Jour., V (October, 1895), 14.


5. "The Law of Nature," Law Quar. Rev., XI (April, 1895), 121.


6. Cf. A. N. Holcombe, The Foundations of the Modern Commonwealth (New York,

1923), p. 438; W. F. Willoughby, The Government of Modern States (New York,

1919), pp. 166-168; W. W. Willoughby, The Nature of the State (New York,

1896), pp. 103 ff.; John W. Burgess, Political Science and Constitutional

Law. I (New York, 1890), 88.


7. T. J. Lawrence, A Handbook of Public International Law (10th ed. by Percy

H. Winfield, 1925), p. 6.


8. John M. Zane, in review of Sir Paul Vinogradoff's Custom and Right, Yale

Law Jour., XXXV (June, 1926), 1026.


9. "The Law of Nature in State and Federal Judicial Decisions," Yale Law

Jour., XXV (June, 1916), 615.


10. There is a field here for much more extensive investigations than have

yet been made; investigations which will effectually expose the common

fallacious contention that natural rights and natural law have long since

ceased to influence American law. Professor Wright is doing original work

along this line in tracing the evolution of these concepts in American

political theory. Cf. supra, pp. 53 n., 55 n.


11. Consult J. B. Thayer, Cases on Constitutional Law, pp. 946 ff., for

extracts from European natural rights philosophers which were cited by

American justices; and my articles "Judicial Review of Legislation in the

United States and the Doctrines of Vested Rights and of Implied Limitations

on Legislatures," Texas Law Rev., II (April, June, 1924), 257, 387 and

"Histories of the Supreme Court written from the Federalist Point of View,"

Southwestern Pol. and Soc. Science Quar., IV (June, 1923), 12.


12. Cf. Ludwig Ehrlich, "Proceedings against the Crown," Oxford Studies in

Social and Legal History VI, (Oxford, 1921), 9.


13. Eakin v. Raub, 12 Sergeant & Rawles 330.


14. Cf. C. G. Haines, The American Doctrine of Judicial Supremacy, pp. 185

ff.


15. Haines, op. cit., pp. 287 ff.


16. "American courts," says Dean Pound, "unrestrained by any doctrine of

Parliamentary supremacy, such as was established in England in 1688, found

themselves opposed to legislatures just as English courts of the sixteenth

and seventeenth centuries had been opposed to the Crown. They found in the

books, over and above express constitutional limitations, vague doctrines of

inherent limitations upon every form of law-making and of the intrinsic

invalidity of certain laws. They soon wielded a conceded power over

unconstitutional legislation." "Common Law and Legislation," Harv. Law Rev.,

XXI (April, 1908), 383.


17. In the following pages portions of a series of articles on "Judicial

Review of Legislation in the United States and the Doctrines of Vested

Rights and of Implied Limitations on Legislatures," published in Texas Law

Rev., II (April and June, 1924), 257, 387 and ibid., III (December, 1924),

I, are used by permission of the editors.


18. Upholding the inherent right of local self-government in cities and

towns the Supreme Court of Nebraska referred to the principle that the state

legislative power is unlimited and quoted the language of Von Holst: "This

does not mean, however, that these restrictions must always be expressed in

explicit words. As it is generally admitted that the factors of the federal

government have certain 'implied powers,' so it has never been disputed that

the state legislatures are subject to 'implied restrictions,' that is,

restrictions which must be deduced from certain provisions of the federal,

or state constitution, or that arise from the political nature of the Union,

from the genius of American public institutions," State v. Moores, 55 Neb.

480, 490 (1898).


19. Cooley, Constitutional Limitations, 1, 358. The underlying purpose of

most of these limitations was to place "the just principles of the common

law ... beyond the power of ordinary legislation to change or control them."

Justice Miller in Pumpelly v. Green Bay Co., 13 Wall. 166, 177 (1871); also

Pound, The Spirit of the Common Law (Boston, 1921), p. 25.


In order to see that the limitations of the constitution were observed and

that no arbitrary power was exercised by any department of government

Justice Peck suggested that "the statutes and common law have laid open a

warehouse of ways, means and processes, that the power of the judges may

not, for want of plans, be defeated in upholding constitutional rights."

Bank of State v. Cooper, 2 Yerg. (Tenn.) 599, 612 (1831).


20. 3 Dallas 386-389 (1798). The assertion of limitations imposed by the

social compact may be illustrated by the following cases: Chief Justice

Buchanan in Regents of the University of Maryland v. Williams, 9 Gill & J.

365, 408, 409 (1838), when a charter incorporating the regents of the

university was held a contract and not subject to impairment by a subsequent

legislative act, thought that independent of the provisions of the federal

and state constitutions "there is a fundamental principle of right and

justice, inherent in the nature and spirit of the social compact, (in this

country at least) the character and genius of our government, the causes

from which they sprang, and the purposes for which they were established,

that rises above and restrains and sets bounds to the power of legislation,

which the legislature cannot pass without exceeding its authority. It is

that principle which protects the life, liberty, and property of the citizen

from violation, in the unjust exercise of legislative power." "With those

judges, who assert the omnipotence of the legislature, in all cases, where

the constitution has not interposed an explicit restraint, I cannot agree,"

said Chief Justice Hosmer, in Goshen v. Stonington, 4 Conn. 209, 225 (1822).

It was claimed that an unjust infraction of vested rights must be regarded

as a violation of the social compact and must be considered by the judiciary

as void. Justice Butler, denying the right of the legislature to pass an

unreasonable retrospective law, said: "the power of the legislature in this

respect is not unlimited. They cannot entirely disregard the fundamental

principles of the social compact. Those principles underlie all legislation,

irrespective of constitutional restraints, and if the act in question is a

clear violation of them, it is our duty to hold it abortive and void" Welch

v. Wadsworth, Conn. 30, 149, 155 (1861). Cf. also, Wheeler's Appeal, 45

Conn. 306, 315 (1877).


21. A vested right is commonly defined as a right which has been acquired by

an individual under the law to do certain acts or to possess and use certain

things. See Justice Chase in Calder v. Bull, 3 Dallas 386 (1798). Rights are

regarded as vested when the right to enjoyment, present or prospective has

become the property of some particular person or persons as a present

interest. There is no standard of sacredness for property interests and

vested rights which are beyond legislative encroachment. The term "vested

rights" is regarded as one of convenience to secure certain ends and is

incapable of accurate definition. It is correctly observed that the

underlying idea involved in the attempt of the courts to give content to the

term is political and sociological rather than legal. Yale Law Jour., XXXIV

(January, 1925), 306, 307. Consult this note for examples of rights becoming

vested and of legislative acts held void for impairing vested rights. See

also Edward S. Corwin, "A Basic Doctrine of American Constitutional Law,"

Mich. Law. Rev., XII (February, 1914), 247. "The doctrine of vested rights,"

says Corwin, "represents the first great achievement of the courts after the

establishment of judicial review," and "is the very matrix of constitutional

limitations in this country." Ibid., p. 275, and "The Extension of Judicial

Review in New York: 1783-1905," ibid., XV (February, 1917), 281, 297.


22. The doctrine of according protection to acquired or vested rights was a

feature of mediaeval law and was particularly advocated by the jurists of

the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.


23. Symsbury Case, Kirby (Conn.) 444, 447 (1785); Ham v. McClaws, 1 Bay (S.

Ca.) 93, 98 (1789), in which a statute prohibiting the importation of slaves

was held not to interfere with vested rights of ownership. The court said:

"It is clear that statutes passed against the plain and obvious principles

of common right and common reason are absolutely null and void as far as

they are calculated to operate against those principles." For an English

case favoring the protection of vested rights, see Couch v. Jeffries, 4

Burrows 2460 (1769). Lord Mansfield's judgment meant only that where at all

possible a statute would be interpreted so as to preserve vested rights.


24. Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, I, 533-534, 541-542; II,

123.


25. Van Horne's Lessee v. Dorrance, 2 Dall. 304, 310 (1795). After referring

to various provisions of the constitution of Pennsylvania, Justice Paterson

maintained, "it is evident that the right of acquiring and possessing

property, and having it protected, is one of the natural, inherent and

inalienable rights of man.... The legislature therefore had no authority to

make an act divesting one citizen of his freehold, and vesting it in

another, without just compensation. It is inconsistent with the principles

of reason, justice and moral rectitude; it is incompatible with the

comfort, peace and happiness of mankind; it is contrary to the principles of

the social alliance, in every free government; and lastly, it is contrary to

the letter and spirit of the constitution." Ibid., 310.


26. Trustees of the University of North Carolina v. Foy, 2 Hay (N. C.) 310,

312 (1804). It was held that "the property vested in the trustees must

remain for the uses intended for the university, until the judiciary of the

country in the usual and common form pronounces them guilty of such acts as

will, in law, amount to a forfeiture of their rights or a dissolution of

their body." Cf. dissenting opinion of Justice Hall for an argument against

implied protection to vested rights.


27. Elliott's Executor v. Lyell, 3 Call. (Va. 1802), 268; Turpin v. Locket,

6 Call. 113 (1804), especially opinions of Judge Tucker, 155, and of Judge

Roane, 169.


28. Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 163 (1803).


29. Fletcher v. Peck, 6 Cranch 87 (1810). Chief Justice Marshall observed:

"It may well be doubted whether the nature of society and of government does

not prescribe some limits to the legislative power; and, if any be

prescribed, where are they to be found, if the property of an individual

fairly and honestly acquired, may be seized without compensation.... It is,

then, the unanimous opinion of the court, that in this case, the estate

having passed into the hands of a purchaser for a valuable consideration,

without notice, the state of Georgia was restrained, either by general

principles which are common to our free institutions, or by the particular

provisions of the Constitution of the United States, from passing a law

whereby the estate of the plaintiff in the premises so purchased could be

legally impaired." Ibid. 135, 139. For an account of the circumstances

leading to this case, consult Albert J. Beveridge, The Life of John

Marshall, III (Boston, 1919), chap. 10.


For Marshall's views as to the meaning of the phrase "obligation of

contract" as influenced by the eighteenth-century philosophy as to natural

rights, see Ogden v. Saunders, 12 Wheat. 213 (1827). Marshall adverted to

the tact that "the framers of our Constitution were intimately acquainted

with the writings of those wise and learned men, whose treatises on the laws

of nations have guided public opinion in the subjects of obligation and of

contract." Ibid., pp. 353, 354. Nathan Isaacs, "John Marshall on Contracts,"

Va. Law Rev., VII (March, 1921), 411, 421 ff.


30. 6 Cranch 143.


31. "Histories of the Supreme Court of the United States Written from the

Federalist Point of View," Southwestern Pol. and Soc. Sci. Quar., IV (June,

1023), 12.


32. See Hamilton's opinion in The Federalist, No. 78; also Beveridge, op.

cit. III, 568; cf. Hampton L. Carson, "James Wilson and James Iredell: A

Parallel and a Contrast," American Bar Association Journal, VII (March,

1921), 125 ff.; and Wales v. Stetson, 2 Mass. 143, 146 (1806).


33. Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 4 Wheat., 518, 628 (1819).


34. Dash v. Van Kleeck, 7 Johns (N. Y.) 477, 505 (1811); "It is not

pretended that we have any express constitutional provisions on the subject;

nor have we any for numerous other rights dear alike to freedom and justice.

An ex post facto law in the strict technical sense of this term, is usually

understood to apply to criminal cases, and that is the meaning when used in

the Constitution of the United States; yet laws impairing previously

acquired civil rights are equally to be condemned. We have seen that the

cases in the English and the Civil law apply to such rights; and we shall

find, upon further examination, that there is no distinction in principle,

nor any recognized in practice, between a law punishing a person criminally

for a past innocent act, and punishing him civilly by divesting him of a

lawfully acquired right. The distinction consists only in the degree of

oppression and history teaches us that the government which can deliberately

violate the one will soon cease to regard the other." Bracton, Pufendorf,

the mediaeval natural law philosopher, and dicta in a few American decisions

were cited in support of Kent's proposition.


35. Gardner v. Village of Newburgh, 2 Johns. Ch. 162, 166, 167 (1816). Kent

felt bound "to conclude, that a provision for compensation is an

indispensable attendant on the due and constitutional exercise of the power

of depriving an individual of his property." Ibid. 167.


36. "A retrospective statute, affecting and changing vested rights, is very

generally considered, in this country, as founded on unconstitutional

principles, and consequently inoperative and void." Commentaries, I (13th

ed., 1884), 455.


37. Again citing Grotius, Pufendorf, Bynkershoek, and Vattel, Kent

maintained that "a provision for compensation is a necessary attendant on

the due and constitutional exercise of the power of the lawgiver to deprive

an individual of his property without his consent; and this principle in

American constitutional jurisprudence is founded on natural equity, and is

laid down by jurists as an acknowledged principle of universal law." Comm.,

II, 339. Early cases sustaining this principle were cited in a footnote.

Ibid., pp. 339 ff. For the interpretation of public purpose as a limitation

on legislatures in tax and eminent domain proceedings see Part III.


38. Comm., II, 340.


39. Terrett v. Taylor, 9 Cranch 43 (1815), in which Justice Story observed:

"That the legislature can repeal statutes creating private corporations, or

confirming to them property already acquired under the faith of previous

laws, and by such repeal can vest the property of such corporation

exclusively in the state, or dispose of the same to such purposes as they

may please, without the consent or default of the corporators, we are not

prepared to admit; and we think ourselves standing upon the principles of

natural justice, upon the fundamental laws of every free government, upon

the spirit and letter of the Constitution of the United States, and upon the

decisions of most respectable judicial tribunals, in resisting such a

doctrine" Ibid. 52.


40. Wilkinson v Leland, 2 Pet 627, 658 (1829); Justice Story said: "The

fundamental maxims of free government seem to require, that the rights of

personal liberty and private property should be held sacred. At least no

court of justice in this country would be warranted in assuming, that the

power to violate and disregard them; a power so repugnant to the common

principles of justice and civil liberty; lurked under any general grant of

legislative authority, or ought to be implied from any general expressions

of the will of the people ... a different doctrine is utterly inconsistent

with the great and fundamental principle of republican government, and with

the right of citizens to the free enjoyment of their property lawfully

acquired. We know of no case, in which a legislative act to transfer the

property of A to B without his consent, has ever been held a constitutional

exercise of legislative power in any state in the Union. On the contrary, it

has been constantly resisted as inconsistent with just principles by every

judicial tribunal in which it has been attempted to be enforced."


41. Goshen v. Stonington, 4 Conn. 209 (1822).


42. See Bedford v. Shilling, 4 Serg. & R. (Pa) 400, 405 (1818) and comment

of C. J. Parker in Rice v. Parkman, 16 Mass. 326, 330 (1820). Regents v.

Williams, 9 G & J (Md.) 365, 403 ff. (1838).


43. For citation of cases, consult Bryant Smith, "Retroactive Laws and

Vested Rights," Texas Law Rev., V (April, 1927), 231, 237.


44. An exception to the general practice was made by the Supreme Court of

North Carolina when it was held partly on the basis of the law of land

provision that the legislature could not transfer an estate in an office.

Hoke v. Henderson, 4 Dev. 1, 15 (1833); cf. also Jones' Heirs v. Perry,

wherein a private act to sell the land of infants was held void, 10 Yerg.

59, 69 (1836).


45. It is the opinion of Professor Dodd that "most of our legal arrangements

and constitutions, both state and national, were designed to thwart and

defeat democracy." Wm. E. Dodd, "The Struggle for Democracy in the United

States," Int. Jour. of Ethics, XXVIII (July, 1918), 465.


46. Martin Van Buren, Inquiry into the Origin and Course of Political

Parties in the United States, p. 96.


47. Martin Van Buren, op. cit., p. 275.


48. Joseph Story, Miscellaneous Writings, p. 228.


49. The persistence of the natural rights philosophy in the state

constitutions, Professor Becker believes, may be attributed primarily to the

"conventional acceptance of a great tradition," for political leaders

continued to reiterate the dogmas of the Declaration of Independence at a

time when they were almost universally ridiculed as "glittering

generalities." The Declaration of Independence, pp. 240 ff. and S. G. Brown,

Life of Rufus Choate (ed. 1881), pp. 325, 326; see also John C. Calhoun's

"Disquisition on Government." F. L. Paxson observes: "It is evident as one

reads these [state] constitutions that a belief in natural rights found

ready lodgment in the minds of residents along the frontier.... As the

crown, and religion, and property lost favor as the foundations of

government, nature came to be the obvious parent of democracy.... It became

more important to preserve liberty than to get work done; more desirable to

check a possible usurpation than to promote efficiency." History of the

American Frontier, pp 100, 101. Professor Wright believes, however, that the

theories of natural law were more prevalent in eastern communities than on

the frontier. Cf. "American Interpretations of Natural Law," Amer. Pol. Sci.

Rev., XX (August, 1926), 535, 536.


50. Rice v. Parkman, 16 Mass. 326, 330 (1820). Under the general powers of

the legislature to pass reasonable and wholesome laws, C. J. Parker claimed

no one imagines that "the legislature could deprive a citizen of his estate,

or impair any valuable contract in which he might be interested."


51. Sohier v. The Massachusetts General Hospital, in which an act confirming

conveyances was held void "as contrary to the spirit and terms of the

constitution." 3 Cush. 483 (1849); Denny v. Matton, 84 Mass. 361 (1861).

"Every individual," said Justice Fletcher, "has a right, under the

constitution, to be protected in the enjoyment of his property, and no one

can be wholly and entirely deprived of it, by having it taken from him and

transferred to another, without compensation or benefit in any way, by a

special act of legislation." 3 Cush. 493.


52. From 1840 to the Civil War "there were probably more statutes

invalidated in New York on constitutional grounds than in all other states

in the Union combined." Edward S. Corwin, "The Extension of Judicial Review

in New York," Mich. Law Res., XV (February, 1917), 281. A considerable

expansion of judicial review in New York was "due in part to the going into

effect of the constitution of 1846, but in greater part to the conflict

between the conservative principles of the courts and the reform tendencies

of legislation, a conflict which also characterizes the ensuing decade."

Ibid., p. 285.


53. Justice Bronson in Taylor v. Porter, 4 Hill 140, 146 (1843); see also

dissent of Justice Nelson, in which he said "whether the security of the

citizen against such arbitrary legislation ... depends upon this clause of

the constitution, or rests upon the broader and more solid ground of natural

right never delegated by the people to the law-making power, it is

unnecessary now to enquire." Ibid. 149.


54. Justice Mason in White v. White, 5 Barb. 474 (1849); also opinion of

Justice Edwards, 12 N. Y. 202 (1854).


55. Justice Comstock thought the law of the land provision was "intended

expressly to shield private rights from the exercise of arbitrary power."

Ibid., p. 398. Wynehamer v. State of New York, 13 N. Y. 378, 382 ff. and 416

ff. (1856); see also, the earlier opinion of Justice Barculo in Holmes v.

Holmes, in which it was held "beyond the scope of legislative authority to

destroy vested rights of property." 4 Barb. 295, 300 (1848).


56. Cf. State v. Noyes, 10 Foster (N. H.) 279 (1855); Lincoln v. Smith, 27

Vt. 328 (1854); Goddard v. Jacksonville, 15 Ill. 589 (1854); People v.

Gallagher, 3 Gibbs. (Mich) 244 (1856); Fisher v. McGirr, 1 Gray (Mass) 1

(1854); State v. Paul, 5 R. I. 181 (1858) and State v. Keeran, 5 R. I. 497.

For a different conclusion see Beebe v. State, 6 Ind. 501, 508 (1856),

holding the right to manufacture and sell spiritous liquors an inalienable

right which the legislature could not take away. When in 1918 the supreme

court of Indiana reversed this decision, Justice Townsend said: "This court

is bound by the same constitution and has no right to curtail legislative

authority this side of the expressed limitations in it. Nor has this court

power to revolutionize the fundamental law by reading limitations into it."

Schmitt v. F. W. Cook Brewing Co. 187 Ind. 623, 626. Justice Spencer

dissented on the ground that the act violated "the principles of abstract

justice, as they have been developed under our republican institutions."

Ibid., 640 ff. A suggestive discussion of the cases interpreting the

doctrine of vested rights is presented by E S. Corwin in "A Basic Doctrine

of American Constitutional Law," Mich Law Rev., XII (February, 1914), 247,

and "The Doctrine of Due Process of Law before the Civil War," Harv. Law

Rev., XXIV (March and April, 1911), 366, 460.


57. Merrill v. Sherbume, 1 N. H. 199, 204 (1819).


58. "Declaration of Sentiments of the American Anti-Slavery Society in

Philadelphia, 1833," W E Channing, Slavery (ed. 1835), p. 31. "The

Constitution regulates our stewardship. But there is a higher law than the

constitution." Works of William H. Seward, I (Boston, 1884), 66, 74. Ct.

also William Hosmer, The Higher Law in its Relation to Civil Government with

particular Reference to the Fugitive Slave Law (1852). See also opinion of

Chase in his argument relative to the unconstitutionality of the fugitive

slave law in the case of Jones v. Van Zandt. C. E. Merriam, American

Political Theories (New York, 1906), p 212.


59. Carl Sandburg, Abraham Lincoln: The Prairie Years, II (New York, 1926),

16, 17.


60. Cf. T. V. Smith, "Slavery and the American Doctrine of Equality,"

Southwestern Pol. and Soc. Sci. Quar., VII (March, 1927), 333 ff.



                   CHAPTER V


  NATURAL LAW THEORIES AND DUE PROCESS OF LAW


1. Divergent Views on the Meaning of Due Process of Law. The development of

limitations on legislative powers in American constitutional law has been

greatly modified by the interpretation of the phrase "due process of law"

into a general restriction on legislative powers. As a unique product of

American public law, due process of law has come to be the foundation of a

considerable part of the modern structure of constitutional limitations on

legislative and executive powers, and it is the main provision through which

natural law theories were made a part of current constitutional law.


Reference may only be made here to a few steps in the gradual evolution of

the meaning of the famous phrase "by the law of the land" as inserted in the

thirty-ninth chapter of Magna Carta.[1] It is commonly conceded that the

purpose of the phrase "by the law of the land," which was later transformed

into the more popular form "due process of law," was intended primarily to

insist upon rules of procedure in the administration of criminal justice,

namely, that judgment must precede execution, that a judgment must be

delivered by the accused man's "equals," and that no free man could be

punished except in accordance with the law of England, per legem terrae.


On various occasions the original meaning of the law of the land provision

was extended. Certain authorities read into the phrase the requirement of an

indictment by a jury[2] and the Petition of Right referred to this phrase as

prohibiting the Crown from making arrests without a warrant. But in its

extended form it was primarily intended as a limitation upon the Crown in

the administration of justice, requiring in the apprehension and trial of

criminals a procedure established by law. There are few indications that the

provision was intended to serve as a limitation on the powers of Parliament.

Any intimations that such a limitation was applicable to Parliament were set

at rest when, after 1689, it assumed control, not only over the Crown, but

also over the courts and court procedure. In England, then, prior to the

eighteenth century due process of law had two fairly well recognized

meanings, namely, a method of procedure in criminal trials, and a procedure

following the ancient customary law or one rendered legal by parliamentary

enactment. The latter meaning had almost entirely supplanted the former in

English legal thought when the first American constitutions introduced the

phrase into the fundamental laws of the United States.


The term "the law of the land" was inserted into the Massachusetts

constitution of 1780[3] and soon found its place in a number of other state

constitutions. That the makers of our first constitutions thought of due

process of law primarily as a phrase relating to procedural limitations and

not as a general limitation on legislative powers seems to be indicated by

the facts -- that the term "due process of law" or "the law of the land" was

inserted in the part of the constitution dealing with procedure; that the

protection to be accorded through due process was left in charge of the

legislature; and that, when the due process clause was first presented to

the courts, it was not regarded by them as a limitation on the substantive

powers of the legislature.[4] Legislative violations of due process of law

in colonial times were to be corrected, as they are now in many countries,

by the influence of public opinion.


Due process of law in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments of the federal

Constitution had little significance as rendering protection either to

liberty or property prior to the decade of 1870.[5] In the states the phrase

was first given the same restricted interpretation and it was held, with

only a few exceptions, not to abridge the general powers of the

legislature.[6]


The interpretation of the origin and meaning of due process of law has led

to a controversy among legal scholars which is far from settled. Some claim

that these words were intended to convey the principle that laws in their

making and enforcement must not be arbitrary and must accord with natural or

substantial justice; in short, must not be contrary to principles of natural

law.[7] Others have contended that they were meant to provide that an

individual should not be interfered with in respect to his private rights

except through a regularly enacted law and formal legal procedure. The first

of these views, though vaguely hinted at on a few occasions from the time of

the promulgation of Magna Carta, was first effectively advanced in the

writings of Sir Edward Coke and some of his followers, and in the opinions

of judges in the United States, who were imbued with the idea that it was

the duty of the courts to set limits to the exercise of legislative powers

and were seeking a justification for such authority. As we have seen, Coke

had little evidence to support his broad claims for the supremacy of the

common law as interpreted by the judges, and the occasional dicta favorable

to his theory have had slight influence on the growth of English law --

separate from the general doctrine of the common law, when statutes did not

provide contrary rules, that principles of reason and justice must be

followed. But just as Coke read into the language of the cases in the

Yearbooks and in the English reports his own political and legal notions, so

his followers, and, especially, legal historians in the United States, who

are interested in defending the practice of the review of legislative acts

by the courts, have built an elaborate superstructure on a small

foundation.[8]


2. Due Process of Law as applied by the Justices of the State Courts prior

to 1870. For the first fifty years after the establishment of the state

governments, the legislatures exercised with but few exceptions a virtual

supremacy over the other departments. The executive was granted few powers,

was denied a veto power, and in other respects was made subordinate to the

other departments. Not only did the legislature create the courts and in

many respects supervise their action, but the judges were frequently

selected and removed by this body; and, in certain instances, the

legislature was made the final court of appeal. It was not unusual,

therefore, for legislatures to decide concrete cases and to dispose of cases

finally by special enactments. Though a few constitutions had provisions for

the separation of governmental powers, the other portions of the

constitutions so mingled the powers -- and the common practice of the time

favored such a mingling -- that the provisions for the separation of powers

had little practical effect. Judicial review of legislation as a check on

these extensive legislative powers, though asserted in occasional cases, had

comparatively little effect on the principle of legislative omnipotence

until toward the middle of the nineteenth century. The state and federal

governments were headed in a direction which, except for a rather marked

change of course, would have led to conditions similar to those prevailing

in England and in Canada. The affirmation of the doctrine of protecting

vested rights had already indicated such a change of course and the

interpretation of the law of the land provisions of the state constitutions

continued the process.[9]


It is not within the purpose of this study to deal with the numerous

judicial decisions which approved the doctrine that the legislatures had

powers as unlimited as the British Parliament, except so far as restricted

by the express provisions of written constitutions. According to this

doctrine the state legislatures had inherently the power to do whatever was

not expressly prohibited by either the federal or state constitutions.[10]


During the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries only an occasional

judicial dictum, such as those of Justice Chase in Calder v. Bull,[11] and

of Chief Justice Hosmer in Goshen v. Stonington,[12] denied legislative

omnipotence when express constitutional restrictions were not ignored.


How, then, did the term the "law of the land," or "due process of law," come

to be interpreted and understood as a general limitation on legislative

powers from which extensive implied restrictions have been developed? The

account of this development involves a considerable part of the growth of

constitutional law in state and federal governments. Only certain phases of

this growth can be briefly sketched. The development itself is intimately

connected with the acceptance of the doctrine of judicial review of

legislative acts, which was gradually established as a part of American

constitutional law in the generation from 1780 to 1810. It was the adoption

of the doctrine of judicial review that rendered it possible to give a

different content to the term "due process of law," though little progress

was made in this direction prior to 1850.


A pioneer case, somewhat like Calder v. Bull and Dash v. Van Kleeck[13] in

establishing implied limitations favorable to vested rights, involved a

North Carolina act repealing an earlier grant of lands to the university in

which due process of law was considered as a limitation on legislative

powers.[14]


In declaring this act void, the court defined the law of the land clause of

the bill of rights to mean that no one shall be deprived of his liberty or

property without the intervention of a court of justice, or without a jury.

It was nearly a generation later that the due process clause was again

defined in any effective measure as a general limitation on legislative

powers.[15]


Some ideas later conceived as involved in due process of law were, however,

taking form. In 1814 a Massachusetts court decided that, though the

legislature was given the right by the constitution to suspend the laws,

such suspensions must be general, for it is "manifestly contrary to the

first principles of civil liberty and natural justice, and the spirit of our

constitution and laws, that any one citizen should enjoy privileges and

advantages which are denied to all others under like circumstances."[16] The

concept of equality and generality in the application of the law later held

to be involved in due process of law was here extracted from the section of

the bill of rights limiting the suspension of laws by the legislature. A few

years later Daniel Webster, in arguing the Dartmouth College Case,

attributed the concept of generality in the application of legal rules to

the law of the land provision,[17] and it was not long before this dictum

met with approval in the state courts.[18] The law of the land provision was

called into service also as a device to prevent retrospective

legislation.[19]


Among the concepts regarded as belonging to due process of law none has had

more significant results than the identification with this phrase of the

natural and inalienable rights philosophy which was developed in the

revolutionary times and was crystallized into specific form in the

Declaration of Independence and in the bills of rights of state

constitutions. Thus the law of the land was judicially construed to mean

that no power was delegated to the legislature to invade the great natural

rights of the individual, and that where express limits were lacking implied

checks must be found to protect these natural rights.[20]


As a rule the appeals to due process of law, as a basis for limiting the

powers of the legislature, were quite different from the appeals to the same

ground for protection against arbitrary commitments without a trial or a

jury. In the first instance it was an appeal against the injustice of the

act in the hope that the legislature itself would repeal the act (only

rarely was the suggestion made that such an act was void), whereas in the

second it was expected that the courts would preserve and protect the

individual from an improper commitment or illegal procedure. Formerly

reference to due process of law was similar to the claim now occasionally

made in England that an act would be unconstitutional because contrary to

the well-known and historic political principles of the past.


It remained to give somewhat more definite content to the law of the land or

to due process of law than generality and equality in the operation of the

laws. The developing concept of protecting vested rights on the ground of

implied limitations on legislative powers had already prepared the way for

such a restatement and state justices soon took advantage of the

opportunities afforded.[21] But the concept of due process of law as

involving general limitations on legislative powers and as embodying a

doctrine of natural and inalienable rights beyond governmental authority was

not formulated as an effective check on legislative powers until the middle

of the nineteenth century. It was at this time that the principle was being

formulated by the justices that the state constitutions were not so much

grants of specific powers as limitations on the exercise of general

powers.[22]


The enormous losses entailed in building canals and supporting other

internal improvements had begun to undermine the former confidence in

legislative bodies. By 1856 the courts of New York found the due process of

law clause a convenient term to check what was then regarded as a

legislative movement to interfere with property rights. Holding invalid an

act for the more effectual protection of the property of married women for

the reason that the people never delegated to the legislature the power to

transfer to another the vested rights of property legally acquired by a

citizen, Justice Mason said:


    I maintain, therefore, that the security of the citizen against
    such arbitrary legislation rests upon the broader and more
    solid ground of natural rights, and is not wholly dependent
    upon those negatives upon the legislative formerly contained
    in the constitution. It can never be admitted as a just
    attribute of sovereignty in a government, to take the
    property of one citizen and bestow it upon another. The
    exercise of such a power is incompatible with the nature and
    object of all government and is destructive of the great end
    and aim for which government is instituted, and is subversive
    of the fundamental principles upon which all free
    governments are organized.[23]


Later a distinction was drawn between what was regarded as destruction and

regulation by statute, and the legislature was denied the power to destroy

property rights.[24] And due process of law was held to require procedure

under a pre-existing rule of conduct by which rights were lawfully acquired

and interference with these rights was prevented except by a trial and

judgment according to the procedure of the common law.[25]


Some milestones had been passed in giving new life and vigor to this portion

of "decrepit Magna Carta." The "law of the land" now being changed to the

more common term "due process of law" had in a few instances been applied as

a general limitation on legislative powers. It had been made a device to

retain a portion of the concept of natural and inalienable rights. And it

had been used as a weapon to wage battle against the political liberals or

radicals who were thought to be endangering property rights. So pliable a

concept was likely to be made use of when economic and political conditions

led conservative leaders to make strenuous efforts to place confines about

the legislative domains. But at the opening of the Civil War a mere

beginning had been made in the efforts to give definiteness of content to

due process of law.[26]


3. Cooley's Efforts to extend the Meaning of Due Process of Law. The vague

and indefinite meaning of the term "due process of law" which prevailed

prior to the Civil War was noted by Thomas M. Cooley.[27] After quoting a

few of the cases in which the term was discussed, Cooley fell back on the

general language of Daniel Webster in his argument in the Dartmouth College

Case.[28] In accord with the purpose of the author as stated in his preface,

to establish limitations upon the legislative authority independent of the

specific restrictions imposed by state constitutions,[29] Judge Cooley aimed

to give greater scope to the term "law of the land." For this purpose he

quoted approvingly the rhetorical statement of Justice Johnson, containing

the not uncommon inaccurate rendering of the meaning of the term "law of the

land": "after volumes spoken and written with a view to their exposition,

the good sense of mankind has at length settled down to this: that they were

intended to secure the individual from the arbitrary exercise of the powers

of government unrestrained by the established principles of private right

and distributive justice."[30] Referring to the frequent statements of the

justices that they could refuse to enforce a legislative act only when in

conflict with some express provision of the constitution, Cooley suggests

that "It does not follow, however, that in every case the courts, before

they can set aside a law as invalid, must be able to find in the

constitution some specific inhibition which has been disregarded, or some

express command which has been disobeyed." And then he indicates various

means by which legislative acts may be regarded as invalid, if contrary to

the general spirit, purposes, and principles of constitutional government.

In his volume on Constitutional Limitations and in his work on the Law of

Taxation he gave formulas for construing implied restrictions on

legislatures. Just as Coke interpolated his ideas of limitations on the King

and Parliament into common law decisions, so Cooley injected his own

theories of desirable limits on legislative action into his commentaries on

constitutional law. As the first attempt of an American text writer to

discuss due process of law Judge Cooley's treatise had an immediate effect

upon the decisions of the courts which were encouraged from many quarters to

set greater limits to the exercise of legislative powers.


4. Economic and Legal Bases for a Revival of Natural Law Thinking. The

doctrines of inalienable rights and of fundamental principles beyond

legislative control served a useful purpose in revolutionary times as a

higher law sanction for a revolt against constituted authority. Most

reformers in attacking an established order fall back on a higher law or

superior rules for guidance. These same doctrines suited well the

eighteenth-century laissez faire theories and thus were accepted by many who

with Thomas Jefferson thought "that government best which governed least."

But as a ground for revolution and as a check on all governmental powers

fundamental principles and inalienable rights were slowly being dissipated

by the absorbing tendencies of popular control of all manner of public

affairs characteristic of revolutionary and early state legislatures. It was

then that Alexander Hamilton, John Marshall, and Joseph Story revived the

higher law doctrine to check the legislative onslaughts on property,

contracts, and vested rights generally. The tide of Jacksonian democracy,

which brooked little interference with the voice of the people, narrowed

these incipient checks to a relatively small circle of governmental powers.

But firm believers in the necessity of limiting legislatures, such as

Chancellor Kent and Judge Cooley, soon took up the higher law philosophy for

the protection of vested rights and through judicial decisions as well as

their writings gave credence to this philosophy. It is a significant fact

that Kent and Story, who practically formulated an American common law, lost

no opportunity to advocate the protection of vested rights both

constitutionally and extra-constitutionally. Judge Cooley through his

Constitutional Limitations fostered the same view. Thus a triumvirate of

three great jurists and commentators was added to those conservative leaders

who saw relief from legislative radicalism only in courts strengthened in

their position by the authority to declare legislative acts void and aided

by both express and implied limitations on legislative powers.


Judge Cooley became the most effective advocate of superior principles

limiting all legislation. Reading the signs of the time favoring extensive

checks on what appeared to the conservative classes as unwarranted

interferences by legislatures in personal and private affairs, he laid down

as a dogma based on the higher law philosophy broad principles of implied

limitations on legislatures and executives for the protection of private and

personal rights. The decade in which Cooley's Constitutional Limitations

appeared, marked the confirmation of the practice of according judicial

protection to vested rights against legislative action, and of the

interpretation of implied limitations on legislatures as indispensable

features of American constitutional law.


The extension of the meaning and application of the term "due process of

law" illustrates concretely the effect of changing economic conditions and

political thought upon the courts and judicial opinions. Incipient efforts

to establish implied limits on legislatures through the vested rights

doctrine or through the due process of law clause, for a period of nearly

fifty years, made little headway against the common belief in and practice

of legislative supremacy, and the tendency to extend the scope of

legislative powers. The decades from 1830 to 1850 saw a notable movement in

the direction of the extension of democratic principles. It was in this

decade that many of the restrictions on suffrage were removed, and the

tendency was to adopt universal manhood suffrage. Terms of officers were

shortened, and the executive and judicial positions of the states were in

many instances made elective. The survivors of the old Federalists, who had

originated the vested rights doctrine, with their principles transformed

into a new Federalism, and conservative leaders generally, resisted this

movement towards democracy. Being unable to prevent its spread, they became

confirmed in the belief that some check had to be placed upon the seat of

popular control, the legislature.


Renewed activities on the part of leaders account in a measure at least for

the efforts to revise and extend the meaning of due process of law, from

1830 to 1842. Conservative opinion, however, was unable to place any special

checks upon the democratic movement[31] until after the panic of 1837, and

not then in a serious way until the great extension of the system of

internal improvements often supported by state aid had resulted in many

failures and in the repudiation of the debts of various states. The tendency

of the legislatures to vote the public funds for these private enterprises,

though as a rule supported by a preponderant public sentiment, and

frequently approved by an almost unanimous popular vote, increased the fears

of those who saw only ruin in the progressive principles of democracy;

especially was this true when the business projects failed and involved the

state and local governments in great financial losses. There was as a result

widespread discontent among the propertied classes who now demanded greater

checks upon the rule of the people. A more determined effort was made,

therefore, both by the placing of express limitations on legislatures in new

constitutions and by bringing pressure to bear upon the courts, to secure

checks upon legislative action which might affect private contract or

property rights or to prevent the majority from "an oppressive and reckless

use of power."[32] The doctrine of natural rights and the insistence upon

inherent limitations against arbitrary government, therefore, were again

reasserted, and renewed efforts were made to add to the content and

significance of the term "due process of law" to place some much-desired

limits to the rule of the majority.


In the extension of the meaning of due process of law and in the development

of the doctrine of protecting vested rights, an effective means was devised

to guide and restrict the rule of the majority in the efforts to extend

governmental regulation into the field of social and political affairs. New

and varied applications of the judicial check based on implied restrictions

were soon found to give legal sanction to conservative and reactionary

principles in state and federal governments. These principles, which were

championed by those who wished to check the tendency to regulate economic

and social life, were fostered by the economic doctrine of laissez faire,

the dominant philosophy of a pioneer individualism.[33] To support laissez

faire principles the requirements of public purpose for taxation and public

use for eminent domain were exalted into rigid standards whose application

rested primarily with the judicial conscience. Also, the doctrine that there

are "fundamental principles" beyond legislative authority was revived and

due process of law was applied with even greater latitude so as to render

invalid all governmental acts considered by judges to be unfair or

arbitrary. Continuing this method of interpretation of higher law principles

and adjusting it to meet some of the rapidly changing industrial conditions,

the courts found additional implied limitations upon legislative powers and

completed the main structure of the modern American concept of due process

of law in the period from 1870 to 1895.


Due process of law, then, was being transformed from its customary meaning

in England, where it referred to procedure in accordance with a regularly

enacted law, to a process which the courts regarded as "due" and, therefore,

reasonable, or not unfair -- a modernized version of natural law.


5. Due Process of Law made an Agency for the Maintenance of Reactionary

Tendencies. The appearance of Cooley's Constitutional Limitations along with

certain economic and political conditions about this time marked the

beginning of a new development in American constitutional law. However, the

main lines of this development were foreshadowed in the secure establishment

of the doctrine of judicial review of legislation, in the growing acceptance

of the idea of protecting vested rights under express and implied

constitutional limits, and, in the conversion of the "law of the land"

phrase into a general limitation on legislative powers. But the application

of all of the above principles had resulted in the courts' declaring void

but few laws and had affected to a relatively slight degree the trend of

political affairs. A judicial review of legislation differentiated in any

marked degree from a similar practice in other countries remained in large

part to be developed, though the courts of New York and Massachusetts had

taken some steps toward inaugurating a new point of view. This era was

characterized by renewed applications of the doctrine of protecting vested

rights and of the due process clause as a guarantee of individual rights.

Certain other implied restrictions on legislatures which had been slowly

emerging were now vigorously applied. These restrictions were evolved by

implications from the doctrine of natural and inalienable rights, from the

due process of law clause, and from the requirement that the property of the

individual could be taken under the power of eminent domain only with the

granting of just compensation.


Constitutions were, as a rule, silent as to the taking of property except

under the power of eminent domain and legislatures dealt rather freely with

property rights short of confiscation. But the courts, inclined to discover

additional limits on legislatures, beyond the express provisions of the

written constitutions, originated the doctrine of public purpose as a

requirement for taxation[34] and extended the application of the principle

of public use for eminent domain proceedings, whether constitutions included

this requirement or not.


The financial activities of the states prior to 1830 were quite limited,[35]

but a change came when the states began to embark in commercial enterprises

and particularly in the improvement of the system of transportation by

building canals, and when state indebtedness was very greatly increased. "In

catering to the clamor of the different interests of their respective

states, eighteen of them had authorized the issue of $108,223,808 of stock

in the three and one-half years between 1835 and 1838."[36] After millions

had been spent in building canals and in various other public improvements,

which were expected to bring large returns to the state treasuries, but

which instead involved all of the states in burdensome debts that increasing

taxation failed to meet, the propriety of lending the state's credit to

private corporations and of taxing for this purpose was questioned.[37]

Illinois, Indiana, Michigan, and other states incurred debts far beyond

their ability to pay.[38] In 1842, when the panic of 1837 had left the

country in a condition of economic paralysis, constitutional restrictions on

the states' power to borrow money and to lend its credit to private

corporations were adopted, and by 1857 most of the state constitutions

contained such provisions.[39]


But when another wave of prosperity came in the fifties, the way was still

open for the legislatures to authorize cities, counties, and towns upon a

popular vote to lend money to public and private enterprises and another

period of reckless borrowing followed. Money was freely voted and lavishly

spent on such projects as railways, canals, manufactories, banks, and

steamship lines.[40] When the question as to the right of the legislatures

to authorize localities to tax for these purposes was first raised, the

courts generally upheld the legislative power.[41] The panic of 1857 proved

as disastrous to the ventures of the localities as did the panic of 1837 to

the earlier speculative efforts of the states. A reaction followed which

seriously affected American constitutional law. Efforts were begun to place

greater restrictions on legislative authority in the state constitutions and

a persistent sentiment was fostered that the doctrine of implied limitations

ought to be applied to check the expenditure of public money for private or

quasi-public enterprises.[42]


The growth of this sentiment and its reflection in court decisions is

illustrated in the opinion of Chief Justice John F. Dillon of Iowa, who

advocated judicial construction of implied limits on legislatures. When the

act of the legislature authorizing local government units to aid in building

railroads came before the supreme court of Iowa, Chief Justice Dillon,

speaking for the majority of the court, reviewed the history of this

controversy in the states.[43] Referring to a previous decision holding such

an act valid,[44] he said the majority of the court there rendered a wrong

judgment and a most unfortunate mistake was made, for counties and cities

throughout the state, acting under the sanction of that decision, incurred

debts amounting to several millions of dollars, and in many cases, exceeding

their ability to pay. "There is no legislative power," said Judge Dillon,

"to endow municipal corporations with the authority to subscribe to the

stock of a railroad company and to levy a tax to pay therefor."[45]


On the basis of the inalienable rights clause of the bill of rights, the due

process of law and eminent domain provisions of the state constitution,

Chief Justice Dillon declared that the legislature cannot touch the property

of the citizen for a private use even if it does make compensation.[46] He

took occasion to condemn those who enunciated the principle of arbitrary and

despotic powers in legislatures,[47] and argued extensively for the doctrine

that the legislature can tax only for a public purpose.[48]


Justice Cole took issue with the majority of the court in his dissenting

opinion. He denied that the courts had any authority to declare an act of

the legislature void except when in direct conflict with the terms of the

written constitution. The courts of Iowa, in previous cases, he claimed, had

not denied power to the legislature to authorize cities and counties to

appropriate money to railroads but had held instead that the legislature had

not passed a law authorizing their issue. This issue, he continued, had been

before the courts in at least twenty-one other states, and in every instance

the legislative power had been affirmed. "If the views of the majority are

sound," said he, "then it is certainly true that our constitution does not

define the powers of the respective departments of our government, but

leaves them to the necessarily uncertain and ever-changing measurement of

judicial discretion."[49]


Though Judge Dillon's opinion ran counter to the decisions of the highest

courts in more than twenty states and was repudiated as an unsound

constitutional doctrine by the Supreme Court of the United States,[50] he

expressed the confident conviction that the reaction under way would soon

lead to the approval of his views.


The contention that there could be no taxation for a private purpose under

the conditions announced by Judge Dillon was not regarded as a principle of

constitutional interpretation in the early part of the nineteenth

century[51] but the courts were gradually prevailed on to apply a principle

to taxation somewhat similar to that adopted for eminent domain proceedings.


That taxation could be for a public purpose only seems to have been

announced particularly in the railway aid and military bounty cases.[52]

Prior to 1870, the doctrine was generally based, not upon any provision of

the constitution, but upon an extra-constitutional basis, falling back upon

the theory of natural rights and the inherent limitations on

legislatures.[53] Judge Cooley stated as a principle of law the suggestion

by the justices in a few state cases that


    Taxation having for its only legitimate object the raising of
    money for public purposes, and the proper needs of
    government, the exaction of moneys from the citizens for
    other purposes is not a proper exercise of this power and
    must therefore be unauthorized.... An unlimited power to
    make any and everything lawful which the legislature might
    see fit to call taxation would be, when plainly stated, an
    unlimited power to plunder the citizen.


To check such extortion, Judge Cooley suggested that the courts should

interfere.[54] Citations to and approval of this dogmatic statement soon

appeared in the opinions of the state courts holding that to tax for a

private purpose was not among the powers conferred upon the legislature.[55]


Though Judge Dillon's theory of implied limitations was repudiated in Iowa

and in a number of decisions by the United States Supreme Court, and though

slow progress was made in construing an implied limit on the taxing power by

a public purpose principle, Cooley did not hesitate to put his own theories

into practice. Two years after the appearance of his Constitutional

Limitations, as justice of the supreme court of Michigan, he reiterated the

views of his text. Holding an act of the legislature void which authorized

cities and towns to tax for the purpose of purchasing stock in railway

companies, he wrote:


    It is conceded, nevertheless, that there are certain limitations
    upon this power, not prescribed in express terms by any
    constitutional provision, but inherent in the subject itself,
    which attend its exercise under all circumstances, and which
    are as inflexible and absolute in their restraints as if directly
    imposed in the most positive form of words.[56]


Three fundamental maxims of taxation were laid down as of universal

application, of which public purpose was placed first. It is only when these

maxims are observed, thought Justice Cooley, that "the legislative

department is exercising an authority over the subject which it has received

from the people."[57]


From 1870 to 1880 constitutional provisions were enacted which prevented

cities, counties, and towns from granting aid to private enterprises and

from levying taxes for such purposes.[58] The decision of Justice Cooley

accomplished the object of a constitutional provision against a state

subsidy in Michigan. But the public purpose principle as an implied

limitation had much greater effect on future legislative policies.

Originally defined as a general and universal principle of taxation, Cooley

developed the principle with considerable detail in his work on the Law of

Taxation, which was published in 1879.[59]


"All definitions of taxation," he contended, "imply that it is to be imposed

only for public purposes, and whatever difference of opinion may exist

regarding the admissibility of taxation in particular cases, the fundamental

requirement, that the purpose must be public, will be conceded on all

sides."[60[


The determination in the first instance of what are public purposes devolves

upon the legislative department but the decision of the legislative

department is not conclusive, for "an unlimited power in the legislature to

make any and everything lawful which it might see fit to call taxation,

would, when plainly stated, be an unlimited power to plunder the citizen."

To support this doctrine, Cooley cited a few decisions of the courts of

Pennsylvania, Massachusetts, and Maine, with his own decision in People v.

Salem and the views of Judge Dillon in Hanson v. Vernon.[61] Then follows an

extensive quotation from the dictum of Justice Miller in the case of Loan

Association v. Topeka.[62]


The change in the attitude of the courts in the process of developing

implied limitations on legislative authority is shown clearly in New York,

where the courts rejected the principle that taxes must be for a public

purpose only,[63] but twenty years later, following the reasoning of

Chancellor Kent and of Judge Cooley, definitely adopted the public purpose

principle as a limitation upon the taxing power of the legislature.[64]


By 1880 the various ramifications of the extensive doctrine of public

purpose as a requirement for taxation were clearly formulated and henceforth

the courts followed Cooley and Dillon and gradually added distinctions which

made of public purpose with respect to taxation one of the most effective

implied limitations on legislative powers.[65]


Constitutions rather generally placed restrictions on the exercise of

eminent domain, such as the requirement of public use and just compensation.

But independent of such constitutional provisions and supplementary thereto

arose a judicially construed limitation on such proceedings.


Chancellor Kent, who was one of the leaders in formulating the doctrine of

protecting vested rights by means of implied restrictions on legislatures,

it was observed, was among the first to state the special limitation as to

the purpose of the power of eminent domain. In the case of Gardner v.

Newburgh,[66] he held that in the absence of a constitutional provision for

the purpose compensation was due the owner for property taken or damaged,

and that the power of eminent domain could be exercised for public purposes

only. Later he confirmed these views in his Commentaries. When New York

adopted the constitution of 1821, a provision requiring just compensation

and a public purpose was inserted as one of the requisites for eminent

domain proceedings.[67]


About a decade later, the New York courts, considering a statute enacted

more than twenty years earlier, were called upon to decide whether property

could be condemned in excess of the amount actually needed for public

purposes. It was observed that "the constitution, by authorizing the

appropriation of private property to public use, impliedly declares that

private property shall not be taken from one and applied to the use of

another. It is in violation of natural right, and if not a violation of the

letter of the constitution, it is of its spirit, and cannot be

supported."[68] Thus the practice of excess condemnation of property beyond

the actual requirements for the public needs was held to be inhibited

through implication from the eminent domain clauses of the state

constitutions.[69] For many years no further attempts were made to authorize

excess condemnation of property and then adverse decisions compelled the

states to resort to the amending process.[70]


Kent's doctrines and the theories of the New York justices had slight effect

upon eminent domain proceedings, prior to 1870. Compensation was confined as

a requirement by the courts to cases of actual taking, including all direct

physical injuries to property,[71] and, in determining the value of the land

actually taken, it was held that elements of special benefit to the part of

the land not taken could be set off against the value of the part taken.[72]

With the return to conservative doctrines which followed the Civil War

courts began to insist that compensation must be given for damages resulting

from a taking as well as for the value of the land actually taken, that it

was improper to set off special benefits to the land not taken, and to

review with careful scrutiny what the legislatures declared to be a public

use.[73]


Cooley again gave effective expression to Kent's views and to the principles

stated somewhat provisionally by some state supreme court justices when he

wrote:


    There is no rule or principle known to our system under
    which private property can be taken from one man and
    transferred to another for the private use and benefit of such
    other person, whether by general laws or special enactment.
    The purpose must be public, and must have reference to the
    needs of the government. No reason of general policy will
    be sufficient to protect such transfers where they operate
    upon existing vested rights.[74]


This dogmatic statement by one who frankly believed in judicial construction

of implied limitations on legislatures, was soon reflected in the opinions

of state and federal justices.


An implied limitation, thus first formulated by the state courts, was

subsequently adopted by the Supreme Court, when it was held that "the taking

by a state of private property of one person or corporation without the

owner's consent, for private use of another, is not due process of law, and

is a violation of the Fourteenth Amendment."[75] Justice Harlan declared

that the necessity for compensation for property taken for a public use was

"an affirmance of the great doctrine established by the common law for the

protection of private property. It is founded in natural equity, and is laid

down by jurists as a principle of universal law. Indeed, in a free

government, almost all other rights become worthless if the government

possesses the uncontrollable power over the private fortune of the every-day

citizen."[76]


State and federal courts combined in assuming that the constitutional

prohibitions against the taking of private property through eminent domain

proceedings except for public purposes and without just compensation

operated, by necessary implication to prevent the taking of private

property for private use, with or without compensation. And the

limitations thus placed upon eminent domain through the adoption of the

public use principle and its acceptance as one of the features of the due

process clause, added materially to the extent of the vested rights placed

beyond legislative control.[77]


The extensive application of public purpose or public use as a limitation

upon legislative powers, was therefore applied both to taxation and to

eminent domain. As in the case of other implied limitations, the public

purpose doctrine, so far as the federal law is concerned, was absorbed in

the due process of law requirement. In defining the term "due process of

law" in relation to the protection of property rights, Justice Brewer,

following the opinion of Justice Miller,[78] held that "this power to take

private property reaches back of all constitutional provisions; and it seems

to have been considered a settled principle of universal law that the right

to compensation is an incident to the exercise of that power."[79] This

principle is now regarded as one of the fundamental requirements of due

process of law under the Fifth Amendment, though it rests now as it always

has both upon express constitutional provisions and upon an

extra-constitutional basis, or upon limitations growing out "of the

essential nature of all free governments."[80]


When the conservative reaction was at its height numerous express

constitutional restrictions upon the powers of state legislatures to take

private property either by taxation or by eminent domain were adopted.

But to the leaders of this reaction it was more important to have a flexible

standard for the courts to use as a test of the validity of new legislative

projects affecting private rights of property. The doctrines of public use

and public purpose filled a gap in which the former doctrine of protecting

vested rights by construing implied limitations on legislatures and the

interpretation of the concept "due process of law" as a general restriction

on legislative powers had so far failed to give the desired protection.


Foreign countries likewise require, as a rule, that the power of the

expropriation of private property be exercised only for a public use. The

determination of what is for a public use rests with the legislature,

however, and there is generally no review of this determination by the

courts. It is usual also to have the requirement that just compensation be

awarded and the intervention of the judiciary becomes legitimate only when

it comes to fixing the amount of compensation.[81] The French Civil Code[82]

contains a representative provision that no one's property shall be taken

except for a public use, and for a just and preliminary indemnity. In

practice the legislature defines what is for a public use[83] and the

meaning of the term has been considerably extended by a recent act. The

legislature has also limited the powers of the jury or committee of award in

determining the compensation to be awarded.[84]


"The whole learning as to eminent domain," says Justice Riddell, "is of no

interest in Canada. The legislature may, indeed, direct compensation to be

paid; but that is in no sense necessary."[85] But in Canada as in England,

where the legislatures can, if they so choose, take private property without

compensation, such power is very seldom exercised. It was the result of a

long period of the growth of legal ideas and of a combination of

extraordinary economic and political conditions that turned American

constitutional law in this field along lines different from the prevailing

practice of the world.


The federal Constitution and a number of early state constitutions were

formed and put into effect on the wave of a conservative reaction from the

radical and democratic doctrines of the revolutionary period.[86] When the

Federalist party became the leader of this conservative movement it

championed the doctrine of judicial review of legislative enactments, the

theory of protecting vested rights both by express and implied limitations

on legislatures, and the principle of placing implied limitations on

legislatures to protect individual rights and to preserve minority

privileges as against the dangers of majority rule. The wave of Jeffersonian

democracy removed some of the restrictions which were in process of

formation under Federalist auspices and others were either eliminated or

modified when the frontier democracy of the West triumphed in the

inauguration of the Jacksonian era.[87] But the conservative spirit as

fostered by such men as Alexander Hamilton, John Marshall, Joseph Story,

Chancellor Kent, and Daniel Webster, never ceased to have a powerful and

directive influence on American political affairs. From 1830 to 1850, when

democratic and liberal principles and practices seemed to be dominant in

American life, a new federalism and a new conservatism were in their

formative stage. It was at this time that a few justices revived the natural

law doctrines of European political philosophers and the higher law notions

of the Declaration of Independence and of the bills of rights of state

constitutions. Following leaders who advocated implied limits on legislative

powers, such as Coke, Kent, and Story, these judges, originally through

dicta, prepared a program for modern conservative policies and reactionary

tendencies, fostered, as was the earlier movement, on the conviction that

majority rule is dangerous and that representative assemblies are not to be

trusted. Not until the results of democratic rule along economic and

financial lines had turned out disastrously in the panics of 1837 and 1857

and in a continuous process of wasteful and extravagant expenditures which

the electorate had, as a rule, approved, did the exponents of the second

conservative reaction secure much of a following. When the unsettled

economic conditions and the high prices of the Civil War period, combined

with the speculative movement that followed, brought another disastrous

panic in 1873, public sentiment was prepared, not only to place more

definite express constitutional restrictions on legislatures, but also to

accept the now well-formulated doctrine of judicially construed implied

limitations on legislative powers,[88] favorable to individual privileges

and to property rights.


It was the background of inalienable rights which was used to sanction

Justice Cooley's dictum soon to be adopted as a fundamental principle of

constitutional interpretation, namely, "that there are on all sides definite

limitations which circumscribe the legislative authority, aside from the

specific restrictions which the people impose by their constitutions."

Justices Dillon, Miller, and Cooley gave credence to the belief that implied

limits must be placed on legislatures in respect to the control over

property and contracts and that the sanction for these limits may, if

necessary, be founded on the inalienable rights clause of the bill of

rights. There is a noteworthy similarity between the reasoning of these

justices and that of Justice Chase in Calder v. Bull when he first advocated

the doctrine of implied limitations based upon natural rights and upon the

principles of a free republican government. But suggestions were already at

hand to direct the natural rights thinking into other channels and to give

to it a semblance of constitutional sanctity in the emerging meaning of "due

process of law." Before the transition was made there was a recurrence to

the principles of the Declaration of Independence as a sanction for natural

rights which were inalienable.


The Supreme Court of the United States in a gradual change of opinion from

1873 to 1895 led the conservative movement, and through its prestige gave it

an added impetus in the state courts. When the peculiar economic and

political conditions of the United States were favorable to the laissez

faire and individualistic theories of Adam Smith and Ricardo which were

prevalent in England and in America in the eighteenth and early nineteenth

centuries, Justices Field and Peckham, inclined toward democratic political

principles, joined with the proponents of conservative policies, such as

Justices Brewer and Harlan, to establish even greater limits on the role of

legislative action than the most extreme advocates of the principles of the

original Federalism could have imagined.[89] It is necessary then to

consider the adoption of the principles of conservatism and reaction by the

federal courts and the further extension of these principles by the state

courts.[90]




1. For a more extensive account see W. S. McKechnie, Magna Carta (New York,

1915); C. H. McIlwain, "Due Process of Law in Magna Carta," Columbia Law

Review, XIV (January, 1914), 27; Rodney L. Mott, Due Process of Law

(Indianapolis, 1926); Malden, Magna Carta Commemoration Essays (London,

1917).


2. Coke's Institutes, II, 45-50; McIlwain, The Sigh Court of Parliament and

its Supremacy, pp. 31 ff.; Justice Curtis in Murray's Lessee v. Hoboken Land

and Improvement Co., 18 How. 272, 276 (1855). For exaggerated claims

regarding the significance of Magna Carta as a fundamental law designed to

secure justice to all, consult Mott, op. cit., chap. 3.


3. "No subject shall be arrested, imprisoned, despoiled, or deprived of his

property, immunities or privileges, put out of the protection of the law,

exiled, or deprived of his life, liberty, or property but by the judgment

of his peers or the law of the land." Declaration of Rights, art. XII.


4. Cf. Edward S. Corwin, "The Doctrine of Due Process of Law before the

Civil War," Harvard Law Review, XXIV (March, 1911), 366, 370 ff. Story in

his Commentaries on the Constitution, published in 1833, gave the current

interpretation of the phrase "due process" that it "affirms the right of

trial according to the process and proceedings of the common law." Sec.

1789.


5. Charles M. Hough, "Due Process of Law -- Today," Harv. Law Rev., XXXII

(January, 1919), 218, 222 ff. Justice Hough says: "That all men of that day

had no conception of due process, other than a summary description of a

fairly tried action at law, is not asserted, but I do submit that reports

before the Civil War yield small evidence that there was any professional

conviction that it was more than that"; see also Francis W. Bird, "The

Evolution of Due Process of Law in the Decisions of the United States

Supreme Court," Col. Law Rev., XIII (January, 1913), 37, 44 ff.


6. State v. -- , 1 Hay. (N. Car.) 29, 31 (1794); per legem terrae. Attorney

General Haywood argued, was not intended "to restrain the legislature from

making the law of the land, but a declaration only that the people are to be

governed by no other than the law of the land." Cf. also Mayo v. Wilson, 1

N. H. 53 (1817), in which Chief Justice Richardson held that an arrest

without warrant had always been considered due process of law in England and

that "the makers of the constitution having adopted a phrase from Magna

Carta, the meaning of which in that instrument was so well known, must have

intended to have used it in the same sense in which it has always been

understood to have been used there." 56, 57. For a different interpretation

see argument in Trustees of the University v. Foy, 1 Murphy (N. Car., 1805)

58, 73 and opinion of Judge Locke.


7. Referring to the moral and emotional values of Magna Carta which appealed

to the popular imagination, McKechnie finds that "fortified as it had been

by the veneration of ages, it became a strongly entrenched position that the

enemies of arbitrary government could safely hold." "Magna Carta

(1215-1915)," Malden, Commemoration Essays, pp. 20, 21. See also Sir Paul

Vinogradoff, "Magna Carta Chapter 39," Commemoration Essays, p. 85; C. H.

McIlwain, "Due Process of Law in Magna Carta," Col. Law Rev., XIV (January,

1914), 26; G. B. Adams, Origin of the English Constitution (New Haven,

1920), pp. 242 ff.


8. Starting with the assumption that somewhat of the divine essence was

breathed into "due process of law" and that there is here involved

"phraseology of the purest gold mined under the stress of heated

constitutional crises, refined by the fire of violent revolutions, proved

by the acid test of centuries of struggle," a recent author sets out to

prove that due process of law was always designed to keep government from

straying into paths of arbitrariness and injustice. Thus imbued with the

will to believe, he finds, contrary to the weight of evidence and to the

mature judgments of both English and American scholars, that the phrase "the

law of the land" was from the beginning intended as a restraint on the

legislature as well as on the executive power, that a considerable number of

acts were declared void in England because contrary to Magna Carta as the

fundamental law, and that there was "a steady stream of dicta that statutes

which were contrary to common right and reason, the law of nature or the

common law were unenforceable." Mott, op. cit., pp. 42-48, 123, 135, 142,

143.


It is surprising to find how few precedents of this kind investigators have

discovered and these were given undue weight by those who desired to find

legal limits on royal authority. But Dr. Mott, feeling sure that Englishmen

prior to the American Revolution were well aware and confident that due

process of law was designed to prevent arbitrary governmental action, is

surprised to discover that no discussion of this device to keep government

in the paths of reason and of justice is to be found in the Federal

Convention at Philadelphia or in the debates on the constitution in the

states. Madison is credited with the assertion that due process of law as

inserted in the Fifth Amendment of the federal Constitution was intended to

limit the legislature but nearly a hundred years elapsed before this was

accepted by the courts. Again there was very little discussion of the

meaning of due process of law when this clause was inserted in the

Fourteenth Amendment as an extra guarantee to render effective the phrase

"equal protection of the laws." Since no one knew what due process of law

meant, it is concluded that it must have been intended to protect all

liberties. Ibid., p. 165.


The majority of text writers, it is noted, followed Justice Story in

defining due process of law as a protection to the criminal from arbitrary

arrest and imprisonment. With the exception of the opinions of Pomeroy and

Cooley in 1868, until the beginning of the twentieth century, authors dealt

only with the procedural phases of due process of law. Cooley is credited

with emphasizing the application of due process of law to taxation in 1876.

With such slow recognition of the significance of this term by statesmen,

text writers, and the public generally, how has due process of law come to

take a central place in American constitutional law? It was the "uncanny

intuition" of the justices in state and federal courts, we are told, which

discovered a new rôle for due process of law. Searching for "the inherent

elements of justice" applicable to all situations the judges extracted from

the vague terms of written charters a "latent and unsuspected" meaning which

conservatives and reactionaries alike were seeking -- an effective device to

check popular lawmaking and to resist arbitrary administrative procedure.

But even the justices were dilatory in finding the hidden meaning of due

process of law. Only a few of the state justices ventured to suggest

implications of the term beyond its well-known procedural implications.


9. A. N. Holcombe, State Government in the United States (New York, 1916),

pp. 47 ff.


10. For a suggestive analysis of the inconsistent positions taken by the

justices on this issue, consult Robert P. Reeder, "Constitutional and

Extra-Constitutional Restraints," University of Pennsylvania Law Review, LXI

(May, 1913), 441.


11. 3 Dallas 398 (1798).


12. 4 Conn. 209 (1822).


13. 7 Johns. 477 (1811).


14. North Carolina v. Foy, 2 Hay 310, 312; 5 N. Car. 57, 63 (1804). To the

contention that the law of the land clause of the bill of rights did not

impose restrictions on the legislature, Justice Locke replied: "It is

evident the framers of the Constitution intended the provision as a

restraint upon some branch of the government, either the executive,

legislative, or judicial. To suppose it applicable to the executive would be

absurd on account of the limited powers conferred on that officer; and from

the subjects enumerated in that clause, no danger could be apprehended from

the executive department, that being entrusted with the exercise of no

powers by which the principles thereby intended to be secured could be

affected. To apply it to the judiciary would, if possible, be still more

idle, if the legislature can make the 'law of the land.' For the judiciary

are only to expound and enforce the law, and have no discretionary powers

enabling them to judge of the propriety or impropriety of laws.


They are bound, whether agreeable to their ideas of justice or not, to carry

into effect the acts of the legislature as far as they are binding or do not

contravene the Constitution. If, then, this clause is applicable to the

legislature alone, and was intended as a restraint on their acts (and to

presume otherwise is to render this article a dead letter), let us next

inquire what will be the operation which this clause will or ought to have

on the present question. It seems to us to warrant a belief that members of

a corporation as well as individuals shall not be so deprived of their

liberties or properties, unless by a trial by jury in a court of justice,

according to the known and established rules of decision derived from the

common law and such acts of the legislature as are consistent with the

Constitution."


Due process of law was held to require, for the transfer of a freehold, a

trial by jury in Bowman v. Middleton, 1 Bay (S. Car.) 252 (1792), and an act

of the North Carolina legislature was held void for attempting to prevent a

judicial settlement of property rights. Bayard v. Singleton, 1 Martin 48

(1787).


See comments of Justice Waties by way of dictum giving a similar

interpretation of lex terrae and suggesting that this phrase was intended

"to become an effectual bar to the innovations of the legislature." Zylstra

v. Corporation of Charleston, 1 Bay 382, 392 (1794).


15. For more than thirty years after due process of law was introduced into

the state constitutions there were few cases interpreting the phrase and no

attempt to define it. See Mott, op. cit., p. 192.


16. Holden v. James, 11 Mass. 396, 405.


17. Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 4 Wheat. 518, 581 (1819). Webster

observed:


"By the law of the land is most clearly intended the general law; a law

which hears before it condemns, which proceeds upon inquiry, and renders

judgment only after trial. The meaning is, that every citizen shall hold his

life, liberty, property, and immunities, under the protection of the general

rules which govern society. Everything which may pass under the form of an

enactment, is not, therefore, to be considered the law of the land."


18. In Bank of State v. Cooper, Justice Green said: "Constitutions are only

intended to secure the rights of the minorities.... If the law be general in

its operation, affecting all alike, the minority are safe, because the

majority, who make the law, are operated on by it equally with the others."

2 Yerg. (Tenn.) 509, 605, 606 (1831). See also Jones' Heirs v. Perry, 10

Yerg. 58, 71, 72 (1836). For dicta in early cases to the effect that due

process of law was intended to limit legislative action, see Mott, op. cit.,

pp. 192 ff.


Chief Justice Skinner, holding void an act releasing a debtor imprisoned on

execution, said: "An act conferring upon any one citizen privileges to the

prejudice of another, and which is not applicable to others, in like

circumstances ... does not enter into the idea of municipal law, having no

relation to the community in general." Ward v. Barnard, 1 Aikens (Vt.) 120,

128 (1825). See reference to the fact that many acts of this kind had been

passed by the legislature and had been enforced without protests. Justice

Catron, in upholding a special act of the legislature prescribing the mode

by which holders of notes might on refusal to pay same recover judgment,

referred to the law of the land as requiring "a general public law, equally

binding upon every member of the community under similar circumstances." Van

Zandt v. Waddell, 2 Yerg. (Tenn.) 260, 270, 271 (1829); also. Wally v.

Kennedy, 2 Yerg. 554, 557 (1831) and Dale "Implied Limitations upon

Legislative Powers," American Bar Association Reports, XXIV (1901), 294,

315-319.


19. Hoke v. Henderson, 15 N. Car. 1, 15 (1833); also comments of Justice

Peck in Officer v. Young, 5 Yerg. 320, 321 (1833).


20. Bank of State v. Cooper, 2 Yerg. 599, 603 (1831). "There are," said

Justice Green, "eternal principles of justice which no government has a

right to disregard. It does not follow, therefore, because there may be no

restriction in the constitution prohibiting a particular act of the

legislature, that such act is therefore constitutional. Some acts, although

not expressly forbidden, may be against the plain and obvious dictates of

reason. 'The common law,' says Lord Coke [8 Coke, 118], 'adjudgeth a statute

so far void.'"


The Alabama court, holding void an act prescribing for public officers and

attorneys an oath against duelling, said that the declaration of rights was

the governing and controlling feature of the constitution and all powers of

the legislature were to be expounded and their operation extended or

restrained with reference to it. Quoting the provision of the bill of

rights that "This enumeration of certain rights shall not be construed to

deny or disparage others retained by the people; and to guard against any

encroachment on the rights retained, or any transgression of the high powers

herein delegated, we declare, that every thing in this article is excepted

out of the general powers of government, and shall forever remain inviolate,

and that all laws contrary thereto are void," Justice Ormond claimed that by

this language the courts were authorized to declare void any act which was

repugnant to natural justice and equity. Hence, "any act of the legislature

which violates any of these asserted rights, or which intrenches on any of

these great principles of civil liberty, or the inherent rights of man,

though not enumerated, shall be void." In re Dorsey, 7 Porter (Ala.) 293,

377, 378 (1838). Due process of law was intended "as a safeguard against the

encroachment upon these inherent rights of the people by Congress or the

state legislatures." Justice Dickerson in State v. Doherty, 60 Me. 504, 509

(1872).


21. The "law of the land" means "the common law and the statute law existing

in this state at the adoption of our constitution. Altogether they

constitute the body of law, prescribing the course of justice to which a

free man is to be considered amenable, in all time to come." Justice O'Neall

in State v. Simons, 2 Spears 761, 767 (1844); also Justice Bronson in Taylor

v. Porter, 4 Hill 140, 146 (1843).


22. Justice Gilchrist in Concord R. R. Co. v. Greeley, 17 N. H. 47, 54

(1845); see also Sill v. Coming, 15 N. Y. 297, 303 (1857).


23. White v. White, 5 Barb. 474, 484, 485 (1849).


24. Wynehamer v. New York, 13 N. Y. 378 (1856), Justice Comstock, profiting

by the opinions of Chief Justice Bronson in Taylor v. Porter and Chief

Justice Ruffin in Hoke v. Henderson, said: "The better and larger definition

of due process of law is, that it means law in its regular course of

administration through courts of justice.... It is plain, therefore, both

upon principle and authority, that these constitutional safeguards, in all

cases, require a judicial investigation, not to be governed by a law

specially enacted to take away and destroy existing rights, but confined to

the question whether, under the pre-existing rule of conduct, the right in

controversy has been lawfully acquired and is lawfully possessed." Ibid.,

395. See dissenting opinions of Justices T. A. Johnson, Wright, and

Mitchell, who objected to setting limits to legislative power "upon any

fanciful theory of higher law or first principles of natural right outside

of the constitution." Ibid., 453.


25. Taylor v. Porter, 4 Hill 140 (1843); Wynehamer 11. State, 13 N. Y. 378

(1856). When the legislature of Pennsylvania passed an act to order a sale

of property contrary to the terms of a will, the supreme court held the act

invalid. Referring to the "law of the land" provision, Justice Coulter said,

"these clauses address themselves to the common sense of the people, and

ought not to be filed away by legal subtleties. They have their foundations

in natural justice; and, without their pervading efficacy, other rights

would be useless.... If property is subject to the caprice of an annual

assemblage of legislators acting tumultuously, and without rule or

precedent, and without hearing the party, stability in property will cease,

and justice be at an end." Ervin's Appeal, 16 Penn. St. 256, 263 (1851).


26. Cf. dictum of Justice Jenkins that the principle of implied limitations

was applicable in the interpretation of legislative powers under the

Southern Confederacy. Jeffers v. Fair, 33 Ga. 347, 367 (1862).


27. Cf. the first edition of his work on Constitutional Limitations (1868),

p. 353.


28. Cf supra, p 112.


29. The avowed object of rendering aid in the development of implied

limitations on legislatures was frankly stated by Cooley in the preface to

the first edition: "In these pages the author has faithfully endeavored to

state the law as it has been settled by the authorities, rather than to

present his own views. At the same time he will not attempt to deny -- what

will probably be sufficiently apparent -- that he has written in full

sympathy with all those restraints which the caution of the fathers has

imposed upon the exercise of the powers of government, and with greater

faith in the checks and balances of our republican system, and in correct

conclusions by the general public sentiment, than in a judicious, prudent,

and just exercise of unbridled authority by any one man or body of men,

whether sitting as a legislature or as a court. In this sympathy and faith

he has written of jury trial and the other safeguards to personal liberty,

of liberty of the press, and of vested rights; and he has also endeavored to

point out that there are on all sides definite limitations which

circumscribe the legislative authority, aside from the specific restrictions

which the people impose by their constitutions," Constitutional Limitations

(1st ed.), p. iv. (Italics by the writer.)


30. Bank of Columbia v. Oakley, 4 Wheat. 235, 244 (1819).


31. "The wishes and opinions of the minority must yield to those of the

majority," said Chief Justice Marshall in Talbot v. Dent, 9 B. Mon. (Ky.)

526, 537 (1849) Cf. for similar opinions Goddin v. Crump, etc., 8 Leigh

(Va.) 120 (1837), and the City of Bridgeport v. Housatonic Railroad Co., 15

Conn. 475 (1843).


32. C. J. Bigelow in Hood v. Lynn, 1 Allen (Mass.) 103, 104 (1861). A

representative example of this method of reasoning was the frank declaration

of Justice Butler, who in reviewing a retrospective law and finding no

inhibition in the constitution on this type of enactment said: "But the

power of the legislature in this respect is not unlimited. They cannot

entirely disregard the fundamental principles of the social compact. Those

principles underlie all legislation, irrespective of constitutional

restraints, and if the act in question is a clear violation of them, it is

our duty to hold it abortive and void." Though the act in question was

upheld, the dictum in Goshen v. Stonington was approved as the settled

doctrine of the court. Welch v. Wadsworth, 30 Conn. 149, 155 (1861).


33. The supreme court of Maine, requested to give an advisory opinion

whether the legislature could pass laws enabling towns, by gifts of money,

to assist individuals or corporations to engage in manufacturing, answered

in the negative. Among the provisions of the constitution cited to sustain

this conclusion were: the natural rights clause of the declaration of

rights, the eminent domain provision, and the law of the land restriction.

As these provisions did not directly inhibit such an act the justices

throughout their opinion indicated their adherence to the doctrine that "the

less the state interferes with industry, the less it directs and selects the

channels of enterprise, the better." It is this philosophy underlying the

reasoning of judges which has frequently prevented local communities from

engaging in quasi-public enterprises. In re Opinion of Justices, 58 Me. 590,

598 (1871).


34. After the middle of the nineteenth century justices continued to hold

that due-process of law had no relation to the power of taxation. People v.

Brooklyn, 4 N. Y. 419, 423 (1857); Johnson v. Stark, 24 Ill. 75, 86 (1860);

People 11. Smith, 21 N. Y. 595, 598, 599 (1860). For additional citations

see Mott, op. cit., p. 438.


35. Horace Secrist, An Economic Analysis of the Constitutional Restrictions

upon Public Expenditures (University of Wisconsin, Economics and Political

Science Series), VIII, 13.


36. Ibid., p. 21. Cf. J. B. McMaster, History of the People of the United

States, XI, 92, as to the wild speculation in railroad securities from 1834

to 1837.


37. Secrist, op. cit., p. 28.


38. McMaster, op. cit., 34.


39. Ibid., p 54.


40. McMaster, op cit., VIII, 285 ff.


41. See Stein v. Mayor, Aldermen, etc. of Mobile, 24 Ala. 501 (1854);

Dubuque Co. v. Dubuque and Pacific Ry. Co., 4 Greene (Ia.) 1 (1853); Gelpcke

v. City of Dubuque, 1 Wall. 175 (1863); Town of Guilford v. Supervisors of

Chenango Co., 13 N. Y. 143 (1855); Sharpless v. Mayor of Philadelphia, 21

Pa. St. 147 (1853); Lawson v. The Milwaukee and Northern Ry. Co., 30 Wis.

597 (1872); Commissioners of Leavenworth Co. 11. Miller, 7 Kan. 479 (1871),

and dissent of Justice Brewer in State v. Nemaha Co., 7 Kan. 542 (1871); and

extensive list of cases cited in 20 Mich. 465. Cf. also Railroad Co. v.

County of Otoe, 16 Wall. 667 (1872) and Township of Pine Grove v Talcott, 19

Wall. 666 (1873).


42. Evidence of this sentiment appears in the observations of the justices

in Iowa in holding invalid a legislative act amending a city charter so as

to include for purposes of taxation a large tract of farm land. There must

be, said the court, some limits to the power to tax, and as a basis for

these limits the distinction was suggested between a just tax and that which

is palpably not a tax. Morford v. Unger, 8 Ia. 82, 91 (1859). Justice Leonard

thought, in rendering a similar decision, that from the eminent domain

provision "we may safely imply the constitutional prohibition against the

arbitrary taking of private property for private use without any

compensation." Wells v. City of Weston, 22 Mo. 385, 388 (1856).


43. Hanson v. Vemon, 27 Ia. 28 (1869).


44. Dubuque County v. Dubuque and Pacific Ry. Co., 4 Greene 1 (1853). For

cases reviewing this decision, see State, etc. v. Wapello Co., 13 Ia. 388

(1862) and McClure v. Owen, 26 Ia. 243 (1868).


45. Ibid., 33, 34.


46. Hanson v. Vemon, 27 Ia. 28, 43. See also Bankhead v. Brown, 25 Ia. 540,

545 (1868), where Chief Justice Dillon, reviewing proceedings to establish a

private road, maintained that the constitutional limitation against taking

private property for public use without just compensation "prohibits by

implication, the taking of private property for any private use whatever,

without the consent of the owner."


47. Cf. Eakin v. Raub, 12 Serg. & R. (Penna.) 344 (1825), dissenting opinion

of Justice Gibson; and Sharpless Case, 21 Penna. St. 147 (1853).


48. 27 Ia. 46 ff. See also opinions of Justice Wright and Justice Beck.

"There is," said Justice Beck, "as it were, back of the written

constitution, an unwritten constitution, if I may use the expression, which

guarantees and well protects all the absolute rights of the people." Ibid.,

73. See reversal of this case, Stewart v. Supervisors of Polk Co., 30 Ia. 9

(1870), after the legislature had re-enacted the former law with certain

changes.


49. Hanson v. Vernon, 27 Ia. 28 ff. For list of cases in other states, see

ibid., 81. In the first edition of his work on Municipal Corporations,

published in 1872, Judge Dillon admitted that "a long and almost unbroken

line of judicial decisions in the courts of most of the states has

established the principle that, in the absence of special restrictive

constitutional provisions, it is competent for the legislature to authorize

a municipal or public corporation to aid ... the construction of railways."

Citing his own opinion in Hanson v. Vernon, and that of Cooley in People v.

Salem, he observed, "the judgments affirming the existence of the power have

generally met with strong judicial dissent and with much professional

disapproval, and experience has demonstrated that the exercise of it has

been productive of bad results." Secs. 104, 105. Cf. note summarizing the

conclusions of numerous decisions. In the preface to this work Dillon

indicates his disapproval of the doctrines embodied in decisions favoring

such powers in the legislatures. See Whiting v. Sheboygan and Fond du Lac

Railway Co., 25 Wis. 167 (1869-70), where Chief Justice Dixon, holding a

similar statute void, cited and approved the reasoning of Dillon. For

decision contra, cf. Lawson v. Milwaukee and Northern Railway Co., 30 Wis.

597 (1872).


50. Gelpcke v. City of Dubuqne, 1 Wall. 175 (1864).


51. Sharpless v. Mayor of Philadelphia, 21 Pa. St. 147 (1853); Dubuque

County v. Dubuque & Pac Ry. Co., 4 Greene (Ia.) 1 (1853).


52. Cases upholding the legislative power to authorize taxation to pay

bounties to soldiers: Taylor v. Thompson, 42 Ill. 9 (1866); Freeland v.

Hastings, 10 Allen 570 (1865); Speer v. School Directors, etc. of

Blairsvflle, 50 Pa. St. 150 (1865); but see Tyson v. School Directors of

Halifax Township, 51 Pa. St. 9 (1865), where the court held an extreme

exercise of such power void because it was not legislation at all. Cases

denying such power to legislatures: Mead v. Acton, 139 Mass. 341 (1885);

State v. Tappan, 29 Wis. 664 (1872).


53. Howard Lee McBain, "Taxation for a Private Purpose," Political Science

Quarterly, XXIX (June, 1914), 185, 197 ff. Taxation for a private purpose

was held invalid in Curtis v Whipple, 24 Wis. 350 (1869).


54. Constitutional Limitations (1868), pp. 487, 488.


55. Opinion of Justices, 58 Me. 590 (1871); People v. Batchellor, 53 N. Y.

128 (1873). For a unique application of this doctrine see opinion of Justice

Brewer holding invalid a statute providing relief for fanners whose crops

had been destroyed, by means of a secured loan for the purchase of grain for

seed and feed. Permanent and fundamental principles were held to prevent an

act to meet a serious emergency. 14 Kan. 418 (1875).


56. People v. Salem, 20 Mich. 452, 473 (1870). For favorable comment on this

decision by Judge Dillon, see American Law Register, IX (N. S., August,

1870), 501.


57. Ibid., pp. 474, 475. The Supreme Court of the United States rejected the

reasoning of Cooley under the language of the constitution of Michigan.

Township of Pine Grove v. Talcott, 19 Wall. 566 (1873). But Cooley adhered

to his former opinion in People v. State Treasurer, 23 Mich. 499 (1871) and

in Thomas 11. City of Port Huron, 27 Mich. 320 (1873).


58. For example, an amendment adopted in Pennsylvania in 1857 provided that

"the legislature shall not authorize any county, city, borough, township, or

incorporated district, by virtue of a vote of its citizens or otherwise, to

become a stockholder in any company, association, or corporation, or obtain

money for, or loan credit to, any corporation, association, institution or

party." Art. xi, sec. 7.


59. Cf. 4th ed. by Nichols (Chicago, 1924), 4 vols.


60. Cooley, Law of Taxation (1st ed.), p 67. In this volume Cooley affirmed

adherence to the doctrine of implied limitations by asserting that "as to

constitutional declarations of individual rights, many of the most important

principles of government are usually not declared at all, but simply taken

for granted," and such limitations, he thought, "are equally imperative

whether declared or not." Page 41, note.


61. Cooley, op. cit., pp. 67, 68.


62. 20 Wall. 655, 663, 664 (1874). This comment of Justice Miller is

frequently cited in support of the theory of implied limitations on

legislatures: "The theory of our governments, state and national, is opposed

to the deposit of unlimited power anywhere. The executive, the legislative,

and the judicial branches of these governments are all of limited and

defined powers. There are limitations on such power which grow out of the

essential nature of all free governments, implied reservations of individual

rights, without which the social compact could not exist, and which are

respected by all governments entitled to the name.... To lay with one hand

the power of the government on the property of the citizen, and with the

other to bestow it on favored individuals to aid private enterprises and

build up private fortunes, is none the less robbery because it is done under

the forms of law and is called taxation This is not legislation It is a

decree under legislative forms."


63. Guilford v Supervisors, 18 Barb. 615 (1854) and 13 N. Y. 143 (1856). In

this case the law of the land and the eminent domain provisions were held to

have no application to taxation. See legislative authorization of a tax to

pay a private debt, Thomas v. Leland, 24 Wend. 65 (1840). But for contrary

opinion see comment of Chancellor Walworth in Cochran v. Van Surlay, 20

Wend. 364, 373 (1838).


64. Weismer v. Village of Douglas, 64 N. Y. 92 (1876).


65. The supreme court of Maine would not allow the legislature to assist

individuals or corporations to carry on manufactories. Opinion of Justices,

58 Me. 590 (1871); Allen v. Jay, 60 Me. 124 (1872). A Massachusetts court

held void an act authorizing the city of Boston to issue bonds and lend the

proceeds to owners of lands and buildings destroyed by fire, Lowell v.

Boston, 111 Mass. 454 (1873); cf. also Mead v. Acton, 139 Mass. 341 (1885);

and Opinion of Justices, 211 Mass. 624 (1912). An Illinois court refused to

permit a levy of a tax to develop the natural advantages of a city for

manufacturing purposes, Mather v. City of Ottawa, 114 Ill. 659 (1885).

Referring to the prohibitions on cities in the raising of taxes to aid

manufacturing establishments, Justice Riddell says: "We do it every day and

in most, if not all, of the cities and in many of the towns and even the

villages of Ontario." Constitution of Canada (New Haven, 1917), p. 139.


66. 2 Johns. 162, 167 (1816).


67. See Coates v. Mayor of the City of New York, 7 Cow. 585, 589 (1827),

referring to requirements of public use and just compensation as based on

principles of natural justice.


68. Matter of Albany street, 11 Wend. 149, 151 (1834). See also one year

later, Varick v. Smith, 5 Paige 137, 159 (1834), in which it was contended

that the exercise of the power of eminent domain for other than a public use

would be an infringement upon the spirit of the constitution, and therefore

not within the general powers delegated by the people to the legislature.

Cf. McBain, "Taxation for a Private Purpose," Pol. Sci. Quar., XXIX, 187, n,

for the halting steps by which New York courts arrived at the public use

doctrine as derived from the due process of law and eminent domain

provisions of the state constitution.


69. Cf. also Dunn v. City Council of Charleston, Harper's Law Repts. 189

(1824) holding that the law of the land provision prevents a taking of more

property than is required for a public improvement, and Emery v. Conner, 3

N. Y. 511 (1850).


70. R. E. Cushman, Excess Condemnation (New York, 1917), chap. 7, and Frank

B. Williams, The Law of City Planning and Zoning (New York, 1922), chap. 3.

For a good brief account of the law of excess and zone condemnation in

Europe see ibid., chap. 2.


71. Wm. E. Britton, "Constitutional Changes in Eminent Domain in Illinois,"

Illinois Law Bulletin, II (April, 1920), 479. Cf. also Wilbur Larremore,

"Incidental Damage to Personal Property in Condemnation Proceedings," Col.

Law Rev. XI (February, 1911), 147. See Sedgwick, Constitutional Law, (2d

ed.), pp. 456 ff. and Lewis, Eminent Domain, vol. I (3d ed.), sec. 66.


72. State v. Evans, 3 Ill. 208 (1840).


73. Lewis, op. cit., chap. 7.


74. Constitutional Limitations (1868), p. 357. See also Lebanon School

District v. Lebanon Female Seminary, 12 Atl. 857, 859 (1888); Justice Cooley

in Detroit v. Detroit and Howell P. R. Co., 43 Mich. 140, 147 (1880); People

v. O'Brien, 111 N. Y. 1 (1888).


75. Mo. Pac. Ry. Co. v. Nebraska, 164 U. S. 403 (1896).


76. Chicago, B. & Q. Ry. Co. v. Chicago, 166 U. S. 226 (1897).


77. "Only a few of the state constitutions in terms prohibit the taking of

property for private use. All courts, however, agree in holding that this

cannot be done. Different courts find different reasons for this

conclusion, some putting it on the ground of an implied prohibition in the

eminent domain provisions of the constitution, some on the ground that it

would be contrary to the provision that no person shall be deprived of his

property except by the law of the land; others, on the ground that it would

be subversive of the fundamental principles of free government, or contrary

to the spirit of the constitution." Lewis, op. cit., I, p. 250, and

footnotes for extensive citation of cases.


78. Pumpelly v. Green Bay Co., 13 Wall. 166, 177, 178 (1871).


79. Monongahela Navigation Co. v. United States, 148 U. S. 312, 324 (1892).

Justice Brewer thought the Fourteenth Amendment was intended to protect

"those rights of person and property which by the Declaration of

Independence were affirmed to be inalienable rights."


80. Cf. McBain, Pol. Sci. Quar., XXIX, pp. 200, 201. With regard to the

requirement of public purpose for taxation "a careful reading of the

numerous cases," says Professor McBain, "in which this doctrine has been

announced impels the conclusion that none of them have progressed very far

in the direction of finding constitutional basis for the doctrine either in

express provision or reasonable implication." Ibid., 199.


81. Paul Errera, Traité de droit public belge, pp. 358 ff. See Constitution

of Belgium (1831), art. XI.


82. Art. 545. Cf. Baudry-Lacantinerie and Chauveau, Traité théorique et

pratique de droit civil (3d ed.), VI, 161.


83. Cf. Laws of May 3, 1841, July 27, 1870, and November 6, 1918; Williams,

op. cit., pp. 68 ff.


84. Léon Duguit, Traité de droit constitutionnel (2d ed.), III, 358, 360.


85. Constitution of Canada, p. 131 and "The Constitutions of the United

States and Canada, Canadian Law Times, XXXII (1912), 849.


86. Cf. Charles E. Merriam, American Political Theories (New York, 1906),

chaps. 2 and 3. The contrast between the radical principles of the

Revolution and the doctrines of the first conservative reaction is shown in

the differences between the Pennsylvania constitution of 1776 drawn chiefly

by Franklin and Bryan and the constitution of 1790 prepared by the leaders

who helped secure the adoption of the federal Constitution.


87. Merriam, op. cit., chaps. 4 and 5.


88. It is worthy of note that the leading American text writers of the

middle of the nineteenth century, such as Kent, Story, Cooley, Dillon, and

Sedgwick (Constitutional Law), were, as a rule, advocates of the doctrine

that there must be implied limits on legislative powers on the basis of

higher law theories.


89. "The influences which produced the restrictions on debt also resulted in

the introduction of a philosophy of laissez faire, public debt and state

activity were condemned together." Secrist, op. cit., p. 8.


90. The point of view of conservative thinkers of the day was clearly

defined by Justice Brewer in a dissenting opinion in State v. Nemaha County,

7 Kan. 549, 555, 556 (1871). "Looking at the provisions of the bills of

rights," said Justice Brewer, "as restrictions upon an otherwise absolute

supremacy in the legislature -- they seem little more than 'glittering

generalities.' But when we regard them as conditions upon which legislative

power is granted -- as the foundation principles upon which all legislative

actions must be based, and a disregard of such action, void, they become

substantial, prominent, vital.... The habit of regarding the legislature as

inherently omnipotent, and looking to see what express restrictions the

Constitution has placed on its action, is dangerous, and tends to error.

Rather regarding first those essential truths, those axioms of civil and

political liberty upon which all free governments are founded, and secondly

those statements of principles in the bill of rights upon which this

governmental structure is reared, we may properly then inquire what powers

the words of the Constitution, the terms of the grant, convey."



                     PART III


     THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT AND NATURAL LAW
                      THEORIES


                    CHAPTER VI


     THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT TO THE FEDERAL
      CONSTITUTION AND DUE PROCESS OF LAW[1]


PRIOR to the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, which has been styled an

"American Magna Carta," due process of law was of little significance in

American constitutional law. For about three quarters of a century after the

introduction of the term into the first state constitutions, it was seldom

used as a basis for the protection of either personal or property rights.

Few legislative enactments were held invalid as contravening due process of

law, and some of the most important efforts to define the phrase were made

in dicta in cases upholding the validity of the laws attacked. On the whole,

the interpretation of the phrase "due process of law" or "the law of the

land" prior to 1870 had placed on legislatures few restrictions which were

not merely procedural in character, and had merely suggested ideas or

principles which under a different environment were soon to be received

favorably.


Though the Fifth Amendment provided that "no person shall ... be deprived of

life, liberty, or property, without due process of law," the federal courts

were seldom called on to protect either personal privileges or property

rights under this provision. And when such an attempt was made it usually

resulted in failure for the litigant.[2]


When the Fourteenth Amendment was adopted in 1868, with the proviso that no

state shall "deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due

process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal

protection of the laws," a serious problem in constitutional interpretation

arose. While the amendment was in the process of formulation in Congress

there were some among the radical Republican group who wanted to change the

whole plan of the federal government, as provided in the Constitution, and

to place a supervisory authority over all state powers in the hands of the

national authorities. The original draft of the amendment was worded so as

to accomplish this object. John A. Bingham, Member of the House of

Representatives, who is credited with the drafting of the original due

process of law clause, said it was his object to render the principles and

restrictions of the Bill of Rights of the federal Constitution applicable to

the acts of the states. Conservative Republicans opposed such a change, and

the original resolution was dropped and one couched in vague and general

terms which proved acceptable to both the radical and the conservative wings

of the Republican party, was submitted to the states for adoption.[3] There

was considerable fear that section one of the amendment contained the germ

of a policy which would mean ultimately a complete change in the relations

between the nation and the states. On this ground some Republicans and

nearly all of the Democrats opposed the adoption of the amendment.[4] By

counting the reconstructed states, forcibly put under Republican control,

the amendment was finally declared adopted with its meaning and intent very

much in doubt. In the controversies over the adoption very little

consideration was given to the significance of section one, the only portion

which has had any noticeable effect upon the relations of the federal and

the state governments.[5]


1. Period of Restricted Interpretation. Congress immediately set about

through enforcement legislation to protect negro voters, to re-enact the

Civil Rights Bill, and to place all violations of these measures under

federal control. But when an issue involving the interpretation of the

amendment came before the Supreme Court, it was decided by a close vote to

reject the radical view favoring a complete change in the federal system,

and the court adopted the conservative opinion of both Democrats and

Republicans -- that the amendment was designed primarily to protect the

negro race in their newly acquired rights and privileges.[6] With this

exception the states, it was thought, were left as free to regulate their

affairs as they were before the Civil War. Thus interpreted, "due process of

law" and the "equal protection of the laws" would have had little effect on

the normal field of state functions. But four members of the court

dissented, and Justice Field in his dissent expressed the view that it was

the intention of the Fourteenth Amendment to "protect the citizens of the

United States against the deprivation of their common rights by state

legislation."[7] Here was a suggestion favorable to special interests

desiring protection, and counsel were not slow to urge upon the court that

the new amendments were intended to place the whole jurisprudence of the

country under the protection of the Supreme Court.[8] The majority of the

justices, however, saw no reason for taking such a significant step, and

chose rather to adhere to the time-honored interpretation of due process of

law. The effect of this and similar decisions[9] was to leave relatively

little power to enforce the amendment in the hands of Congress, and to

transfer its definition and application primarily to the courts. And for ten

years the federal courts consistently discouraged litigation under the

amendment -- so much so that only nine cases were considered in a decade.

This attitude may have been due in part to the fear that Congress, which had

overridden both the executive and the courts in carrying out its

reconstruction policies, would unduly interfere with the powers of the

states. From 1877 to 1885 twenty-six additional cases were adjudicated under

this amendment, making a total of thirty-five cases in sixteen years.

Considering the fact that a considerable number of these cases were either

unimportant or trivial, it seemed that the adoption of the Fourteenth

Amendment had affected but slightly the powers of the states as they existed

prior to the Civil War.[10]


Justice Miller thought that the just compensation principle of the Fifth

Amendment was not comprehended under the Fourteenth Amendment. It seemed to

him


    not a little remarkable, that while this provision has been in
    the Constitution of the United States, as a restraint upon the
    authority of the federal government, for nearly a century, and
    while, during all that time, the manner in which the powers of
    that government have been exercised have been watched
    with jealousy, and subjected to the most rigid criticism in all
    its branches, this special limitation upon its powers has rarely
    been invoked in the judicial forum or the more enlarged
    theater of public discussion. But while it has been a part of
    the Constitution as a restraint upon the powers of the states,
    only a very few years, the docket of this court is crowded
    with cases in which we are asked to hold that state courts
    and state legislatures have deprived their own citizens of life,
    liberty or property, without due process of law. There is
    here abundant evidence that there exists some strange
    misconception of this provision as found in the Fourteenth
    Amendment. In fact, it would seem, from the character of
    many of the cases before us, and the arguments made in
    them, that the clause under consideration is looked upon as
    a means of bringing to the attention or the decision of this
    court the abstract opinion of every unsuccessful litigant in the
    state courts, or jury of the decision against him, and of the
    merits of the legislation upon which such decisions may be
    founded.[11]


When an attempt was made to secure protection under the due process clause

from legislative regulation of private business the court again refused to

accept the extended application of due process of law.[12]


When the argument was presented that the owner of property is entitled to a

reasonable compensation for its use, even though it be clothed with a public

interest, and that what is reasonable is a judicial and not a legislative

question, the answer was given by the court that the practice has been

otherwise.[13]


That this power might be abused, it was admitted, but for protection against

abuses by legislatures, the court replied, "the people must resort to the

polls, not to the courts."[14] The controlling fact was held to be the power

to regulate at all. If that existed the right to establish the maximum

charge as one of the means of regulation was implied. In short, the issue

was regarded as a political question, and was referred to the political

departments of the government. A dissenting opinion by Justices Field and

Strong emphasized the importance of judicial determination of questions of

this nature. The majority opinion was condemned as "subversive of the rights

of private property, heretofore believed to be protected by constitutional

guarantees against legislative interference."[15]


Thus far the federal courts had refused to limit the power of taxation by an

implied public purpose doctrine or by the due process of law clause, to

restrict the legislative regulation of private callings, even to the extent

of permitting the creation of an exclusive monopoly, or to prevent the

fixing, without judicial recourse, of the maximum charge for the use of

property affected with a public interest.[16]


2. Economic and Political Pressure brings about a Change in Supreme Court

Decisions. But the conservative policies which had grown into favor and had

met with judicial approval in the states, were reflected in a reversal of

the position of the Supreme Court, which gradually made the minority views

in the Slaughter-House and the Granger Cases the majority opinion of the

court. The persistent appeal to the court by counsel, representing interests

desiring protection under the Fourteenth Amendment and under other clauses

of the Constitution, ultimately had the desired result.[17] Some marked

changes in economic and social conditions, and political developments

arising therefrom, prepared the way for a change of opinion on the meaning

of the vague phrases of the Fourteenth Amendment.


The Civil War brought on something in the nature of an industrial revolution

in the United States. When foreign intercourse was almost entirely cut off,

the growth of domestic industries was greatly increased. The movement once

begun, and encouraged by a high protective tariff, a phenomenal growth of

manufactures took place from 1870 to 1900. The opening up of extensive areas

in the West, begun before the issues of the Civil War overshadowed

everything else, was accelerated by the Homestead Act and by the building of

transcontinental railways through lavish grants of land by state and federal

governments, and through generous financial aid in other ways. The wave of

commercial expansion that followed the war, augmented by high protective

duties, offered rare opportunities for masters of finance and captains of

industry, which were taken advantage of in the consolidation of the railways

into great systems, and often in wrecking their finances by outrageous

manipulations, and in the beginnings of concentration and integration of

small units in the field of manufactures. As the capitalists grew in number,

and their interests increased in importance, they sought not only to control

legislative assemblies in order to secure special favors but also, in

certain other respects, to curtail their activities.[18]


At the same time that such a marked commercial expansion was under way and

the process of consolidation and integration was going on, certain movements

originating mostly in the West and the South aimed to check this

development, and to bring many of the business practices involved under

regulation by law. The early eighties saw "everywhere increasing inclination

to translate social yearnings into statutes that interfered with the also

fast-increasing class who wished to be let alone because they were well able

to take care of themselves under a static common law."[19] The Granger

Movement, populism, and the beginning of the regulation of industry on

behalf of labor, gave what seemed to many ominous warnings of a dangerous

trend toward state socialism. Thus there arose a clearly drawn controversy

between the leaders of industry, commerce, and finance, and the forces

favoring public regulation and control.


The rush of immigration to the West and the commercial enterprises involved

in opening up large sections of new land, gave to the frontier and to the

philosophy accompanying frontier conditions a dominance in American public

life. Large corporations and industrial enterprises, amply able to take care

of themselves, began to advocate a policy of hands off by the government,

and this policy accorded well with the interests of those who were pushing

the frontier farther to the West. A combination of conservative leaders in

both leading parties was organized to contest all forms of regulation of

business interests by the public. As Hamilton and Madison thought when the

federal Constitution was being formed, that it was necessary to take steps

to check the activities of "overbearing majorities," so Judge Dillon

expressed the opinion of a dominant class in the latter part of the

nineteenth century when he said, "We cannot fail to see that what is now to

be feared and guarded against is the despotism of the many -- of the

majority."[20] A solid front faced the seemingly radical regulative

tendencies growing in the South and the West. The line was clearly drawn

between the conservatives, combined now with the augmented followers of the

laissez faire policy, and the radical leaders of the movement favoring

public regulation of public service enterprises and legislative control of

industrial conditions, regarded as harmful both to the laborers and to the

general public. Justice Holmes had in mind this controversy when he referred

to conditions which


    led people who no longer hope to control the legislatures to
    look to the courts as expounders of the Constitutions, and
    that in some courts new principles have been discovered
    outside the bodies of those instruments, which may be
    generalized into acceptance of the economic doctrines which
    prevailed about fifty years ago, and a wholesale prohibition
    of what a tribunal of lawyers does not think about right. I
    cannot but believe that if the training of lawyers led them
    habitually to consider more definitely and explicitly the social
    advantages on which the rule they lay down must be
    justified, they sometimes would hesitate where now they are
    confident, and see that really they were taking sides upon
    debatable and often burning questions.[21]


It was the drawing of a well-defined issue between conservative and, at

times, reactionary forces which now opposed public regulation of business

interests, public and private, and the liberal or radical leaders who were

committed to regulative and restrictive policies that finally brought

pressure to bear on the Supreme Court sufficient to secure a reversal of its

interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment.[22]


Speaking of the growth of litigation under due process of law as the product

of two generations, Justice Hough remarks:


    "To me the reasons seem to have no very close relation to
    the law or its professors; but to rest on the social and
    material changes which have within the years indicated
    transformed this country from an agricultural to a
    manufacturing community, and its population so largely from
    rural to urban."[23]


Reference was made previously to an apparent change of position when Justice

Miller defended the public purpose criterion in taxation as the basis for

well-defined implied limits on state legislatures. The conclusion was

reached that there can be no lawful tax which is not levied for a public

purpose, and that the determination of what is a public purpose is

ultimately for the courts.[24] That the majority of the court was changing

the grounds on which judicial review of legislation was formerly exercised

was asserted in a dissent by Justice Clifford.[25] The Supreme Court,

however, was not as yet inclined to accept, as a general limitation

applicable to the taxing power of the federal and state governments, the

public purpose doctrine of Justices Cooley and Dillon with all of its

implications.


3. Reversal of the Former Opinions on the Meaning of Due Process of Law. A

change of opinion relative to the meaning of the due process of law clause

of the Fourteenth Amendment, which has extended its scope into many phases

of federal and state law, was indicated primarily in cases relating to the

state regulation of public utilities, in those involving the concept of the

liberty of contract or liberty of calling, and in the interpretation of due

process of law into a broad rule of reason to test the validity of many

controversial state enactments.


(a) Due Process of Law applied to the Procedure in the Regulation of Public

Utilities. Signs of the changing attitude of the justices of the Supreme

Court relative to the legislative control over public utilities appeared

when Chief Justice Waite in upholding the right of legislatures to regulate

railway charges said:


    It is not to be inferred that this power of limitation or
    regulation by the state is itself without limit. This power to
    regulate is not the power to destroy, and limitation is not the
    equivalent of confiscation ... the state cannot ... do that
    which in law amounts to a taking of private property for
    public use without just compensation, or without due
    process of law.[26]


Justice Gray, who joined with the majority in the Munn Case, had changed his

opinion in a decade sufficiently to approve Waite's dictum "as a general

rule of law," but doubted whether the court would, under any circumstances,

have the power to hold a state rate act void on the ground that it was

unreasonable.[27] And as late as 1892 the court again expressed doubt

whether it could hold that a rate fixed by the legislature was

unreasonable.[28]


But the doubt and uncertainty prevailing for some time was in a large part

removed when in the epoch-making Minnesota Rate Case the Supreme Court held

that rate regulation, although primarily legislative in character, was

subject to judicial review under the due process of law clause. Declaring

invalid the Minnesota Act of 1887, providing that the rates established by a

railroad and warehouse commission shall be final and conclusive as to what

are equal and reasonable charges, and that there could be no judicial

inquiry on the question of reasonableness, Justice Blatchford, extending

Chief Justice Waite's dictum, said:


    The question of the reasonableness of a rate of charge for
    transportation by a railroad company, involving as it does
    the element of reasonableness both as regards the company
    and as regards the public, is eminently a question for judicial
    investigation, requiring due process of law for its
    determination.[29]


Justice Bradley, with whom concurred Justices Gray and Lamar, asserted that

the majority opinion of the court practically overruled Munn v. Illinois and

other railroad cases decided by the court, and commented as follows:


    But it is said that all charges should be reasonable, and that
    none but reasonable charges should be exacted; and it is
    urged that what is a reasonable charge is a judicial question.
    On the contrary, it is preeminently a legislative one, involving
    considerations of policy as well as of remuneration; and is
    usually determined by the legislature by fixing a maximum of
    charges.... If this maximum is not exceeded, the courts
    cannot interfere.... Thus, the legislature either fixes the
    charges at rates which it deems reasonable; or merely
    declares that they shall be reasonable; and it is only in the
    latter case, where reasonableness is left open, that the courts
    have jurisdiction of the subject.[30]


A decision which made the courts the final arbiters in the regulation of

rates, Justice Bradley thought, was an assumption of an authority on the

part of the judiciary which it had no right to make. To the repeated

arguments that such a power in the hands of legislatures was dangerous and

that implied limits on legislatures were essential to preserve and protect

property rights, Justice Bradley replied, defending the principles of

democratic control of public affairs:


    It may be that our legislatures are invested with too much
    power, open, as they are, to influences so dangerous to the
    interests of individuals, corporations and society. But such is
    the constitution of our republican form of government; and
    we are bound to abide by it until it can be corrected in a
    legitimate way. If our legislatures become too arbitrary in the
    exercise of their powers, the people always have a remedy
    in their hands; they may at any time restrain them by
    constitutional limitations. But so long as they remain invested
    with the powers, that ordinarily belong to the legislative
    branch of government they are entitled to exercise those
    powers, amongst which, in my judgment, is that of the
    regulation of railroads and other public means of
    intercommunication, and the burdens and charges which
    those who own them are authorized to impose upon the
    public.[31]


The original purpose of the due process of law clause was to protect the

weak and the oppressed but when the Supreme Court decided that corporations

were entitled to the protection of the Fourteenth Amendment and that foreign

corporations could not be deprived of their property arbitrarily,[32] the

way was opened for organizations of capital to contest before the Supreme

Court such laws as they regarded unwise or detrimental to their interests.

Comparatively few cases have arisen under the amendment to protect personal

or individual rights and instead it has become the bulwark for the

protection of the privileges and interests of large corporations. Where

states reserved in their constitutions the right of the legislature to

alter, amend, or repeal at will corporate franchises, the Supreme Court

intervened to insist that the power of alteration and amendment is not

without limit. The alterations must be reasonable and they must not take the

property of the company without just compensation.[33] Such a holding has

amounted to the practical proposition that legislatures may amend corporate

charters to the advantage of the incorporators but not to their detriment.


As a result of this change in the attitude of the court, and the extension

of due process of law as a standard applicable to rate regulation and the

reasonableness of measures for public control, a large field of public

powers, namely, the manifold regulations of state legislatures and

administrative commissions, in their effort to control public utilities, has

become subject to the continuous critical scrutiny of the courts,[34] often

primarily concerned with preserving the property rights of the utilities.


Judicial review by this extension of the application of due process of law

has entered a new field, and has placed numerous restrictions and

obstructions in the way of effective regulation of public utilities by

states and other local bodies. Such review manifestly was not inherent in

any constitutional provision or a necessary concomitant of constitutional

interpretation as first understood and applied in state and federal

governments. It came as a result of the fear of democratic control and of

popular participation in the regulation of public utilities and of the

belief that private property could be made safe only with extensive

limitations on legislatures rendered effective by courts through judicial

review of legislative and administrative findings.


While the court was gradually changing its position on the review of

legislative and administrative procedure in rate-making and in the

regulative power exercised by states over corporations and public utilities,

members of the court imbued with the frontier philosophy of individualism,

or sympathetic with conservative doctrines were establishing a standard by

construction to pass on the fairness or expediency of labor legislation.

Justice Field had suggested in the Slaughter-House Cases that in his opinion

the Fourteenth Amendment was intended to protect all citizens of the United

States in their "common rights," and it was in the definition of these

"common rights" that the theories of the Declaration of Independence and of

the eighteenth-century natural rights were again applied.[35]


(b) Due Process of Law and Liberty of Contract. As an advocate of the

natural rights ideas of the revolutionary period Justice Field became the

mouthpiece for the judicial protection of the fundamental rights which

belong to man "as a free man and a free citizen."[36] At the first available

opportunities Justice Field gave a careful exposition of his views as to the

nature of these fundamental rights, as follows:


    As in our intercourse with our fellow-men certain principles
    of morality are assumed to exist, without which society
    would be impossible, so certain inherent rights lie at the
    foundation of all action, and upon a recognition of them
    alone can free institutions be maintained. These inherent
    rights have never been more happily expressed than in the
    Declaration of Independence, that new evangel of liberty to
    the people; "We hold these truths to be self-evident" -- that
    is, so plain that their truth is recognized upon their mere
    statement -- "that all men are endowed" -- not by edicts of
    Emperors, or decrees of Parliament, or acts of Congress,
    but "by their Creator with certain inalienable rights" -- that
    is, rights which cannot be bartered away or given away, or
    taken away except in punishment of crime -- "and that
    among these, are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness,
    and to secure these" -- not grant them, but secure them --
    "governments are instituted among men, deriving their just
    powers from the consent of the governed."


    Among these inalienable rights, as proclaimed in that great
    document, is the right of men to pursue their happiness, by
    which is meant the right to pursue any lawful business or
    vocation, in any manner not inconsistent with the equal rights
    of others, which may increase their prosperity or develop
    their faculties, so as to give to them their highest enjoyment.


    The common business and callings of life, the ordinary
    trades and pursuits, which are innocuous in themselves, and
    have been followed in all communities from time
    immemorial, must, therefore, be free in this country to all
    alike upon the same conditions. The right to pursue them,
    without let or hindrance, except that which is applied to all
    persons of the same age, sex, and condition, is a
    distinguishing privilege of citizens of the United States, and
    an essential element of that freedom which they claim as
    their birthright.


    It has been well said that "the property which every man has
    in his own labor, as it is the original foundation of all other
    property, so it is the most sacred and inviolable. The
    patrimony of the poor man lies in the strength and dexterity
    of his own hand, and to hinder his employing his strength
    and dexterity in what manner he thinks proper, without
    injury to his neighbor, is a plain violation of this most sacred
    property. It is a manifest encroachment upon the just liberty
    both of the workman and of those who might be disposed to
    employ him. As it hinders the one from working at what he
    thinks proper, so it hinders the others from employing whom
    they think proper." Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations, Bk. I,
    chap. 10.[37]


    The Fourteenth Amendment, in declaring that no state "shall
    deprive any person of life, liberty, or property without due
    process of law, nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction
    the equal protection of the laws," undoubtedly intended not
    only that there should be no arbitrary deprivation of life or
    liberty, or arbitrary spoliation of property, but that equal
    protection and security should be given to all under like
    circumstances in the enjoyment of their personal and civil
    rights; that all persons should be equally entitled to pursue
    their happiness and acquire and enjoy property; that they
    should have like access to the courts of the country for the
    protection of their persons and property, the prevention and
    redress of wrongs, and the enforcement of contracts; that no
    impediment should be interposed to the pursuits of any one
    except as applied to the same pursuits by others under like
    circumstances; that no greater burdens should be laid upon
    one than are laid upon others in the same calling and
    condition, and that in the administration of criminal justice no
    different or higher punishment should be imposed upon one
    than such as is prescribed to all for like offenses.[38] 


These dicta, along with some similar remarks of other justices, introduced

into American law the concept of liberty of contract and of calling. This

concept, which is one of the by-products of natural law thinking, had its

origin in mediaeval times and was accepted in France and in England as one

of the principles of the economic policy of laissez faire. The principle was

accepted and applied by the state courts to check the increased efforts of

legislatures to regulate wage contracts and labor conditions.[39]


It was merely necessary to translate these dicta into concrete terms and to

use them in rendering the judgments of the Supreme Court.[40] This was done

by Justice Peckham when he asserted that, "in the privilege of pursuing an

ordinary calling or trade, and of acquiring, holding and selling property

must be embraced the right to make all proper contracts in relation

thereto,"[41] and with extensions beyond Field's broad terms, by Justices

Harlan[42] and Pitney.[43]


Thus, beginning in a series of dicta, a doctrine of liberty of contract was

developed as a phase of the Fourteenth Amendment and was gradually accepted

and interpreted by the majority of the Supreme Court to embody the natural

and inalienable rights doctrine of the Declaration of Independence. The

terms of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments were thereby given an

interpretation which placed new limits on legislative powers for the state

and federal governments.[44] Advocates of the "new liberties" soon

formulated what they called a fundamental principle, namely, that the term

"liberty" as used in the Declaration of Independence and as extracted from

the general language "due process of law" in written constitutions meant not

only for the individual freedom from servitude and restraint, but also

freedom to use his powers and faculties, and to pursue such vocation or

calling as he may choose, subject only to the restraints necessary to

protect the common welfare.[45]


The adoption by the courts of the principle of judicial review of public

utility regulations as a requirement for the due process clause of the

Fourteenth Amendment, combined with an incorporation therewith of a

considerable part of Chancellor Kent's vested rights doctrine,[46] which the

judiciary were specially charged to apply, and the interpretation of the

amendment to include the natural rights theories of the Declaration of

Independence went a long way toward construing the Fourteenth Amendment as

radical Republican leaders had desired, so as to exercise national

supervision over the control of civil rights -- an interpretation which the

court itself had repeatedly rejected.[47] But with all of these ideas

combined in the due process clause a mere beginning was made to develop in

the constitutional law of the United States a formidable Naturrecht or

natural law, which was to be fostered into a new lease of life by combining

the phrases "due process of law" and the "equal protection of the laws."

These have been united to assure the broadest kind of protection for the

fundamental rights of the individual and for the assurance that there can be

no arbitrary interference with personal liberty. Thereby a theory of the

protection of human rights glorified by the common law courts was

consecrated into a constitutional doctrine and characterized as democratic.




1. "Our constitutional liberty during the last thirty years, with

comparatively few exceptions, may be said to be but little more than a

commentary on the Fourteenth Amendment, which indeed nationalized the whole

sphere of civil liberty. This great amendment to the Federal Constitution

has done more than any other cause to protect our civil rights from

invasion, to strengthen the bonds of the Union, to make us truly a nation,

and to assure the perpetuity of our institutions" William D. Guthrie,

Lectures on the Fourteenth Article of Amendment to the Constitution of the

United States, (Boston, 1898), pp. 1, 2.


2. Cf. Murray's Lessee v. Hoboken Land and Improvement Co., 18 How. 272

(1855). Due process the court held to be a restraint on the legislative as

well as the executive and judicial powers of government and a process of law

which is not otherwise forbidden, and which can be shown to have had the

sanction of settled usage both in England and in this country. Cf. also

Hurtado v. California, 110 U. S. 516, 528 (1883), and Holden v. Hardy, 169

U. S. 366, 390 (1898). For incidental reference to the Fourteenth Amendment,

see United States v. Harris, 106 U. S. 629 (1883); see also Yick Wo v.

Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356. Cases in which federal acts have been held void as

violating due process of law are: Adair v. U. S., 208 U. S. 161 (1908);

United States v. Cohen Grocery Co , 255 U. S. 81 (1921); Adkins v.

Children's Hospital, 261 U. S. 525 (1923); Untermeyer v. Anderson, 276 U. S.

440 (1928).


3. Horace E. Flack, The Adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, chaps. 1 and

2. Dr. Flack concludes that Congress had the following objects in view in

submitting to the states the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment:


    1. To make the Bill of Rights (the first eight amendments)
    binding upon, or applicable to, the states.


    2. To give validity to the Civil Rights Bill.


    3. To declare who were citizens of the United States. See
    pp. 92 ff. It must not be forgotten, however, that it was a
    Congress dominated by the bitter war spirit and led by the
    radical Reconstruction leaders of the Republican party
    which was responsible for the amendment, and, that a large
    part of the legislation enacted and of the policies fostered by
    these leaders was repudiated when something approaching
    normal political conditions was restored. 


4. Cf. B. B. Kendrick, The Journal of the Joint Committee of Fifteen on

Reconstruction, 39th Congress, 1865-1867, Columbia University Studies in

History, Economics and Public Law, vol. LXII. "The line of Democratic

hostility in the nation and the states was absolutely unbroken" James G.

Blaine, Twenty Years of Congress, pp. 308-310.


5. Flack, op. cit., p. 208. "The Fourteenth [Amendment] was a straight party

measure, due to the distrust of the states solely in respect of their

possible treatment of the negro. The sufficient proof of party spirit is

that in all the legislatures of all the states exactly one Democrat voted

for it." Charles M. Hough, "Due Process of Law -- Today," Harvard Law Review,

XXXII (January, 1919), 220.


6. The Slaughter-House Cases, 16 Wall. 36 (1872). See Edward S. Corwin "The

Supreme Court and the Fourteenth Amendment," Michigan Law Review, VII (June,

1909), 643.


7. 16 Wall. 89.


8. Murdock v. Memphis, 20 Wall. 590, 599 (1874).


9. See United States v. Cruikshank, 92 U. S. 542 (1875). But Chief Justice

Waite threw out the suggestion that the Fourteenth Amendment "furnishes an

additional guaranty against any encroachment by the states upon the

fundamental rights which belong to every citizen as a member of society."

Ibid., 554.


10. Prior to 1883 "appeals to due process of law in the federal courts were

rare, and (barring the negro cases) never successful, except on the

procedural side." Pennoyer v. Neff, 95 U. S. 714 (1877) is called a

"monument" of the latter type of decision. Cf. Hough, op. cit., p. 218.


11. Davidson v. New Orleans, 96 U. S. 97, 103-104 (1877). It was in this

case in which Justice Miller, refusing to define due process of law, said:

"There is wisdom, we think, in the ascertaining of the intent and

application of such an important phrase in the federal Constitution, by the

gradual process of inclusion and exclusion, as the cases presented shall

require." Ibid., 104.


Referring to the above observation of Justice Miller in 1885, Justice Field

remarked that after the lapse of eight years, it may be repeated with an

expression of increased surprise at the continued misconception of the

purpose of this provision." Missouri Pacific Railway v. Humes, 115 U. S.

512, 520 (1885). For a change in the position of the court see opinion of

Justice Gray in Missouri Pacific Railway v. Nebraska, 164 U. S. 403, 417

(1896). A requirement that a company lease its property to a private party

was held to be a taking of property and a denial of due process of law.

Chicago, Burlington and Quincy Ry. Co. v. Chicago, 166 U. S. 226, 233, 241

(1896). Henceforth it was regarded as settled that a state might not under

the due process provision take private property for public use without just

compensation.


12. Munn v. Illinois, 94 U. S. 113 (1876) and the Granger Cases, 94 U. S.

155, 164, 179, 180. See Buck, The Granger Movement, chaps. 4-6. For similar

decisions approving the regulative power of the states see Bradwell v. The

State, 16 Wall. 130 (1872); Bartemeyer v. Iowa, 18 Wall. 129 (1873); United

States v. Cruikshank, 92 U. S. 542 (1875); Hurtado v. California, 110 U. S.

516 (1883); Barbier 11. Connolly, 113 U. S. 27 (1884); and Powell v.

Pennsylvania, 127 U. S. 678 (1887). See, however, Justice Field's opinion on

the broad implications of the Fourteenth Amendment, 113 U. S. 31.


13. Munn v. Illinois, 94 U.S. 133, 134. At common law, in the absence of

legislation, a public utility was bound to charge no more than a reasonable

rate and in case of complaint it was for a court to decide whether the rate

was reasonable. But if Parliament fixed a schedule of rates no court could

inquire into the question of reasonableness. The remedy in such case lay in

an appeal to Parliament or to the voters, not to the courts. Gerard C.

Henderson, "Railway Valuation and the Courts," Harv. Law Rev., XXXIII (May,

1920), 904.


14. 94 U.S. 134.


15. Ibid., 136. In Stone v. Wisconsin, it was again maintained by the

minority that the court's decision that a corporation charter was subject

to alterations or repeal by the state legislature was wrong, and that it

will "justify the legislature in fixing the prices of all articles and the

compensation for all services. It sanctions intermeddling with all business

and pursuits and property in the community, leaving the use and enjoyment of

property to be regulated according to the discretion of the legislature." 94

U. S. 181, 186 (1876).


16. The decisions in the Granger Cases Judge Hough remarks "seemed to put

all complaints of corporate regulation of service and charges out of court,

if an appeal under the due-process clause was ventured against a state; the

still continuing dissents of Justice Field seemed most unorthodox. The

remarks in another judgment, that due process was usually what the state

ordained, seemed to clinch the matter." Harv. Law Rev., XXXII, 226 and

Walker v. Sauvinet, 92 U. S. 90 (1875).


17. See argument of Joseph H Choate in Pollock v Farmers' Loan & Trust Co.,

157 U S. 429, 532, 534 (1895): "I believe there are private rights of

property here to be protected; that we have a right to come to this court

and ask for this protection, and that this court has a right, without asking

leave of the attorney general or any counsel, to hear our plea. The act of

Congress which we are impugning before you is communistic in its purpose and

tendencies and is defended here upon principles as communistic, socialistic

-- what shall I call them -- populistic as ever have been addressed to any

political assembly in this world.... I have thought that one of the

fundamental objects of all civilized governments was the preservation of the

rights of private property. I have thought it was the very keystone in the

arch upon which all civilized government rests and that this once abandoned,

everything was at stake and in danger."


18. S. J. Buck, The Granger Movement (Cambridge, 1913), pp. 13 ff.


19. Hough, op. cit., p. 227.


20. The Laws and Jurisprudence of England and America, pp. 204-205.


21. Collected Legal Papers (New York, 1920), p. 184 and Harv. Law Rev., X

(March, 1897), 456, 467.


22. "Conservative and liberal schools of interpretation not only instantly

appeared at bar, but in the court, and along party lines, in a way not

usually recognized." Hough, op. cit., p. 225. "The Granger legislation

aroused bitter political passions and grave fears among those who believed

the welfare of the country depended upon the security of property. In case

after case, as it came before the Supreme Court, the leaders of the bar

appealed to the court not to leave the vast interests of private

stockholders at the mercy of radical state legislatures. To have withstood

this appeal would have been utterly inconsistent with the individualistic

spirit which pervaded American jurisprudence in the latter part of the

nineteenth century. Some method must be devised by which courts could check

the assaults of western legislatures upon established property rights."

Henderson, op. cit., p. 905. See also Hough, op. cit., p. 227.


23. Hough, op. cit., p. 222.


24. Loan Association v. Topeka, 20 Wall. 655, 662, 663 (1874). See comment

of Justice Miller in Davidson v. New Orleans, "that because of the fact that

the Loan Association Case came to the federal courts because of the

character of the parties, the justices felt free to enforce general

principles of constitutional law." 96 U. S. 97, 105 (1877).


When the contention was made that unjust and oppressive taxation by the

states should be prevented, the Supreme Court held that the Constitution was

not intended to furnish a corrective for every abuse of power which may be

committed by the state governments and could not afford relief between a

state and its citizens against taxation, however unjust, oppressive, or

onerous. Kirtland v. Hotchkiss, 100 U. S. 491, 498 (1879). But eleven years

later, speaking again through Justice Harlan, an unwise exercise of the

power of levying special assessments was held invalid on the general ground

that "the power of the legislature in these matters is not unlimited."

Norwood v. Baker, 172 U. S. 268, 278 (1898). For a modification of the

judgment in this case see French v. Barber Asphalt Pav. Co, 181 U. S. 324

(1901). Justices Harlan, White, and McKenna dissented.


25. "Courts cannot nullify an act of the state legislature," said Justice

Clifford, "on the vague ground that they think it opposed to a general

latent spirit supposed to pervade or underlie the Constitution, where

neither the terms nor the implications of the instrument disclose any such

restriction. Such a power is denied to the courts, because to concede it

would be to make the courts sovereign over both the Constitution and the

people, and convert the government into a judicial despotism.... Unwise laws

and such as are highly inexpedient and unjust are frequently passed by the

legislative bodies, but there is no power vested in a circuit court, nor in

this court to determine that any law passed by a state legislature is void

if it is not repugnant to their own constitution nor the Constitution of the

United States." 20 Wall. 669, 670.


26. Stone v. Farmers' Loan and Trust Co., 116 U. S. 307, 331 (1885). "It is

now settled in this court," said the Chief Justice, "that a state has power

to limit the amount of charges by railroad companies for the transportation

of persons and property within its own jurisdiction, unless restrained by

some contract in the charter, or unless what is done amounts to a regulation

of foreign or interstate commerce." Ibid., 325. Justices Harlan and Field

dissented on the ground that the state act was void in so far as it

authorized a commission rather than a court to determine finally the fair

return on the value of a railroad. For a similar suggestion see Spring

Valley Water Works v. Schottler, 110 U. S. 347, 354 (1883). See opinion of

Justice Harlan in Ruggles v. Illinois, 108 U. S. 526, 535 (1883) for an

effort to place the basis for the judicial review of rate regulation on the

contract clause and on the principles announced by Chief Justice Marshall in

the Dartmouth College Case. Using this decision as a basis the railroads

denied the right of the states or of the nation to regulate them. Buck, The

Granger Movement, p. 12.


27. Dow v. Beidleman, 125 U. S. 680, 686, 691 (1888). A state law in this

case which fixed a maximum of three cents a mile for a railway charge for

carrying passengers was held not to deny these corporations due process of

law. Justice Gray, who joined the dissenters in Chicago, Milwaukee and St.

Paul Ry. Co. v. Minnesota, 134 U. S. 418 (1890), had shifted his position

completely and was with the majority in Smyth v. Ames, 169 U. S. 466 (1898).


28. Budd v. New York, 143 U. S. 517, 548 (1892); cf. Henderson, op. cit.,

pp. 904 ff.


29. Chicago, Milwaukee & St. Paul Ry. Co. v. Minnesota, 134 U. S. 418, 458

(1889); through the opinions of Justice Brewer in Reagan v. Farmers' Loan

and Trust Co., 154 U. S. 362, 397 (1894) and of Justice Harlan in Smyth v.

Ames, 169 U. S. 466, 523 ff. (1898), the change in position was completed.

Under the Fourteenth Amendment it has since been repeatedly held that "the

rates must be sufficient to cover reasonable operating expenses, plus a

proper allowance for depreciation, plus a fair return upon the value of the

property; in short, there must be a reasonable judgment having its basis in

the proper consideration of all relevant facts." R. L. Hale, "Rate Making

and the Revision of the Property Concept," Columbia Law Review XXII (March,

1922), 209.


For the opinions of Justice Brewer as Circuit Justice supporting an

extensive judicial review to protect the vested rights of utility

corporations, see Ames v. Union Pac. Ry. Co., 64 Fed. 163, 176 (1894) and

National Waterworks Co. v. Kansas City, 62 Fed. 853, 864 ff. (1804). See

also Justice Brewer's opinion holding invalid an act of Congress which

abolished the tolls charged by a private company on river traffic with an

express provision that the value of the franchise was not to be included in

the condemnation proceedings. A franchise, he said, "is a vested right. The

state has power to grant it. It may retake it, as it may other private

property, for public use, upon the payment of just compensation ... but it

can no more take the franchise which the state has given than it can any

private property belonging to the individual." Monongahela Navigation Co. v.

United States, 148 U. S. 312, 341 (1893).


30. 134 U. S. 418, 462 (1889).


31. 134 U. S., 466.


32. Cf. Opinion of Justice Field in the Santa Clara Railroad Tax Case, 9

Sawyer 165, 210, and of Justice Harlan in Santa Clara County v. Southern

Pacific Railroad Co., 118 U. S. 394 (1886); also Justice Field in Pembina

Mining Co. v. Pennsylvania, 125 U. S. 181, 188 (1888) and Minneapolis and St

Louis Ry. Co. v. Beckwith, 129 U. S. 26, 28 (1889) Also Henderson, The

Position of Foreign Corporations in American Constitutional Law, chap. 9.

That a foreign corporation was entitled to the equal protection of the laws

was held, also, in Pembina Mining Case, infra, and Southern Railway Co. v.

Greene, 216 U. S. 400, 412 (1910).


Mr. Smith claims by rendering the inhibitions of the Fourteenth Amendment

applicable to corporations the Constitution of the United States was amended

"by the act of the judiciary alone." "We approach now," he asserted, "a

Revolution in our form of government accomplished by the Supreme Court of

the United States, so startling that it seems almost incredible, and this

Revolution was completed so silently that it has passed almost unnoticed

even by the careful historians of the Constitution and of the Court." F.

Dumont Smith, "Decisive Battles of Constitutional Law," American Bar

Association Journal, X (July, 1924), 505, and The Constitution: Its Story

and Battles (Los Angeles, 1926), p. 359.


33. Justice Swayne in Shields v. Ohio, 95 U. S. 319, 325 (1877).


34. For about thirty years "we have had every species of state action

productive of permanent loss to vested rights, or limiting business

liberty, put to the acid test of due process in the Supreme Court." Hough,

op. cit., p. 229. The decisions as to public utility rates and regulations

are regarded as "extraordinary in the extent of the power which they place

in the hands of the courts, and in the way in which they tie the hands of

the state legislatures in respect to subjects over which it has always been

considered they had absolute control ... the will of the people in this, as

in other respects, is expressed through the acts of their representatives in

the legislature. The opinion that the reasonableness of an act is not a

legislative but a judicial question substitutes the will of the judges for

the will of the people. Mr. Justice Bradley clearly foresaw this, and deeply

regretted the inevitable conflict between the courts and the legislature."

"The Judicial Record of Justice Bradley," William Draper Lewis in The

Miscellaneous Writings of Joseph P. Bradley (1902), p. 25. "After the

Chicago Case," says Justice Hough, "legislators were arraigned before the

bar and courts passed judgment not, mark you, on the justice or wisdom, but

on the reason, of what they had done." Harv. Law Rev., XXXII, 228. For an

analysis of the shifting of Supreme Court justices in defining the terms

"liberty" and "property" from the standpoint of an economist, consult John

R. Commons, Legal Foundations of Capitalism (New York, 1924), especially

chap. 9.


For review of the decisions of public utility commissions by the federal

courts in order to make sure that the decisions are "fair" and

"reasonable," consult John Dickinson, Administrative Justice and the

Supremacy of the Law in the United States (Cambridge, 1927), chap. 6.


35. Justice Field, in holding void a personal judgment rendered by a state

court in an action in personam against a non-resident upon whom no personal

service was made, defined due process of law so as to include a portion of

the concept of natural law: "They then mean a course of legal proceedings

according to those rules and principles which have been established in our

system of jurisprudence for the protection and enforcement of private

rights. To give such proceedings any validity, there must be a tribunal

competent by its constitution -- that is, by the law of its creation: to

pass upon the subject-matter of the suit; and, if that involves merely a

determination of the personal liability of the defendant, he must be brought

within its protection by service of process within the state, or his

voluntary appearance." Pennoyer v. Neff, 95 U. S. 714, 733 (1877). For an

approval of this interpretation, see opinion of Justice Gray in Scott v.

McNeal, 154 U. S. 34, 46 (1894).


36. See dissent in Slaughter-House Cases, 16 Wall. 36, 95 (1872); also

opinion of Justice Brewer in Monongahela Navigation Co. v. United States,

148 U. S. 312, 324 (1892). Justice Brewer regarded the Declaration of

Independence as the cornerstone of the federal Constitution. Cf. address,

Yale Law School, June, 1891, on "Protection to Private Property from Public

Attack."


37. Butchers' Union Co. v. Crescent City Co., 111 U. S. 746, 756 (1883).

This opinion, though it was not in accord with the majority views of the

Supreme Court, had an extensive influence on the state courts -- "It

produced a reactionary line of decisions in New York on liberty to pursue

one's calling, and through these cases its echoes are still ringing in the

books." Pound, "Liberty of Contract," Yale Law Journal, XVIII (May, 1909),

454, 470.


38. Barbier v. Connolly, 113 U. S. 27, 31 (1885).


39. Cf. the recognition of liberty of contract as an inalienable right of a

citizen by Justice Brewer in Frisbie v. United States, 157 U. S. 160, 165

(1894). The main guaranty of private rights against unjust legislation is

found in the due process clause, according to Justice Andrews. As protected

under this clause Justice Andrews thought "the right to life includes the

right of the individual to his body ... the right to liberty, the right to

exercise his faculties and to follow a lawful avocation for the support of

life; the right of property, the right to acquire power and enjoy it in any

way consistent with the equal rights of others and the just exactions and

demands of the state." Bertholf v. O'Reilly, 74 N. Y. 509, 515 (1878). See

also Godcharles v. Wigeman, 113 Pa. St. 431, 6 Atl. 354 (1886); Millett v.

People, 117 Ill. 294, 7 N. E. 631 (1886); Braceville Coal Co. v. People, 147

Ill. 66, 35, N. E. 62 (1893); State v. Loomis, 115 Mo. 307, 22 S. W. 350

(1892); State v. Norton, 5 Ohio N. P. R. 183 (1898); State v. Goodwill, 33

W. Va. 179, 10 S. E. 285, 863 (1889); in re House Bill, 21 Col. Rep. 27

(1895); Ritchie v. People, 155 Ill. 98, 104 ff. (1895); and People v.

Williams, 189 N. Y. 131 (1907).


For summary of decisions developing the doctrine of liberty of contract from

1890-99, cf. Pound, "Liberty of Contract," Yale Law Jour., XXIII, 472 ff.

and G. G. Groat, "Economic Wage and Legal Wage," Ibid., XXXIII (March,

1924), 488, 494. The application of this concept by the Supreme Court in

invalidating a Minimum Wage Act for the District of Columbia, in Adkins v.

Children's Hospital, 261 U. S. 525 (1923), will be considered later.

According to Louis D. Brandeis, "Courts continued to ignore newly arisen

needs. They have applied complacently eighteenth century conceptions of

liberty of the individual and of the sacredness of private property ...

where statutes giving expression to the new social spirit were clearly

constitutional, judges, imbued with the relentless spirit of individualism,

often construed them away." Illinois Law Review, X (February, 1916), 461,

464. Though some of the illiberal decisions relating to labor contracts have

been reversed, the liberty of contract doctrine still stands as a bar to

progressive measures in the field of labor legislation. Cf. Ritchie v.

Wayman, 244 Ill. 509 (1910) and People v. Charles Schweinler Press, 214 N.

Y. 395 (1915).


40. The concept of liberty of contract which was formulated by Justice

Field, and developed in a series of state decisions, was thus defined by

Justice Shope in the Braceville Coal Company case: "The fundamental

principle upon which liberty is based, in free and enlightened government,

is equality under the law of the land. It has accordingly been everywhere

held, that liberty, as that term is used in the constitution, means not

only freedom of the citizen from servitude and restraint, but, indeed, to

embrace the right of every man to be free in the use of his powers and

faculties, and to adopt and pursue such avocation or calling as he may

choose, subject only to the restraints necessary to secure the common

welfare. 147 Ill. 66, 71 (1893). In most cases the language of Justice Field

was used, with variations to suit the circumstances of the case.


41. Allgeyer v. Louisiana, 165 U. S. 578, 591 (1897).


42. "The right of a person to sell his labor upon such terms as he deems

proper is, in its essence, the same as the right of the purchaser of labor

to prescribe the conditions upon which he will accept such labor from the

person offering to sell it. So the right of the employé to quit the service

of the employer, for whatever reason, is the same as the right of the

employer, for whatever reason to dispense with the services of such employé.

It was the legal right of the defendant, Adair, -- however unwise such a

course might have been, -- to discharge Coppage because of his being a

member of a labor organization, as it was the legal right of Coppage, if he

saw fit to do so, -- however unwise such a course on his part might have

been, -- to quit the service in which he was engaged, because the defendant

employed some persons who were not members of a labor organization In all

such particulars the employer and the employe have equality of right, and

any legislation that disturbs that equality is an arbitrary interference

with the liberty of contract which no government can legally justify in a

free land," Adair v. United States, 208 U. S. 161, 174-175 (1908).


43. "Included in the right of personal liberty and the right of private

property -- partaking of the nature of each -- is the right to make

contracts for the acquisition of property. Chief among such contracts is

that of personal employment, by which labor and other services are exchanged

for money or other forms of property. If this right be struck down or

arbitrarily interfered with, there is a substantial impairment of liberty in

the long established constitutional sense. The right is as essential to the

laborer as to the capitalist, to the poor as to the rich; for the vast

majority of persons have no other honest way to begin to acquire property,

save by working for money." Coppage v. Kansas, 236 U. S. 1, 14 (1915).


44. Commenting on the fact that the due process clauses of the Fifth and

Fourteenth Amendments were rarely invoked as an aid to protect private

rights or referred to by justices prior to 1880, Mr. Willis says: "Finally,

with the case of Davidson v. New Orleans, 96 U. S. 97 (1878), and a long

line of cases following it. Coke's doctrine of a supreme fundamental law was

merged in the doctrine of due process of law, and legislation has since then

been set aside because not due process of law but not because in violation

of some supreme fundamental law." Hugh Evander Willis, "Due Process of Law

under the United States Constitution," University of Pennsylvania Law

Review, LXXIV (February, 1926), 331, 335.


45. In considering the application of a woman to practice law, Justice

Hackney claimed: "There is a law higher in this country, and one better

suited to the rights and liberties of the American citizens, the natural

right to gain a livelihood by intelligence, honesty and industry in the

arts, the sciences, the professions, or other vocations" and the exclusion

from such practice was held to interfere with inalienable rights, citing

Justice Field in Cummings v. Missouri, 4 Wallace 277, 321. In re Leach, 134

Ind 665, 668 (1893).


46. In 1896 and 1897 it was held that due process of law was a limitation on

the power of eminent domain. Fallbrook Irrigation District v. Bradley, 164

U. S. 113 (1896); Chicago, Burlington and Quincy Ry. Co. v. Chicago, 166 U.

S. 226 (1896).


47. Instead of the judges having discovered new meanings for due process of

law, Dr. Mott claims they have merely appropriated portions of a general

residual meaning. Mott, Due Process of Law, p. 590. From this viewpoint an

unappropriated portion of this concept will always be available to keep

legislators in the straight and narrow paths which judges lay out.



                   CHAPTER VII


 THE DEVELOPMENT OF A GENERAL RULE OF REASON TO
    DETERMINE THE VALIDITY OF LEGISLATIVE ACTS


TO GIVE due process of law a more effective scope as a criterion to measure

the validity of new legislative projects, the justices who were exponents of

conservative principles and laissez faire policies adopted the dicta of a

few authorities on Magna Carta and of several state justices that this

phrase was designed to prevent all governmental acts arbitrary in their

nature and to preserve the fundamental principles of a free republican

government. The application of a rule of reason or a rule of expediency as a

primary standard to evaluate the propriety of legislation was accomplished

by making due process of law an inhibition against arbitrary legislative or

administrative acts, against any interference with the fundamental rights of

the individual, and against social and economic legislation which was

regarded unreasonable or discriminatory.


1. Arbitrary Legislative and Administrative Acts are Void. Locke is credited

with suggesting the idea that exercising governmental powers in an arbitrary

manner is unconstitutional.[1] The suggestion of this idea, however, may be

traced to opinions rather common in ancient and mediaeval times. The claims

that certain clauses of Magna Carta were intended to check all forms of

arbitrary political authority,[2] had few supporters in England, as we have

seen, but was repudiated by all parties prior to the time that the American

colonies set up new governments.


Early in the nineteenth century the belief had been expressed in the United

States that the law of the land provision was intended to remove arbitrary

power from every branch of the government.[3] One justice declared that "the

framers of the constitution never dreamed of permitting the exercise of

arbitrary power in any department of government."[4] The suggestion that due

process of law was intended to secure the individual from the arbitrary

exercise of the powers of government[5] and that the security of a citizen

against arbitrary legislation rested upon the broader and more solid ground

of natural rights, and was not wholly dependent on those negatives upon the

legislative power contained in the constitution,[6] gave an indication of

possible future interpretations of due process of law. But there were few

occasions to consider these comments or to apply them concretely[7] until a

similar doctrine was adopted by the Supreme Court of the United States, and

made a part of the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Justices

Bradley and Field were among the first to suggest the notion that the

Fourteenth Amendment was intended to be an inhibition against arbitrary

legislative and administrative acts.[8] They pleaded for an extensive

application of the requirement of due process of law to all state acts, and

suggested that if such acts were "arbitrary, oppressive, and unjust," they

might be declared not to be in accord with due process of law.[9]


When judges insisted that "under our institutions, arbitrary power over

another's lawful pursuits is not vested in any man nor in any tribunal,"[10]

due process of law, applied in England only as a guard against executive

usurpation, was destined to become in the United States a bulwark against

arbitrary legislation.[11] This new standard for legislative acts was

applied when it was determined that the validity of statutes was not to be

tested in the federal courts unless "they are clearly inconsistent with some

power granted to the general government or with some right secured by that

instrument or unless they are purely arbitrary in their nature."[12]


The phrase "equal protection of the laws," though not in the Fifth Amendment

of the federal Constitution, and not, as a rule, in the state constitutions,

had been interpreted as a requirement for legislative and executive acts by

certain justices in state and federal courts prior to 1879.[13] It was used

without any clear indication as to the purpose of the phrase in the draft of

the Fourteenth Amendment which was finally adopted, and the courts were

loath to apply its vague content to concrete cases until there was a

determined effort on the part of certain justices to incorporate the natural

rights philosophy and the doctrine of equality of the Declaration of

Independence into the Fourteenth Amendment, in order to condemn acts which

the judges regarded as arbitrary or unreasonable.[14] The movement to

declare void acts judicially construed as arbitrary[15] found the equal

protection clause a supplement to what would otherwise have been construed

as a requirement of due process of law. That due process would ultimately

have been interpreted as involving the equal protection principle is shown

by the fact that statutes regarded as conferring undue favors, class

privileges, or discrimination are seldom attacked on the equal protection

clause alone, but also as a denial of due process of law.


Due process of law and equal protection of the laws, then, combined were

being construed with wide enough scope to prevent all legislative and

administrative acts which the justices regarded as arbitrary and, like

certain other implied limits on legislatures, the equal protection principle

was made an essential part of the concept of due process of law.[16] Hence

acts which were not general in their application to a particular class were

held not to be in accord with the due process and equal protection phrases

of the Fourteenth Amendment.[17]


"The due process clause requires," said Chief Justice Taft,


    that every man shall have the protection of his day in court,
    and the benefit of the general law, a law which hears before
    it condemns, which proceeds not arbitrarily or capriciously
    but upon inquiry, and renders judgment only after trial, so
    that every citizen shall hold his life, liberty, property and
    immunities under the protection of the general rules which
    govern society.[18]


And Justice Holmes believes that state acts interfering with liberty should

be held valid unless "a rational and fair man" would admit that they

necessarily infringe "fundamental principles as they have been understood by

the traditions of our people and our law."[19] But where is the rational and

fair man, what are the fundamental principles, and how are the traditions of

the people to be discovered? Since when has the sole custody of these

principles and traditions been assigned to the judges?


The way in which judges made limitations applicable to legislative action is

admirably shown in one of Cooley's dicta:


    The bills of rights in the American constitutions forbid that
    parties shall be deprived of property except by the law of
    the land; but if the prohibition had been omitted, a legislative
    enactment to pass one man's property over to another
    would nevertheless be void. If the act proceeded upon the
    assumption that such other person was justly entitled to the
    estate, and therefore it was transferred, it would be void,
    because judicial in its nature; and if it proceeded without
    reasons, it would be equally void, as neither legislative nor
    judicial but a mere arbitrary fiat.[20]


Those who defend the application of judicial standards for the justness or

fairness of legislative action claim that it is the only way that unjust

interference, not called for by the public needs, with private property and

personal liberty can be effectively prevented. But what are unjust

interferences with private property, and do these not depend upon changing

times and conditions which may be perceived by legislators as well as by

judges? And who shall determine what the public needs demand, the

representatives of the people or arbiters who have assumed the rôle of

umpires?[21]


2. Acts Contrary to Fundamental Rights are Void.[22] Among the ideas which

have supplemented other phases of the elastic term "due process of law," in

limiting legislative functions, is the doctrine that there are immutable

fundamental rights or principles which no governmental authorities may

invade.


Notions of natural law and of fundamental natural rights, as we have noted,

were among the dominant notions of the leaders of the American Revolution

and of the framers of the first written constitutions in the United States.

Governments, it was believed, were instituted primarily to preserve these

rights. And it was taken for granted that legislative enactments which

contravened such rights were void, though ideas as to how to prevent such

legislative acts or to assure protection to the people against illegal

procedure under them were often indefinite. The assertion by the courts of

the right to review the constitutionality of legislative acts and to become

the special guardians of the written instruments containing assertions of

natural rights gave a new turn to the legal applications of the fundamental

rights philosophy.


It was in connection with the interpretation of the privileges and

immunities guaranteed to the citizens of the several states by the federal

Constitution that the doctrine of fundamental rights was early announced.

Justice Washington said:


    "We feel no hesitation in confining these expressions to those
    privileges and immunities which are, in their nature
    fundamental; which belong, of right, to the citizens of all free
    governments." Though it was regarded as difficult to
    enumerate these fundamental privileges a few were
    suggested, such as the enjoyment of life and of liberty, the
    right to acquire and possess property of every kind, and to
    pursue and obtain happiness and safety, subject to such
    restraints as the government may prescribe for the general
    good.[23] "Standing upon the principles of natural justice,
    upon the fundamental laws of every free government, upon
    the spirit and letter of the Constitution of the United States,"
    Justice Story held invalid a state legislative act which
    attempted to interfere with the vested property rights of a
    corporation.[24] The rather common belief in fundamental
    rights also received his sanction when he called attention to
    the "fundamental maxims of free government," which
    required that the rights of personal liberty and private
    property should be held sacred.[25]


When the doctrines of the Federalists and of conservative thinkers generally

lost ground and were repudiated by all departments of the government,

including the judiciary, in favor of popular theories of political control,

little was heard for several decades of immutable fundamental rights in

state or federal courts.[26]


The doctrine was reaffirmed after the Civil War by Justice Chase[27] and

then by Justice Miller, who insisted that there are rights in every free

government beyond the control of the state and that there are limitations

which grow out of the essential nature of all free governments, "implied

reservations of individual rights, without which the social compact could

not exist, and which are respected by all governments entitled to the

name."[28] All men, thought Justice Field, have certain inalienable rights;

among these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness; in the pursuit

of happiness all avocations, all honors, all positions, are alike open to

everyone; and in the protection of these rights are all equal before the

law.[29]


The eighteenth-century notion of fundamental rights beyond the realm of

government interference and the concept of inalienable rights as formulated

in the Declaration of Independence which, it was thought, governments were

designed to protect, have now been incorporated by means of judicial

construction as essential elements of due process of law and as necessary

principles of the American system of government.[30]


Few lawyers or judges were as frank as Justice Harlan who was among those

applying natural law ideas, when he said: "the courts have rarely, if ever,

felt themselves so restrained by technical rules that they could not find

some remedy, consistent with the law, for acts, whether done by government

or by individual persons, that violated natural justice or were hostile to

the fundamental principles devised for the protection of the essential

rights of property."[31]


Justice Moody was similarly frank when he preferred to rest the decision

regarding exemption from self-incrimination on broader ground than the

strict language of the Constitution and raised the query, "Is it a

fundamental principle of liberty and justice which inheres in the very idea

of free government and is the inalienable right of a citizen of such a

government? If it is, and is of a nature that pertains to process of law,

this court has declared it to be essential to due process of law."[32]


Despite these apparent applications of principles of reason, or of natural

law and natural justice in the opinions of the justices and of the marked

change in the meaning of due process of law, the assertion is repeated

consistently that judges in the decision of cases have nothing to do with

the wisdom, justice, or expediency of legislative acts.[33]


3. Police Regulations must be Reasonable. The extensive limitations which

were inserted in the state constitutions and the implied limitations

developed by the courts placed many restrictions upon the authority of the

states and rendered it difficult to meet the public needs and requirements.

Hence the doctrine of the police power was conceived as a kind of

safety-valve through which the necessary authority for the protection of the

public order, public morals, and public health might be authorized despite

these restrictions.[34] But the exercise of such powers, it was eventually

held, was subject to the requirements of due process of law and equal

protection of the laws and the general necessity of reasonableness. American

courts, following the English practice, held that the by-laws of a municipal

corporation, unless expressly authorized by a legislative act, must be

reasonable, and must not be inconsistent with the general principles of the

common law, particularly those having relation to the liberty of the

individual or the rights of private property.[35] This meant that ordinances

might be held void which were deemed unfair, oppressive, or discriminatory.


State legislatures, also, in their efforts to regulate social and industrial

conditions were held subject to the requirement that "under the mere guise

of police regulations personal rights, and property rights cannot be

arbitrarily invaded, and the determination of the legislature is not final

or conclusive."[36] It was also held for the courts to decide whether a

regulation had in fact some relation to the public health, whether it was

appropriate, and adapted to the end aimed at.[37]


The federal justices, who first refused to interfere with the police powers

of the state under the due process provision, were prevailed upon to adopt

the dictum of the New York court,[38] that the power to regulate is not the

power to destroy,[39] and to render this dictum applicable to all types of

social legislation. A rule of reason test for police regulations extensive

in its scope was also formulated by Justice Peckham.[40]


A state law, therefore, might be held void when enacted to protect the

public health, the public morals, or the public safety if it had "no real or

substantial relation to those objects, or is, beyond all question, a plain,

palpable invasion of rights secured by the fundamental law."[41]


The criteria by which the Supreme Court determines whether a state act is a

legitimate exercise of the police power are:


    1. The object of the legislation must be permissible.


    2. The means must have a substantial relation to the end.


    3. Fundamental rights must not be infringed.


    4. The effect of the enforcement of the law must not be
    arbitrary, unreasonable, or oppressive.[42]


Thus it will be seen that the courts may adopt Locke's dictum and hold that

an act which appears to them unwise is not within the scope of legislative

action. Or they may conclude that the ways and means adopted by the

legislature are not appropriate to accomplish the object intended. If an act

meets these tests it may run afoul of the fundamental rights of the

individual and what are fundamental rights has never been determined.

Finally, it must meet the test of reasonableness, which is the most

difficult of all requirements, for who knows what will appear reasonable to

the judicial mind?[43] It is not surprising then for the conclusion to be

reached, after a thorough analysis of the attempts to apply the criterion of

due process of law to cases arising under the police power, that the

opinions of the Supreme Court "have confused rather than clarified the

subject and that from such attempts have come no rules, standards, or

principles capable of certain applications to concrete cases."[44]


The criteria upon which the court proceeds in such cases, it is observed,

are largely subjective and depend upon the personal, political, and economic

opinions of the justices. The terms "arbitrary," "unreasonable," and

"oppressive" are not defined in the written law and can be applied only "in

the light of the judges' own mental processes."[45] It is here that the

silence of the Constitution speaks in a voice tuned only to judicial ears.


The situation resulting from the application of the general language of the

Fourteenth Amendment to state legislation on social and industrial matters

is thus summarized by Mr. Nesbitt:


    The difficulty with what I have chosen to call the categorical
    view of the due process of law requirement as applied to
    legislation, dealing with social and economic changes, is that
    it extols bare authority at the expense of experience; that it
    results in the deductive application of general principles to
    precise facts often without any accommodation to the
    particular situation out of which the legislation has arisen;
    that it tends to limit the content of the clauses to a fixed,
    unconditional meaning, precluding all flexibility in their
    application; that it construes the due process of law clauses
    not so much as broad guarantees of "relatively fundamental
    rights" as the regulations of a code, as arbitrary abstract
    principles rather than organic rules; and that it excludes
    consideration of public opinion as a fact to be taken into
    account in determining the reasonableness of legislation, thus
    making the opinion of the court as fixed by judicial
    experience the measure of the limit of the legislative function.
    The standard of reasonableness which it would apply is
    remote and traditional.[46]


There is involved in much of the reasoning of the judges in the cases under

the police power an assumption of inherent superiority of the wisdom and

judgments of justices over the judgments of members of the other departments

of government. The legislature, it is asserted, cannot invade the rights of

person or property, under the guise of a police regulation when it is not

such in fact. It is insisted also that it is the province of the judiciary

to determine when personal or property rights have been invaded and whether

a measure is appropriate for the desired object.[47] Constitutions do not

define police regulations which do or do not invade personal or property

rights nor do they give any indication as to the appropriate objects of such

regulations. Police power as a constitutional concept is a judge-made

concept arising from the assumption that legislatures are disposed to

fritter away constitutional inhibitions and that it is the duty of judges to

prevent such legislative depredations. The term "police power" was hit upon

as a convenient phrase for the courts to determine whether a legislative act

which interfered with private rights was reasonable enough to have judicial

approval.


What the whole matter amounts to, we are told, is: "There must be some sort

of reasonable balance between the degree of interference with private rights

and the public benefit which may be expected to flow from that

interference."[48] What is a "reasonable balance," and who is in the best

position to decide this question -- a judge or a legislator -- probably a

judge if the chief object is to preserve private rights, and a legislator if

the public interest and convenience is to be given superior weight?


4. Results of the Extension of the Meaning of Due Process of Law. With

judicial review of legislative enactments applied via due process of law to

the main lines of public regulation of business and economic conditions, it

was not long before the Fourteenth Amendment took its place as the foremost

feature of the federal Constitution, so far as the limitations on the powers

of the states are concerned. Whereas for the first twenty years after the

adoption of the amendment about one case per year on the average arose under

its provisions, it was not long before thirty or more cases were adjudicated

in the same period. In such important fields of state power as eminent

domain, taxation, public utility regulation, and the police power, state and

local acts had been attacked before the Supreme Court in more than six

hundred cases to the year 1910.[49]


To 1910 according to the table of Collins the following questions had been

raised under the Fourteenth Amendment:


    Eminent domain ..................     27 cases


    Taxation ........................... 144 "


    Matters of procedure ........        146 "


    Police power ....................    302 "


Most of the cases which have arisen under this amendment have been decided

since 1896. From 1900 to 1913 there were four hundred and nine opinions or

about thirty one per year. Out of a total of more than six hundred cases

only twenty-eight dealt with the rights of the negro race for whose

protection the amendment was primarily enacted. More than half of the cases

have come to the court on appeals of public utility interests and other

corporate organizations asking protection from the acts of the legislatures

and administrative agencies of the states.[50] Though the amendment was

enacted primarily as a charter of liberty for the negro race it has been

used to a great extent by corporations, public and private, to resist the

efforts toward public regulation and to check the exercise of state

authority through eminent domain, taxation, and the police power.[51]


As a result of such a series of decisions, quasi-legislative in character,

the prohibitions involved in due process of law were held applicable to

substantive law as well as to legal procedure, to executive, administrative,

and judicial acts as well as to legislation, and to corporations as well as

to natural persons.[52] Writing in 1919, Judge Hough believed that "the

direct appeal of property to due process of law had for the most part

failed.... The indirect appeal through liberty is still going on.... But it

is dying, and the courts, when invoked today under the due-process clause,

are doing little more than easing the patient's later days."[53] That this

prediction is not being fulfilled is shown by the fact that since 1920 more

acts in the field of social and economic legislation have been invalidated

under the due process clause than were set aside from 1868 to 1920.[54]


    Phrased in percentages this means that from 1868 to 1912
    the Court held against the legislature in a very little more than
    six per cent of the cases; from 1913 to 1920 in a little more
    than seven per cent of the cases; while since 1920 the Court
    has held against the legislature in twenty-eight per cent of the
    cases. And if we go behind the decisions and look at the
    votes of the individual judges in each case, we will find the
    same startling increase in the number of opinions adverse to
    the validity of legislation under the due process clauses. In
    the period up to 1921 the judicial vote was cast
    approximately ninety per cent in favor of the various statutes
    considered, and only ten per cent against. Since then,
    however, the favorable vote has shrunk to about sixty-nine
    per cent and the adverse vote grown to thirty-one per
    cent.[55]


Evidently the justices regard with increasing seriousness their assumed duty

to guide political action in a safe course so as to avoid the dangers of

economic or social radicalism.


5. Some Examples of Higher Law Concepts in Recent Supreme Court Decisions.

The doctrine of liberty of contract, an inalienable-right product, is now

construed as involved in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments. This doctrine

was applied in a decision of the Supreme Court of the United States by

holding invalid the Minimum Wage Act passed by Congress for the District of

Columbia.[56] Justice Sutherland, rendering the opinion of the court, held

that the right to contract about one's affairs is a part of the liberty of

the individual protected by the Fifth Amendment. Quoting with approval the

much criticized opinion of Justice Peckham in the case of Lochner v. New

York,[57] he concluded that the Act of Congress was


    simply and exclusively a price-fixing law, confined to adult
    women -- who are legally as capable of contracting for
    themselves as men. It forbids two parties having lawful
    capacity -- under penalties as to the employer -- to freely
    contract with one another in respect of the price for which
    that one shall render services to the other in a purely private
    employment where both are willing, perhaps anxious, to
    agree.[58]


The standard for the guidance of the board under the act was regarded so

vague as to be impossible of practical application. It took into account the

necessities of only one party to the contract and it fixed an arbitrary wage

payment and thus interfered with economic laissez faire; altogether the act,

Justice Sutherland declared, was "clearly the product of a naked, arbitrary

exercise of power."[59]


Chief Justice Taft, dissenting, with whom concurred Justice Sanford, took

issue with the contention that there is, in many instances, a substantial

equality as between employer and employee. He admitted that the policy of a

compulsory minimum wage is one on which there is much dispute but he thought

it was "not the function of this court to hold congressional acts invalid

simply because they are passed to carry out economic views which the Court

believes to be unwise or unsound."[60] The principle of the limitation of

liberty of contract was recognized by the court in the regulation of wages

and labor conditions under the police power and it seemed difficult to

understand the difference between regulating the manner and time of payment

of wages or fixing maximum hours of labor and the fixing of a minimum

wage.[61]


In his opinion the Lochner Case was overruled and he expressed surprise at

the attempt of the majority justices to quote the case as a precedent. The

intimation that the controlling effect of earlier opinions had been weakened

by the Nineteenth Amendment was answered by the statement that this

amendment did not change the differences between men and women recognized by

Congress in the passage of this act.


Justice Holmes also dissented and observed that:


    Notwithstanding the deference due to the prevailing
    judgment of the Court, the power of Congress seems
    absolutely free from doubt. The end, to remove conditions
    leading to ill health, immorality, and the deterioration of the
    race, no one would deny to be within the scope of
    constitutional legislation. The means are the means that have
    the approval of Congress, of many states, and of those
    governments from which we have learned our greatest
    lessons. When so many intelligent persons, who have
    studied the matter more than any of us can, have thought
    that the means are effective and are worth the price, it seems
    to me impossible to deny that the belief reasonably may be
    held by reasonable men....


    The earlier decisions upon the same words in the Fourteenth
    Amendment began within our memory, and went no farther
    than an unpretentious assertion of the liberty to follow the
    ordinary callings. Later that innocuous generality was
    expanded into the dogma, liberty of contract. Contract is not
    specially mentioned in the text that we have to construe. It is
    merely an example of doing what you want to do, embodied
    in the word liberty. But pretty much all law consists in
    forbidding men to do some things that they want to do, and
    contract is no more exempt from law than other acts.[62]


The opinions of Justice Van Orsdel of the District of Columbia Court and

Justice Sutherland illustrate the attenuated methods of reasoning involved

in declaring void legislative acts under the phrase "due process of

law."[63] They likewise illustrate the process of judicial interpretation by

which implied limitations on legislative powers are extracted from the

general language of constitutions. It is the method of reasoning which first

discovered a doctrine of vested rights which might be preserved whether or

not constitutions gave such a protection, which found inherent limitations

on legislatures to protect property rights through the terms "public

purpose" and "public use," and which, lacking any express provision, fell

back on the spirit of the constitution or the general principles of free

government to condemn, as Justice Holmes suggests, what "a tribunal of

lawyers does not think about right."[64] Both justices assume certain

fundamental principles and then by what appears to them as "indubitable

demonstration" they conclude that the acts are arbitrary, unreasonable, and

necessarily void -- as contrary to due process of law. Here is an

application of the old natural rights and natural law philosophy, combined

with the mechanical concept of the functions of the court. That there is no

clear dividing line between arbitrary restraint and reasonable regulation;

that the determination of the dividing line is largely one of policy on

which the judgment of the legislature with the full facts before it ought to

be relatively sound, or can be readily changed, if found unsound; and that a

court is overstepping the bounds of its legitimate authority to pass on the

wisdom or folly of the economic policy of wage legislation, did not make any

difference to the justices imbued with the doctrine of fundamental

principles or of a modern Naturrecht.


Conceived in the spirit of individualism and laissez faire characteristic of

the pioneer conditions which prevailed in a large part of the country more

than a generation ago, the concept of liberty of contract as an absolute

right is ill suited to the industrial conditions now prevailing in many

American communities.[65] If there is any field in which the precept should

prevail that law is a progressive science, that rights are subject to

restrictions and limitations as the social interest may require, and that

the determination as to what restrictions are on the whole wise and salutary

belongs primarily to the legislature, it is the growing field of the

necessary regulations and adjustments in the wage contract. A minimum wage

law may or may not be wise from the economic or social viewpoint. But the

best way to determine its wisdom or unwisdom would appear to be to give it a

trial under terms and conditions laid down by a legislative body which could

change those conditions, if the act proved unwise after a fair trial. For

the court to prevent such experimentation, with the care, foresight, and

experience manifested in the enactment and administration of labor laws,

under an attenuated view of due process of law, protecting liberty and

property, is to place too heavy a burden upon the judiciary and to throttle

the avenue of advance for government to meet the growing needs of modern

economic and industrial society.


When the bakers resisted the enforcement of a Nebraska statute providing for

standard sizes for loaves of bread with an allowance for an excess over the

specified standards, as unnecessary, unreasonable, and arbitrary, the

Supreme Court held, Justice Butler rendering the opinion, that the state may

not "under the guise of protecting the public arbitrarily interfere with

private business or prohibit lawful occupations or impose unreasonable and

unnecessary restrictions upon them." The provisions of an act must have, he

demanded, a reasonable relation to the protection desired to be

accomplished.[66] Regarding the act as essentially unreasonable and

arbitrary it was held void as contrary to the Fourteenth Amendment.


Justice Brandeis, dissenting, stated the problem of the application of the

rule of reason in such cases as follows:


    With the wisdom of the legislation we have, of course, no
    concern. But, under the due process clause as construed,
    we must determine whether the prohibition of excess
    weights can reasonably be deemed necessary; whether the
    prohibition can reasonably be deemed an appropriate means
    of preventing short weights and incidental unfair practices;
    and whether compliance with the limitation prescribed can
    reasonably be deemed practicable. The determination of
    these questions involves an enquiry into facts. Unless we
    know the facts on which the legislators may have acted, we
    cannot decide whether they were (or whether their measures
    are) unreasonable, arbitrary, or capricious.[67]


After an extensive summary of evidence showing the practical necessity of

the prohibition of excess weights as a means of preventing short weights, he

concluded:


    The evidence contained in the record in this case is,
    however, ample to sustain the validity of the statute. There is
    in the record some evidence in conflict with it. The
    legislature and the lower courts have, doubtless, considered
    that. But with this conflicting evidence we have no concern.
    It is not our province to weigh evidence. Put at its highest,
    our function is to determine, in the light of all facts which
    may enrich our knowledge and enlarge our understanding,
    whether the measure, enacted in the exercise of an
    unquestioned police power and of a character inherently
    unobjectionable, transcends the bounds of reason. That is,
    whether the provision as applied is so clearly arbitrary or
    capricious that legislators acting reasonably could not have
    believed it to be necessary or appropriate for the public
    welfare.


    To decide, as a fact, that the prohibition of excess weights
    "is not necessary for the protection of the purchasers against
    imposition and fraud by short weights"; that it "is not
    calculated to effectuate that purpose"; and that it "subjects
    bakers and sellers of bread" to heavy burdens, is, in my
    opinion, an exercise of the powers of a super-legislature --
    not the performance of the constitutional function of judicial
    review.[68]


Again the majority of the court, as in the Minimum Wage Case, refused to

accept the judgment of the legislature on the facts and then condemned the

policy determined by the legislative body to deal with the facts.


The vacillation and uncertainty involved in according a general power of

review over state acts to judges who are likely to be unfamiliar with the

local conditions which prompted the acts are shown in many recent cases.

There are cases in which the judges indicate a disposition to place the

burden of proof upon those who attack state statutes and to defer to the

judgment of state authorities, legislative and judicial.[69] When this

tendency was beginning to be considered as a rule of law,[70] the justices

again showed an inclination to resort primarily to their own judgments of

facts and local conditions. The refusal to give special consideration to

local conditions, is indicated in the New York Theater Ticket Case.[71]


The New York legislature passed a law to remedy notorious abuses in the

resale of theater tickets, because in its judgment the matter was of

sufficient public interest to warrant public regulation. But the Supreme

Court declared the law void on the ground that the act was an unwarranted

interference with a private business. "The mere declaration by the

legislature," said Justice Sutherland, "that a particular kind of property

or business is affected with a public interest is not conclusive upon the

question of the validity of the regulation. The matter is one which is

always open to judicial inquiry."[72]


Justice Holmes, who has expressed more frequently and insistently than

any other justice the view that the justices have substituted their views of

public policy for those of the legislature, said in a dissenting opinion,


    I think the proper course is to recognize that a state
    legislature can do whatever it sees fit to do unless it is
    restrained by some express prohibition in the Constitution of
    the United States or of the State, and that courts should be
    careful not to extend such prohibitions beyond their obvious
    meaning by reading into them conceptions of public policy
    that the particular court may happen to entertain.... I am far
    from saying that I think this particular law a wise and rational
    provision. That is not my affair. But if the people of the State
    of New York speaking their authorized voice say they want
    it, I see nothing in the Constitution of the United States to
    prevent their having their will.[73]


Reasonable as this opinion may seem, the majority of the Supreme Court have

declared otherwise. Again, when Minnesota attempted to prohibit buyers of

dairy products from discriminating between localities, the majority of the

Supreme Court refused to accept the legislative determination of facts and

held the law invalid as an unwarranted interference with freedom of

contract.[74]


The way in which the Supreme Court makes law in interpreting the Fourteenth

Amendment is illustrated in the gradual inclusion of the first eight

amendments, which were held to apply only to federal law and procedure,[75]

as a part of the Fourteenth Amendment -- and hence as limitations on state

laws and procedure. Subsequent to the Barron Case it was held frequently

that the provisions of the Bill of Rights of the federal Constitution were

not applicable to state action. This opinion was reaffirmed in recent

decisions when it was asserted that "neither the Fourteenth Amendment nor

any other provision of the Constitution of the United States imposes upon

the states any restriction about freedom of speech."[76] But three years

later Justice Sanford, upholding the validity of the New York Criminal

Anarchy Law, said:


    "We may and do assume that freedom of speech and of the
    press -- which are protected by the First Amendment from
    abridgement by Congress -- are among the fundamental
    personal rights and liberties protected by the due process
    clause of the Fourteenth Amendment from impairment by
    the States."[77]


Repeated efforts to secure protection from the federal courts in such

matters as state interferences with the right of suffrage, the right of

assembly, the right to bear arms, the right of impartial trial, the right

against cruel and unusual punishment, the right against compulsory

self-incrimination[78] were given little countenance prior to 1925. In 1925

it is assumed without argument or discussion that the fundamental rights and

liberties of the first eight amendments are protected by the due process

clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. "Despite arguments to the contrary which

had seemed to me persuasive," said Justice Brandeis,


    it is settled that the due process clause of the Fourteenth
    Amendment applies to matters of substantive law as well as
    to matters of procedure. Thus all fundamental rights
    comprised within the term liberty are protected by the
    federal Constitution from invasion by the states. The right of
    free speech, the right to teach, and the right of assembly are,
    of course, fundamental rights.[79]


Justice Stone, speaking of the holding of the Supreme Court that the Sherman

Anti-Trust Law prohibits only such restraints upon interstate commerce as

are unreasonable, says: "Reasonableness is not a concept of definite and

unchanging content. Its meaning necessarily varies in the different fields

of the law, because it is used as a convenient summary of the dominant

considerations which control in the application of legal doctrines." And

recognizing the uncertainty of the test of reasonableness as a legal

concept, he continues:


    Moreover, in the absence of express legislation requiring it,
    we should hesitate to adopt a construction making the
    difference between legal and illegal conduct in the field of
    business relations depend upon so uncertain a test as
    whether prices are reasonable -- a determination which can
    be satisfactorily made only after a complete survey of our
    economic organization and a choice between rival
    philosophies.[80]


If such complete economic surveys had been made would a ten-hour bakeshop

law, or a minimum wage law as well as a number of other state and federal

acts have been declared void?


When the Fourteenth Amendment was construed to prohibit state legislative

and administrative acts which were deemed arbitrary, to prevent any

interference with fundamental rights, to require that all state and local

police regulations must be reasonable, and the justices determined that it

was their duty to examine the facts on which state legislative and

administrative policies were based as well as the ends to be accomplished by

regulation, a change in the American system of government was effected, the

results of which are only beginning to be realized. The change has its roots

in the political and legal thinking of earlier periods but few could have

surmised what a significant turn in political practice was to follow from a

slow and silent revolution in constitutional interpretation.[81]




1. See F. W. Maitland, "An Historical Sketch of Liberty and Equality" in

Collected Papers (ed. by H. A. L. Fisher, Cambridge, 1911), I, 80, 83.


2. Cf. Mott, Due Process of Law, chaps. 3 and 4.


3. For use of the terms "arbitrary" or "unreasonable" in passing on the

validity of legislative acts in the United States, consult Robert P.

Reeder, "Is Unreasonable Legislation Unconstitutional";" University of

Pennsylvania Law Review, LXII (January, 1914), 191.


4. See comments of Attorney General Haywood in State v. -- 29, 30 (N. C.,

1794) and of Justice Peck in State v. Cooper, 2 Yerg. (Tenn., 1831) 599,

611. The law of the land provision, Justice Nott thought, was intended "in

some way or other, to operate as a check upon the exercise of arbitrary

power." Dunn v. City Council of Charleston, Harper's Law Reports. 189, 199

(1824). Chief Justice Gibson in Norman v. Heist, 5 W. & S. (Pa., 1843) 171,

173 claimed that the design of the convention which framed the state

constitution was to exclude arbitrary power from every branch of the

government. The exercise of a governmental power which is arbitrary is void,

according to Justice Campbell, dissenting in Sears v. Cottrell, 5 Mich. 251,

281 (1858).


5. Justice Johnson in Bank of Columbia v. Okely, 4 Wheat. 234, 244 (1819).

This dictum of Justice Johnson was cited and approved by Justice Gray in

Scott v. McNeal in denying to a state court the right to sell property for

the payment of debts without notice to a party absent from the state for

seven years. 154 U. S. 34, 45 (1893).


6. Justice Mason in White v. White, 5 Barb. 474, 484 (1849).


7. See, however, Chief Justice Hines in Barbour v. Louisville Board of

Trade, 82 Ky. 645, 648 (1885).


8. "The principal, if not the sole, purpose of its [the Fourteenth

Amendment] prohibitions is to prevent any arbitrary invasion by state

authority of the rights of persons and property." Justice Field, dissenting

in Butchers' Union v. Crescent City Co., 111 U. S. 746, 759 (1883).


9. Justice Bradley, concurring in Davidson v. New Orleans, 96 U. S. 97, 107

(1877).


10. Justice Field in ex parte Wall., 107 U. S. 265, 303 (1882). And again,

he asserted, the Fourteenth Amendment undoubtedly intended that there should

be "no arbitrary deprivation of life or liberty, or arbitrary spoliation of

property," and that equal protection and security should be given to all

under like circumstances in the enjoyment of their personal and civil

rights. Barbier v. Connolly, 113 U. S. 27, 31 (1885). Cf. also Stuart v.

Palmer, 74 N. Y. 183, 190 (1878), in which a New York justice regarded the

due process clause as a limitation upon the arbitrary exercise of

legislative powers. "The legislature may not, under the guise of protecting

the public interests, arbitrarily interfere with private business, or impose

unusual and unnecessary restrictions upon lawful occupations." Justice Brown

in Lawton v. Steele, 152 U. S. 133, 137 (1894).


11. Hurtado v. California, 110 U. S. 516, 532 (1884). Beginning with

Davidson v. New Orleans, 96 U. S. 97 (1878), Mr. Willis asserts, Coke's

doctrine of a fundamental law superior to all legislation was made a part of

due process of law. Hugh Evander Willis, "Due Process of Law under the

United States Constitution," Univ. of Pa. Law Rev., LXXIV (February, 1926),

331, 335. For applications of the new interpretation see Chicago, Milwaukee

and St. Paul Ry. Co. v. Minnesota, 134 U. S. 418 (1890); Allgeyer v.

Louisiana, 165 U. S. 578 (1897); and Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45

(1905).


12. Justice Harlan in Chicago, Burlington and Quincy Ry. Co. v. Chicago, 166

U. S. 226, 234 (1896), and Chicago, Rock Island & Pac. Ry. Co. v. Arkansas,

219 U. S. 453, 465 (1910).


13. Cf. Holden v. James, 11 Mass. 396, 405 (1814) and supra, p. 111.


14. Opinions of Justices Field in Barbier v. Connolly, 113 U. S. 27, 32

(1885), and Matthews in Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356, 369, 370 (1886).

Said Justice Matthews: "When we consider the nature and the theory of our

institutions of government, the principles upon which they are supposed to

rest, and review the history of their development, we are constrained to

conclude that they do not mean to leave room for the play and action of

purely personal and arbitrary power." Chief Justice Fuller confirmed the

rights of the states to deal with criminals within their borders provided no

person or class of persons was denied equal and impartial justice and

provided state procedure did not subject "the individual to the arbitrary

exercise of the powers of government unrestrained by the established

principles of private right and distributive justice." Leeper v. Texas, 139

U. S. 462, 468 (1890).


15. The term "arbitrary" is vague enough in its connotations to give the

widest latitude for a judicial censorship. It may mean acts not governed by

any fixed rules, or which are capricious, unfair, absolute, despotic,

tyrannical, or irresponsible. It is obvious that personal and partisan

inclinations will have great weight in determining whether legislative

enactments come within one of these indefinite categories.


16. Upholding a New York law providing for capital punishment by

electrocution, Chief Justice Fuller said that the Fourteenth Amendment

required that the action of the states be "exerted within the limits of

those fundamental principles of liberty and justice which lie at the base of

all our civil and political institutions. Undoubtedly the amendment forbids

any arbitrary deprivation of life, liberty, or property, and secures equal

protection to all under like circumstances in the enjoyment of their

rights." In re Kemmler, 136 U. S. 436, 448 (1889). See also Justice Moody in

Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U. S. 78, 100 (1908).


17. Classification "must always rest upon some difference which bears a

reasonable and just relation to the act in respect to which classification

is proposed, and can never be made arbitrarily and without any such basis...

but arbitrary selection can never be justified by calling it

classification." Justice Harlan in Connolly v. Union Sewer Pipe Co., 184 U.

S. 540, 560 (1902), citing the opinion of Justice Brewer in Gulf, Colorado

and Santa Fé Railway v. Ellis, 165 U. S. 150, 155, 159 (1896). Cf., also,

Justice Day in Southern Ry. Co. v. Greene, 216 U. S. 400, 417 (1909). For

state cases declaring arbitrary police regulations void, cf. Mott, op cit.,

p. 338.


18. Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U. S. 312, 332 (1924). Mr. Reeder suggests that

the practice of declaring legislative acts void because unreasonable, may be

regarded as more nearly related to the old idea of natural justice than to

the due process of law provision Op. cit., p. 200.


19. Dissenting opinion in Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45, 76 (1904).


20. Cooley, Constitutional Limitations (8th ed., 1927), pp. 356, 357. If no

other grounds can be discovered to prohibit legislative action, the people

have reserved the power to themselves. Whether an act is or is not arbitrary

depends upon the conditions prevailing at the time. Justice Pound in People

v. La Fetra, 230 N. Y. 429, 444 ff.; 130 N. E. 601 (1921); Justice Holmes in

Pennsylvania Coal Co. v. Mahon, 260 U. S. 393, 413 (1922); and Emergency

Rent Cases -- Block v. Hirsch, 256 U. S. 135 (1921) and Levy Leasing Co. v.

Siegel, 258 U. S. 242 (1922).


21. See Reeder, op. cit., pp. 191, 192, for cases in which the Supreme Court

has suggested that action would violate the due process of law provision, if

unreasonable or arbitrary, and in which the court has intimated that it will

pass on the necessity or desirability of legislative or administrative

action.


Referring to the claim that an order of the Interstate Commerce Commission

based upon its findings of fact was conclusive, Justice Lamar said: "A

finding without evidence is arbitrary and baseless.... Such authority,

however beneficently exercised in one case could be injuriously exerted in

another, is inconsistent with rational justice, and comes under the

Constitution's condemnation of all arbitrary exercise of power." Int. Com.

Comm. v. Louisville & Nashville R. R., 227 U. S. 88, 91 (1912).


"The purpose of the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment is

to secure every person within the State's jurisdiction against intentional

and arbitrary discrimination." Chief Justice Tatt in Sioux City Bridge v.

Dakota County, 260 U. S. 441, 445 (1922), or state procedure in assessments

for local improvements must not be "palpably arbitrary or a plain abuse."

Justice Holmes in Gast Realty Co. v. Schneider Granite Co., 240 U. S. 55, 58

(1915).


Judgments obtained by fraud or without service are not erroneous and not

voidable but "upon principles of natural justice, and under the due process

clause of the Fourteenth Amendment are absolutely void." Justice Lamar in

Simon v. Southern Ry. Co., 236 U. S. 115, 122 (1915). [Italics by the

author.]


22. For an analysis of cases affirming the doctrine of fundamental rights

and of the incorporation of this doctrine in the due process of law clause,

see Francis W. Bird, "The Evolution of Due Process of Law in the Decisions

of the United States Supreme Court," Columbia Law Review, XIII (January,

1913), 37.


23. Corfield v. Coryell, 4 Wash. C. C. 371, 380-382 (1823), Fed. Cas. No.

3230.


24. Terrett v. Taylor, 9 Cranch, 43, 51 (1815); see reference to "republican

principles" by Justice Chase in Calder v. Bull, 3 Dallas, 388 (1798).


25. Wilkinson v. Leland, 2 Pet. 627, 657 (1829); for extract from Story's

opinion cf. supra, p 94.


26. Occasional references may, of course, be found to what Daniel Webster,

in arguing the Dartmouth College Case, called "the great principles of

republican liberty and of the social compact," or to the "eternal principles

of justice which no government has a right to disregard." Justice Green in

Bank of State v. Cooper, 2 Yerg. 599, 603 (1831). "There is a fundamental

principle of right and justice, inherent in the nature and spirit of the

social compact... that rises above and restrains and sets bounds to the

power of legislation," said Chief Justice Buchanan in Regents v. Williams, 9

G. & J. 365, 408 (1838). Cooley thought certain "fundamental rights" when

inserted in a constitution operated as a limitation on the legislature

without any express provisions. Constitutional Limitations (1st ed., 1868),

and People v. Hurlbut, 24 Mich. 44, 97-98 (1871).


27. "There are, undoubtedly, fundamental principles of morality and justice

which no legislature is at liberty to disregard." License Tax Cases, 5 Wall.

462, 469 (1866).


28. Loan Association v. Topeka, 20 Wall. 655, 663 (1874); see also Justice

Harlan in Madisonville T. Co. v. St. Bernard M. Co., 196 U. S. 239, 251, 252

(1904); and Justice Brown in Holden v. Hardy, 169 U. S. 366, 389 (1898),

wherein "certain immutable principles of justice" are declared to "inhere in

the very idea of a free government"; and Benson v. Mayer, 10 Barb. 223, 245

(1850), in which reference was made to "the great principles of Eternal

Justice, which lie at the foundation of all free governments." To Justice

Swayne they are the "conservative principles which lie at the foundation of

all free government," St. Louis v. The Ferry Co., 11 Wall. 423, 429 (1870);

and to the Wisconsin Supreme Court they are "a part of the inherent rights

which governments under our conception are established to conserve,"

Nunnemacher v. State, 129 Wis. 190, 197-202 (1907). See also Justice

Knowlton in Commonwealth v. Perry, 155 Mass. 117, 121 (1891), and Justice

Deemer in State v. Barker, 116 Ia. 96, 105 (1902).


29. Cummings v. Missouri, 4 Wall. 277, 321 (1886). The Fourteenth Amendment,

according to Justice Field, "was intended to give practical effect to the

Declaration of 1776 of inalienable rights which are the gift of the Creator,

which the law does not confer, but only recognizes." Slaughter-House Cases,

16 Wall. 36, 105 (1872). Agreeing with this opinion, Justice Harlan said

that since the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, "the privileges and

immunities specified in the first ten amendments as belonging to the people

of the United States are equally protected by the constitution." Dissent in

Maxwell v. Dow, 176 U. S. 581, 616 (1899). And again he said, "I go further

and hold that the privileges of free speech and of free press, belonging to

every citizen of the United States, constitute essential parts of every

man's liberty, and are protected against violation by that clause of the

Fourteenth Amendment forbidding any state to deprive any person of his

liberty, without due process of law." Patterson v. Colorado, 205 U. S. 454,

456 (1906). Compare this view with the majority opinion of Justice Sanford

in Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652 (1925); cf. infra, p. 193. Speaking

through one of the champions of individualism, the Supreme Court held on

another occasion that the Fourteenth Amendment "simply furnishes an

additional guaranty against any encroachment by the states upon the

fundamental rights which belong to every citizen as a member of society."

Chief Justice Waite in United States v. Cruikshank, 92 U. S. 542, 554

(1875); see reference to "immutable principles of liberty and justice" in

Hurtado v. California, 110 U. S. 516, 535 (1884), also Justice Day in Watson

v. Maryland, 218 U. S. 173, 177 (1910). For comment as to the way in which

the pursuit of the immutable principles of justice in connection with the

concept of due process of law leads into the "fields of speculation

cultivated by writers on the law of nature and the nebulous natural rights

of man," see L. P. McGehee, Due Process of Law, pp. 38, 57 ff.


30. For a summary of citations that the fundamental rights of the citizen

are inviolable, cf. Robert P. Reeder, "Constitutional and

Extra-Constitutional Restraints," Univ. of Pa. Law Rev., LXI (May, 1913),

441, 452. The emerging concept of liberty of contract was soon to be grouped

with the undefined fundamental rights. "No proposition is now more firmly

settled," thought Justice Rapallo, "than that it is one of the fundamental

rights and privileges of every American citizen to adopt and follow such

lawful industrial pursuit, not injurious to the community, as he may see

fit." People v. Marx, 99 N. Y. 377, 386 (1885). "There are certain

fundamental rights of every citizen which are recognized in the organic law

of all our tree American states. A statute which violates any of these

rights is unconstitutional and void even though the enactment of it is not

expressly forbidden.... The right to acquire, possess, and protect property

includes the right to make reasonable contracts, which shall be under the

protection of law." Commonwealth v. Perry, 155 Mass. 117, 125 (1891). The

federal courts can only interfere when fundamental rights guaranteed by the

federal Constitution are violated, Justice McKenna in Ballard v. Hunter, 204

U. S. 241, 262 (1907); Justice Day in Rogers v. Peck, 199 U. S. 423, 434

(1905), and in Franklin v. South Carolina, 218 U. S. 161, 164, 165 (1910);

"the limit of the full control which the state has in the proceedings of its

courts both in civil and criminal cases, is subject only to the

qualification that such procedure must not work a denial of fundamental

rights or conflict with specific and applicable provisions of the federal

Constitution." Justice Peckham in West v. Louisiana, 104 U. S. 258, 263

(1904); see also Waters-Pierce Oil Co. v. Texas, 212 U. S. 86, 107 (1009).

Legislative acts, according to Chief Justice Taft, are not due process which

are not in accord with the fundamental principle of equality of application

of the law. Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U. S. 312, 332 (1921). Judge Dillon

thought the value of the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment

consisted primarily "in the great fundamental principles of right and

justice, which it embodies and makes part of the organic law of the nation."

The Laws and Jurisprudence of England and America (1894), pp. 208-212. "The

great fundamental rights," said Judge Dillon," guaranteed by [American]

constitutions are life, liberty, contracts and property." Ibid., p 203. One

can readily discover that judicial construction had an extraordinarily

large share in giving this sort of a content to the meaning of the

Fourteenth Amendment.


31. Monongahela B. Co. v. United States, 216 U. S. 177, 195 (1910).


32. Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U. S. 78, 106 (1908). "We cannot interfere

[with a judgment of a state court] unless the judgment amounts to mere

arbitrary or capricious exercise of power, or is in clear conflict with

those fundamental principles which have been established in our systems of

jurisprudence for the protection and enforcement of private rights." Justice

McReynolds in American Ry. Express Co. v. Kentucky, 273 U. S. 269, 273

(1927).


33. For an extensive list of citations that the Supreme Court has no right

to inquire into the wisdom or justice of the acts of the federal or state

governments, see Robert P. Reeder, "Constitutional and Extra-Constitutional

Restraints," Univ. of Pa. Law Rev., LXI (May, 1913), 441, 446, 456.

Regarding the statements of justices relating to inalienable rights,

fundamental rights, and rights which grow out of the essential nature of

free governments, Mr. Reeder thinks "it is sufficient to say that the

premises upon which they are based have been abandoned by thoughtful men for

over a century, [and] that those statements are against the vast weight of

direct authority." For another summary of judicial opinions that courts may

not pass on the justice or expediency of legislative acts, consult Cooley,

Constitutional Limitations (8th ed.), I, 341 ff.


34. Cooley, Constitutional Limitations (8th ed.), chap. 21; also Freund, The

Police Power: Public Policy and Constitutional Rights (Chicago, 1904),

especially chap. 1.


35. Dillon, Municipal Corporations (5th ed.), sec. 589.


36. Justice Earle, in re Jacobs, 98 N. Y. 98, no (1885). Due process of law,

as a limitation on the police power of the federal government, was suggested

by Chief Justice Taney in Dred Scott v. Stanford, 19 How. 393, 450 (1856)

and referred to in several dissenting opinions but was consistently

repudiated by the federal justices. Justice Field expressed the prevailing

sentiment when he declared that the Fourteenth Amendment was not "designed

to interfere with the power of the state, sometimes termed its police

power." Barbier v. Connolly, 113 U. S. 27, 31 (1885). For reference to

additional cases, see Mott, op. cit., pp. 334, 335.


37. Justice Peckham in People v. Gibson, 109 N. Y. 389, 400 ff. (1888). Cf.

as to the definition of the term "liberty," citing chiefly Justice Field's

opinions in the Supreme Court and Justice Andrews' opinion in Bertholf v.

O'Reilly, 74 N. Y. 509 (1878); in re Jacobs, supra; and People v. Marx, 99

N. Y. 377 (1885).


38. Wynehamer v. State of New York, 13 N. Y. 378, 392 ff. (1856).


39. Chief Justice Waite in Stone v. Farmers' Loan and Trust Co., 116 U. S.

307, 331 (1886) and Justice Brewer in Reagan v. Farmers' Loan and Trust Co.,

154 U. S. 362, 397 (1893).


40. Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45, 56 (1898).


41. Referring to the decision of the Supreme Court in Yick Wo v. Hopkins,

118 U. S. 356 (1885) in which a municipal ordinance was held void because

its administration was regarded as arbitrary and discriminatory, Justice

Brown said: "While this was the case of a municipal ordinance, a like

principle has been held to apply to acts of a state legislature passed in

the exercise of the police power." Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537, 550

(1895). See also Justice Peckham in Lake Shore and Michigan Southern Ry. Co.

v. Smith, 173 U. S. 684, 689 (1899), and in W. M. & P. R. R. Co. v.

Jacobsen, 179 U. S. 287, 297 (1900). The police power is subject to judicial

review and property rights cannot be wrongfully destroyed by arbitrary

enactments. Justice Day in Dobbins v. Los Angeles, 195 U. S. 223, 236

(1904). Cf. also Justice Harlan in Jacobsen v. Massachusetts, 197 U. S. 11,

31 (1904); cases cited to sustain this view are Mugler v. Kansas, 123 U. S.

623, 661 (1887); Minnesota v. Barber, 136 U. S. 313, 320 (1889); Atkin v.

Kansas, 191 U. S. 207, 223 (1903). "The principle involved in these

decisions," said Justice Hughes, "is that where the legislative action is

arbitrary and has no reasonable relation to a purpose which it is competent

for government to effect, the legislature transcends the limits of its

power." Chicago, Burlington & Quincy Ry. Co. v. McGuire, 219 U. S. 549, 569

(1910).


The general result is that specific provisions of constitutions are likely

to be enforced literally but indefinite provisions such as due process of

law and the equal protection of the laws will be applied so as to prohibit

governmental acts which are considered as against natural justice.


No proceeding may be declared invalid "unless in conflict with some special

inhibitions of the Constitution, or against natural justice." Justice Brewer

in Arndt v. Griggs, 134 U. S. 316, 321 (1890). "Under the Fourteenth

Amendment, the legislature is bound to provide a method for the assessment

and collection of taxes that shall not be inconsistent with natural

justice." Justice Brown in Turpin v. Lemon, 187 U. S. 51, 60 (1902).


42. "A police measure must fairly tend to accomplish the purpose of its

enactment, and must not go beyond the reasonable demands of the occasion."

Cooley, Constitutional Limitations (8th ed.), II, 1231.


43. Thomas Reed Powell, "The Judiciality of Minimum Wage Legislation,"

Harvard Law Review, XXXVII (March, 1924), 545.


44. Ray A. Brown, "Due Process of Law, Police Power, and the Supreme Court,"

Harv. Law Rev., XL (May, 1927), 943, 966.


45. Brown, op. cit., p. 956. President Goodnow quotes Professor Seager's

conclusion that "the question of the constitutionality of a restrictive

labor law is inseparably connected with the question of the wisdom of such a

law." And then he adds:


"What the courts actually do in cases in which they declare a law of this

sort unconstitutional, is to substitute their ideas of wisdom for those of

the legislature, although they continually say that this is not the case."

Social Reform and the Constitution (New York, 1911), p. 247, and Henry R.

Seager, "The Attitude of American Courts toward Restrictive Labor

Legislation," Political Science Quarterly, XIX (December 1904), 589.


46 James L. Nesbitt, "Due Process of Law and Opinion," Col. Law Rev., XXVI

(January, 1926), 22, 27. The categorical view of due process of law, Mr.

Nesbitt thinks, is best illustrated in the majority opinion in the Minimum

Wage Case, Adkins v. Children's Hospital, 261 U. S. 525 (1923). When the

Supreme Court, under the due process clause, performs "the function of

umpiring the contest between competing social forces" Mr. Nesbitt finds that

three attitudes are in evidence: first, an abstract standard to determine

the line between reasonable regulation and arbitrary restraint, e. g.,

Justice Sutherland's opinion in the Minimum Wage Case; second, a personal

standard of the court, such as that of Chief Justice Taft and Justice

Sanford in the same case; and third, a standard of what others have declared

reasonable; see Justice Holmes in dissent, Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S.

45, 76 (1898).


47. Legislatures may use only such means as are reasonably designed to deal

with existing conditions, Herlihy v. Donahue, 52 Mont. 601, 610, 161 Pac.

164 (1916); also Mott, op. cit., p. 539. On the way in which the "silence of

the original Constitution utters restraints," see T. R. Powell, "Due Process

Tests of State Taxation," Univ. of Pa. Law Rev., LXXIV (March, 1926), 423,

573.


48. Mott, op. cit., p. 539.


49. Charles Wallace Collins, The Fourteenth Amendment and the States

(Boston, 1912), p. 183. See also summary of Judge Hough in Harv. Law Rev.,

XXXII (January, 1919), 229, where it is noted that from 1868 to the 1910

term of the Supreme Court there were more than four hundred cases

interpreting due process of law alone and less than one hundred before 1883.

From 1890 to 1900 there were one hundred and ninety-seven appeals under the

recent cases relating to corporations, with public service companies

predominating.


50. See Collins, op. cit., p. 183.


51. The Supreme Court, says Professor Commons, has legislated by definition:

"It changed the meaning of due process of law and thus amended the federal

and every state constitution. It changed the meaning of property and liberty

as used in the Fourteenth Amendment and thus took over from the states the

final determination of what was due process of law in the regulation of

property and business." Legal Foundations of Capitalism, p. 355. The change

in the court's interpretation of the term "due process of law," Mr. Willis

thinks, was brought about "through the efforts of corporations; through a

change in the personnel of the bench, and through the personal activity of

Justice Field, who always championed this doctrine and who strangely, in

writing an opinion for the Supreme Court, cited his own opinion while a

circuit judge as the opinion of the Supreme Court." Minneapolis Ry. Co. v.

Beckwith, 129 U. S. 26 (1898); "Due Process of Law under the United States

Constitution," Univ. of Pa. Law Rev., LXXIV, 337; and County of San Mateo v.

Southern Pacific Ry. Co., 13 Fed. 722 (1882).


52. Willis, Univ. of Pa. Law Rev., LXXIV, 338. Mr. Willis claims that by

attacking all forms of state legislation before the Supreme Court

corporations are attempting to undermine our dual form of government. Ibid.,

p. 342. The Fourteenth Amendment, in the judgment of Mr. Coffins, was to be

a charter of liberty for human rights, but it operates today to protect

primarily the rights of property. It has become the Magna Carta of organized

capital. It "gives to the federal government undefined and illimitable

control over every phase of state activity. It throws into the hands of the

Supreme Court of the United States more power over the states than does all

the rest of the Constitution combined." Collins, op. cit., pp. 146 ff.


53. "Due Process of Law -- Today," Harv. Law Rev., XXXII, 218, 233. For

similar judgments regarding the decline of significance of this phrase,

consult Charles Warren, "The Progressiveness of the United States Supreme

Court," Col. Law Rev., XIII (April, 1913), 294, and Robert E. Cushman, "The

Social and Economic Interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment," Michigan

Law Review, XX (May, 1922), 737, 757 ff.


54. Ray A. Brown, op. cit., pp. 943 ff.


55. Ibid., pp. 944, 945.


56. Adkins v. Children's Hospital, 261 U. S. 525 (1923). The committees of

both Houses of Congress unanimously recommended the legislation, House Rep.

No. 571 and Senate Rep. No. 562, 65th Congress, 2d Session. The House of

Representatives passed the bill without opposition, and only twelve votes

were recorded against it in the Senate, vol. LVI, Cong. Rec., Pt. 9, pp.

8875 ff.; Pt. 10, pp. 10278 ff.; Pt. 12, pp. 604 ff. In the consideration of

this case some extracts are used from an editorial note by the writer in

Texas Law Review, II (December, 1923), 99.


57. 198 U. S. 45 (1904), It is a well-known fact that in the attempts of the

federal courts to define due process of law there has been much wavering and

uncertainty, and dissenting opinions have been prevalent. The court seldom

reverses itself in the interpretation of due process -- it explains,

distinguishes, or modifies. The effect is often a reversal in whole or in

part. The uncertainties and misapprehensions are apparent in the general

impression of the bench and bar that the majority opinion in the Lochner

Case had been overruled, and that the court had adopted the minority views

of Justice Holmes and the reiteration of the majority views in that case by

Justice Sutherland, rendering the opinion in Adkins v. Children's Hospital.

See Fletcher Dobyns, "Justice Holmes and the Fourteenth Amendment," Illinois

Law Review, XIII (June, 1918), 71, 92, and Cardozo, The Nature of the

Judicial Process (New Haven, 1922), p. 79.


58. 261 U. S. 554, 555. Referring to Justice Sutherland's views on the

freedom of contract in the Minimum Wage Case, Powell remarks, "It represents

his personal views of desirable governmental policy. Those views are shared

by many others, but they are not written into the Constitution of the United

States except as judges from time to time have inscribed them there." "The

Judiciality of Minimum Wage Legislation," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVII (March,

1924), 545, 555, 556.


59. 261 U. S. 559.


60. Ibid., 562.


61. See Holden v. Hardy, 169 U. S. 336 (1897), limiting employment of

workmen in mines to eight hours per day; Patterson v. The Eudora, 190 U. S.

169 (1903), prohibiting masters from paying seamen in advance; Muller v.

Oregon, 208 U. S. 412 (1908), limiting hours of labor of women employed in

laundries to ten hours per day; Riley v. Massachusetts, 232 U. S. 671

(1914), limiting employment of women in manufacturing establishments to ten

hours per day, or not more than fifty-six hours per week; Erie Railway Co.

v. Williams, 233 U. S. 685 (1914), prohibiting employers from paying

employees less often than semi-monthly; Bosley v. McLaughlin, 236 U. S. 385

(1915), limiting employment of women for more than eight hours per day, or

more than forty-eight hours per week in certain designated employments;

Bunting v. Oregon, 243 U. S. 426 (1917), forbidding employment of anyone in

mill or factory for more than ten hours per day.


62. 261 U. S. 567, 568.


63. On the effect of the personal influences in the decisions of the Supreme

Court on labor cases, see Powell, "The Constitutional Issue in Minimum Wage

Legislation," Minnesota Law Review, vol. II (December, 1917). The reasoning

of the court in the Adkins Case led to a judgment against the validity of

the Arizona Minimum Wage Act and to a condemnation of other meliorative

acts. See ex parte Smith 223 Pac. 971 (1924).


64. Collected Legal Papers, p. 184.


65. "Though neither the doctrine of individualism nor of laissez faire is

contained in the language of the constitution, they permeate many judicial

opinions interpreting the constitution." Powell, "The Constitutional Issue

in Minimum Wage Legislation," Minn. Law Rev., II, 11. For a different

interpretation see Brown, ibid., I (June, 1917), 471.


66. Burns Baking Company v. Bryan, 264 U. S. 505, 513 (1923).


67. Ibid., 519, 520.


68. 264 U. S. 533, 534.


69. "One who assails the classification [made by a state legislature] must

carry the burden of showing that it does not rest upon any reasonable basis,

but is essentially arbitrary." Justice Sanford in Whitney v. California, 274

U. S. 357 (1927) citing Lindsley v. Natural Carbonic Gas Co., 220 U. S. 62,

78, 79 (1910).


70. Mott, op. cit., pp. 562 ff.


71. Tyson and Bro. United Theater Ticket Offices v. Banton; 273 U. S. 418

(1927). Referring to the failure of the justices to give due weight to the

evidence before the legislature in the case of Lochner v. New York, 198 U.

S. 45 (1905), Sir Frederick Pollock believes that "the legal weakness of

this reasoning, if we may say so, is that no credit seems to be given to the

state legislature for knowing its own business and it is treated like an

inferior court which has to find affirmative proof of its competence. How

can the Supreme Court at Washington have conclusive judicial knowledge of

the conditions affecting bakeries in New York? If it has not such knowledge

as matter of fact, can it be matter of law that no conditions can be

reasonably supposed to exist which would make such an enactment, not

necessarily wise or expedient (for no one attributes to any court, state or

federal, a general jurisdiction to review legislation on the merits) but

constitutional?" "The New York Labour Law and the Fourteenth Amendment," Law

Quarterly Review, XXI (July, 1905), 212.


72. Tyson and Bro. United Theater Ticket Offices 11. Banton, 273 U. S. 418

(1927). As authority for this view, Wolff Co. v. Industrial Court, 262 U. S.

522, 536 (1922) was cited.


73. 273 U. S., 433, 434.


74. Fairmont Creamery Co. v. Minnesota, 274 U. S. 1 (1927).


75. Barron v. Baltimore, 7 Pet 243 (1833). See comment of Chief Justice

Waite in 1876 that "it is now too late to question the correctness of this

construction," and citation of cases, Harv. Law Rev., XXXIX (February,

1926), 436.


76. Prudential Insurance Co. v. Cheek, 259 U. S. 530, 538, 543 (1922);

Patterson v. Colorado, 205 U. S. 454 (1907).


For the claim that it was the intention of the framers of the Fourteenth

Amendment that the rights and privileges of the first eight amendments

should be the "secure possession of every citizen" of the United States,

beyond the power of any state to abridge," see Guthrie, Lectures on the

Fourteenth Article of Amendment to the Constitution of the United States, p.

61.


77. New York v. Gitlow, 268 U. S. 652, 666 (1925). Justice Sanford said that

the court did not regard the statement quoted above from the Prudential

Insurance Cases as "determinative," but he does not refer to the other cases

in which similar opinions were rendered.


78. See Minor v. Happersett, 21 Wall. 162 (1874), 1; United States v.

Cruikshank, 92 U. S. 542 (1875); in re Kemmler, 136 U. S. 436 (1890);

Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U. S. 78 (1908).


79. Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357 (1927).


80. United States v. Trenton Potteries Co., 273 U. S. 392 (1927). For

applications of the concept of reasonableness in passing on the validity of

combinations in restraint of trade, consult U. S. v. Trans-Missouri Freight

Association, 166 U. S. 290 (1896); Northern Securities Co. v. United States,

193 U. S. 197 (1903); Standard Oil Co. v. United States, 221 U. S. 1 (1910);

United States v. American Tobacco Co., 211 U. S. 106 (1910).


"It is submitted that up to the present time very little can be learned as

to the meaning of due process of law from the decisions of the Supreme Court

as to what in its judgment is reasonable and what unreasonable. They neither

give us a rule of law nor a definition." Willis, Univ. of Pa. Law Rev.,

LXXIV, 338, 339. See comment how the Supreme Court, in finding a new meaning

for due process of law, made some new constitutional law. P. 339.


81. For comments on one phase of this revolution, see F. Dumont Smith,

"Decisive Battles of Constitutional Law," American Bar Association Journal,

X, 505, and The Constitution: Its Story and Battles, chap. 15.



                   CHAPTER VIII


 NATURAL LAW DOCTRINES AID IN CHANGING THE BASIS
      FOR JUDICIAL REVIEW OF LEGISLATIVE ACTS


BEGINNING with the dominance of the Federalist Party over the political

affairs of the country after the inauguration of the federal Constitution in

1789, a tradition was established which insisted that the continuance of

federalism and its control over political affairs was essential to the

political peace and order of the country, and that anti-federalism tended in

the direction of chaos and ruin. This tradition was fostered in large part

through the business and commercial interests over which Hamilton and his

successors held sway. For the greater part of the nineteenth century the

successors of the Federalist Party preserved the doctrine that peace and

order depended upon their control and insisted that the turning over of the

government to their opponents would bring ruin and disruption to the

country.


To prevent an excess of democracy and the disorders supposed to accompany

the people's management of public affairs there was an insistence that one

department of government must not be directly influenced by temporary public

opinion, and it was determined to make the judiciary such a stabilizing

power.[1]


Under the leadership of such men as Chief Justice Marshall, Justice Joseph

Story, and Daniel Webster, it came to be an accepted view that nationalist,

conservative, and commercialist views of American law and politics were

looked upon as sound statesmanship and opposite views were identified with

ruin and disunion. The Republican Party, which became the successor of the

old Federalist and Whig Parties, accepted and fostered the conservative and

capitalist traditions championed by the old Federalist Party. After the

program was inaugurated of applying the resources of the government to

economic development through a liberal land policy, which gave an impetus to

the settlement of the frontier, through subsidies and land grants to

railways, which gave settlers access to world markets, and through

protective duties, which were designed to build up home industries, the

party adopted the principles and practices of the coalition between the

commercial and capitalist interests which were characteristic of the

policies of Alexander Hamilton. Hence the party leaders again asserted the

former contention that their control of the country alone could preserve

peace and order.


As the Democratic Party was disrupted through the realignments resulting

from the Civil War it was easy to maintain the position that the turning

over of the government to this party would, as was charged against the

anti-federalists many decades earlier, lead the people in the direction of

political disorder and ruin. The old doctrine is continued in the

oft-repeated claim that the decisions of John Marshall "remain the charter

of courts of justice in the modern republican world: the world of law and

constitutional government. They speak order, power, progress and peace. Had

a contrary conception of civil institutions prevailed, could anything else

have followed than weakness and strife, decay and chaos?"[2] It has become

one of the axioms of American political philosophy that "to maintain the

principle that there is a limit in republican government to the power of the

majority to make laws is one of the most valuable functions the courts have

to perform."[3]


1. Conservative Doctrines and Judicial Review of Legislation. The battle cry

of those who believe in conservative doctrines is that every effort must be

made to place limits upon the despotism of the majority.[4] No device is

better designed to accomplish this end than the practice of the judicial

review of legislative acts with a written constitution as an express guide

and with a broad rule of reason as a supplementary weapon of defence. And a

principle of government which was identified with one of the great parties

of American political development has been espoused by the leaders of both

major parties.


The conservative reaction, which, among other things, secured the judicial

application of the doctrine of inherent limits on legislative powers and

left its impress upon the Fourteenth Amendment to such an extent as to bring

a change in the federal Constitution greater than all amendments and

interpretations made since 1789, was not the result of any one group,

division, or class of the American people. Like the medley of interests

which combined to make and to secure the adoption of the Constitution, a

rather unusual combination of individuals, groups, and interests joined

forces to bring about a radical change in the adjustment of relations

between the nation and the states. A peculiar set of circumstances,

economic, political, social, and philosophic, gave color to dominant modes

of thinking which affected all, including the justices in state and federal

courts. Certain ideas were fostered and became the stock in trade of the

politicians and of the legal fraternity. It is not surprising, therefore, to

find the state and federal justices about the same time giving form and

utterance to the peculiar concept of "liberty of contract" and to various

doctrines of economic individualism. These ideas were prevalent and the

semi-political views of the justices, meeting a responsive chord in public

sentiment, as a rule, were received with popular approval. The change in the

interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment, whereby a content was declared

involved therein which the majority of the Supreme Court had repeatedly held

was not intended in its adoption, was the result of the reasoning of many

justices, though a few of this number bore the brunt of the controversy

which turned the tide toward a broad judicial review of legislation.


Three justices seem to have determined, in large part, the trend of the

opinions of the Supreme Court, in the cases changing the meaning and content

of the term "due process of law" and in ushering in a period characterized

as a "carnival of unconstitutionality, which perhaps was at its height

between 1890 and 1910."[5] They were Justices Field, Harlan, and Brewer.

Certain peculiarities and characteristics of these justices made a distinct

impression upon this unique feature of modern American constitutional law.

Foremost of this group is Justice Field.


He had, we are told, a quality of intellect which led him on all occasions

to seek for fundamental and universal principles.[6] His creative power,

exhibited in a marked degree in his legislative career, was also

characteristic of his decisions on the bench.[7] His experience in a

frontier community, as well as his training in early life, developed a

philosophy of individualism in which he was disposed to encourage in every

way individual self-exertion, and to object to measures attempting to

regulate economic life.[8] It was this philosophy that led Justice Field to

object strongly to any exercise of governmental power which to him seemed

arbitrary,[9] and that impelled him to insist that the Fourteenth Amendment

was designed to prevent arbitrary governmental acts.[10] More consistently

than any other justice, he opposed the inclination of the justices of the

Supreme Court not to give the broadest meaning and application to the due

process and equal protection phrases of the Fourteenth Amendment. He was the

spokesman of the court in some of the leading cases in which the

interpretation of the amendment was changed, and continued on the bench

until the reversal of the Slaughter-House Case and similar cases was

accomplished, and until the amendment was interpreted as at least a negative

protection to any interference with civil or political rights.[11]


Justice Harlan, like Justice Field, was influenced considerably by the

philosophy and experience of the frontier, and he, too, was individualistic

in much of his thinking. He was regarded as a "militant justice," and was

strongly nationalistic in his political theories.[12] Inclined to emphasize

the theory of natural rights he was readily disposed to adopt the doctrine

of fundamental rights which the justices of the Supreme Court were slowly

developing in connection with the interpretation of the due process clause.

He had supposed, he said, that the intention of the people of the United

States was to prevent the deprivation of any legal right in violation of the

fundamental principles inhering in due process of law,[13] objected to any

interference with private property rights,[14] and joined, as a rule,

Justice Field in protesting against the regulative measures of the state

legislatures. He agreed with Justice Field that Congress and the courts

ought to be authorized to exercise a national control over civil rights.[15]


No greater exponent of the individualistic philosophy of this period was

appointed to the Supreme Court than Justice Brewer.[16] In decisions while

on the circuit court, and in his opinions and influence on the Supreme

Bench, he availed himself of every opportunity to defend the extreme

individualistic doctrines which prevailed at this time. His point of view

was expressed quite freely in an address delivered before the graduating

class of the Yale Law School in June, 1891, on "Protection to Private

Property from Public Attack." Referring to the Declaration of Independence

and the bills of rights of state constitutions, Justice Brewer said, "they

equally affirm that sacredness of life, of liberty, and of property, are

rights, inalienable rights, anteceding human government, and its only sure

foundation, given not by man to man, but granted by the Almighty to

everyone, something which he has by virtue of his manhood, which he may not

surrender and of which he may not be deprived." To Justice Brewer, the

Declaration of Independence was the cornerstone of the federal

Constitution.[17]


Justice Brewer also asserted in his address that "the demands of absolute

and eternal justice prevent that any private property legally acquired or

legally held should be subordinated or destroyed in the interests of public

health, morals, or welfare without compensation." The destruction of

property rights, he thought, might be as effectively accomplished by the

regulation of charges, or by the regulation of the use to which property may

be put as by the direct destruction of the property itself. Referring to the

controversy before the Supreme Court, which resulted in the reversal of the

case of Munn v. Illinois, he approved Justice Blatchford's opinion for

reversal with the comment that it "will ever remain the strong and

unconquerable fortress in a long struggle between individual rights and

public greed. I rejoice to have been permitted to put one stone into that

fortress." He approved the doctrine of Chancellor Kent and of Justice Cooley

that legislatures may not disturb vested rights, whether constitutional

provisions prohibit such acts or not, and regretted that the Fourteenth

Amendment had not been interpreted more favorably in the direction of

protecting property rights. The frontier individualistic philosophy of

Justices Field and Harlan had an able defender in Justice Brewer.


Appointed to the court after the change in the interpretation of the

Fourteenth Amendment was under way, Justice Peckham was well suited to

become one of the leading exponents of the conservative and individualistic

thinking of Justices Field, Harlan, and Brewer. As a member of the Court of

Appeals of New York, Justice Peckham not only approved the doctrine of

Justice Field that the due process clause comprehended the inalienable

rights referred to in the Declaration of Independence but he also indicated

his inclination to join the ranks of the laissez faire school and to look

with disapproval on the increasing tendency to regulate economic conditions.

When placing the stamp of disapproval on a state law prohibiting the giving

of a gift or reward with the sale of an article of food, Justice Peckham

said:


    It is evidently of that kind which has been so frequent of late,
    a kind which is meant to protect some class in the
    community against the fair, free, and full competition of some
    other class, the members of the former class thinking it
    impossible to hold their own against such competition, and
    therefore flying to the legislature to secure some enactment
    which shall operate favorably to them or unfavorably to their
    competitors in the commercial, agricultural, manufacturing or
    producing field.[18]


The natural inclination here expressed to hold the legislative power within

"reasonable" limits qualified Justice Peckham to become the spokesman for

the majority in Lochner v. New York and to assert that


    it must, of course, be conceded that there is a limit to the
    valid exercise of the police power of the state. In every case
    that comes before this court, therefore, where legislation of
    this character is concerned and where the protection of the
    federal Constitution is sought, the question necessarily arises:
    Is this a fair, reasonable and appropriate exercise of the
    police power of the state or is it an unreasonable,
    unnecessary and arbitrary interference with the right of the
    individual to his personal liberty?[19]


And on this ground it was held that a particular limitation of the hours of

labor did not come within the police power.[20]


Since the controversy which resulted in changing the meaning of the due

process clause was an issue primarily between the liberal or radical groups

and those imbued with the principles and philosophies of individualism and

of conservatism, the ordinary partisan affiliations of the justices did not

have a controlling influence in bringing about the change. The majority of

the justices who gave a narrow interpretation to the amendment in the decade

from 1870 to 1880 were Democrats, a number of whom, as supporters of the

Union, had joined the Republican Party. It was Justice Miller, however, a

Republican, and an intense partisan who usually supported federalist

doctrines, who rendered the opinion of the majority in the Slaughter-House

Case; and it was Justice Field, a Democrat, who gave the minority opinion

and pleaded for a broad interpretation of the amendment. Justice Bradley, a

Republican, protested strongly against judicial review of the legislative

power of rate-making and of public utility regulation. And the effective

shift favorable to judicial review of the regulation of public utilities in

the Minnesota Rate Case of 1889 was accomplished with three Republicans and

three Democrats forming the majority and two Republicans and one Democrat

the minority. Though the majority of the justices from 1870 to 1900 were

Republicans, Democrats joined with Republicans in many decisions extending

the general terms of written constitutions and in construing implied limits

on legislatures. The truth of the matter is that, except for some of the

differences between the parties left over from Civil War times and the

tariff controversy, leading Democrats and Republicans looked at political

matters from similar viewpoints. The parties seldom took sides on the vital

issues of the day, and, as a rule, their leaders joined in helping to bring

about a covert but effective revolution in federal and state constitutional

interpretation.


The federalism of Marshall, Kent, Story, Cooley, and Dillon suggested ideas

and formulated principles for a political conservatism which American

constitutions were presumed to foster. It remained for the justices of the

Supreme Court, aided by a group of assertive state justices, to turn these

ideas into the channels of a new conservatism and to complete a structure of

constitutional limitations and inhibitions the mere outlines of which had

been previously sketched. The vested rights doctrine and the implied

limitations originally considered as necessary for the protection of such

rights took on a new form and were rounded out and extended by giving new

meaning and content to the contract clause, to the just compensation

principle for eminent domain proceedings, to the public purpose requirement

for taxation, and to due process of law rendered applicable to all forms of

legislative and administrative action, and particularly in so far as

property rights might be affected.


In New York the total number of acts or parts thereof invalidated from 1783

to 1905 was three hundred and sixty-three. From 1860 to 1905 the number was

two hundred and ninety-seven and more than one third of this number was

declared void in the decade from 1891 to 1900.[21] Massachusetts courts used

their powers sparingly to review and invalidate acts, only fifty-three acts

or parts thereof being set aside to 1915. Ten of these were held void prior

to 1860 and fifteen in the decade 1891 to 1900.[22]


But more important than the marked increase in the statutes invalidated in

the latter part of the nineteenth century is the basic reason for such a

change. Professor Corwin attributes the extension of judicial review in New

York to the increase in the legislative product, the greater detail of

constitutional provisions, and the development of constitutional doctrine,

but he concludes that "the heart and soul of constitutional limitations in

New York, thanks especially to Chancellor Kent, has been the doctrine of

vested rights" and that the New York courts did constructive work in

utilizing the "due process of law" clause as "a safe vehicle for the

doctrine of vested rights."[23] Nearly one half of the statutes invalidated

in Massachusetts was held in violation of due process of law or other

provisions of the constitution which were construed as favorable to the

protection of vested rights.[24] Evidently the justices had strayed a long

way from the landmarks established in early precedents supporting the power

of judicial review of legislative enactments.[25]


The obvious results of all the implied limitations and correlative ones,

which have amplified and extended the scope of judicial review of

legislation, and the extraordinary expansion of due process of law into a

general limitation applicable to the entire realm of legislation and

administration led to a construction by judicial interpretation of a broad

rule of reason as a standard to test the fairness and reasonableness of

legislative enactments, and incidentally to consider the wisdom or

expediency of many governmental acts. The justices, however, continued to

render lip service to the adage that courts had nothing to do with the

wisdom or policy of legislation, their sole duty being to apply the express

language of written constitutions. But express constitutional limitations

with such vague terms as "due process of law" gave justices a roving

commission to disapprove such measures as seemed to them to change too

abruptly some regulation affecting the existing social or political order,

or to presage too radical tendencies, and to seek refuge for such

disapproval behind the indefinite language of express constitutional

terms.[26]


It is not so much, then, the original language or intent of written

constitutions that is responsible for the unique character of the practice

of judicial review of legislative acts in the United States, as compared

with a similar practice in foreign countries. It is the judge-made

constitutional doctrines supported by the conservative groups of the country

and fostered by the extreme individualism of leaders of industry and finance

who, while busily engaged in securing governmental favors, were solicitous

to make sure that popular assemblies might not be permitted to regulate too

freely their property or contract rights.


It is coming to be better understood today than formerly that methods of

thinking fostered by the common law, supported by the capitalists and

industrial leaders of the country, and applied by conservative-minded

judges, rather than constitutional provisions have given the peculiar trend

to judicial review of legislation in the United States. Though foreign

critics of the American system of government have frequently pointed out

this fact, none has recognized it more clearly or dealt with it so

convincingly as Professor Edouard Lambert, of the University of Lyons. In a

recent volume dealing with certain phases of the problem of judicial review

of legislation, he contrasts the early period of the exercise of this power

by American courts -- when the object was to control the competency of the

legislature to deal with certain subjects, and not the way in which the

legislature had dealt with the subjects -- and the modern practice of

judicial review through which due process has been interpreted to form a new

Magna Carta "built piece by piece by the judges to protect the free play of

individual energies against the arbitrary manifestations of popular

sovereignty."[27]


In the twentieth century, Professor Lambert observes, the American judiciary

is in possession of a power which permits it to exercise an energetic

tutelage over the legislature, and to check the progress of legislation.

This tutelage, he finds, is exercised in passing on the reasonableness of

legislative measures, a well-known rule of reason now applied extensively by

federal and state courts; and second, the criterion of expediency by which

the courts pass on the economic value or political desirability of

legislative measures. In the application of these principles, Professor

Lambert thinks that American courts applying the conservative principles of

the common law hold legislative activities within well-defined bounds. This

practice of the courts, he believes, has had the result to erect a political

judiciary against a political legislature, and often in conflict with it on

the most irritating questions of a changing political and economic order. It

is not surprising to find, then, that it operates to the detriment of the

popularity and confidence ordinarily belonging to courts of justice.[28] The

justices having taken sides on some of the fiercely contested political

issues could expect nothing less than that their decisions would involve the

courts in the maelstrom of party politics.


What is arbitrary and what is beneficent must be decided by common sense

applied to a concrete set of facts.[29] But what criteria except their own

consciences, have judges to guide them, as to what acts are unreasonable,

unfair, discriminatory, outrageous, capricious, and shocking to the moral

sense of mankind?" Is it surprising that the judgments of the individual

justices differ widely as to the application of such vague and indefinite

terms, that dissenting opinions are prevalent, that the courts frequently

shift their positions, and that a feeling of uncertainty prevails as to the

application of the rule of reason or the higher law philosophy supposed to

be comprehended in the Fourteenth Amendment?


When legislation carefully formulated to deal with the complications and

adjustments of the social order and to remedy some of the insistent evils of

present industrial conditions is declared of no effect by a divided court,

against the earnest and caustic protests of the minority justices, in the

application of subjective criteria which constitute no standards at all, it

is not strange that confidence in the judiciary is weakened, and that the

leaders who are seeking to regulate more effectively the economic conditions

which are deemed detrimental to human welfare are disposed to protest

against the unwarranted powers assumed by the judges. "Here is the whole

story behind the failure of all formulae connected with 'due process' and

all the meaningless and circular statements as to what acts are and what are

not 'due process.' In determining whether an act has a substantial and

rational or reasonable relation to the enumerated matters, the court has in

mind the background of 'fundamental principles' which are beyond the reach

of any legislative power."[30] But is it not natural to expect that those

for whom the oracles expound the "fundamental principles" should believe

that the voice of the numen is not always correctly understood and that in

the process of exposition some of the power once thought to belong to the

people or to their representatives has been silently and surely

dissipated?[31]


2. Underlying Purpose of the Revival of the Natural Law Philosophy in

American Constitutional Law. American constitutions were drafted when there

was a deep-seated conviction that the people could not be trusted and that

well-defined checks must be placed upon the rule of the people. It was under

these conditions that the courts with strong popular approval asserted the

right, which they held to be implied from the language of the written

constitution, to declare void legislative acts deemed to be in conflict with

the written fundamental law. A growing distrust for legislative assemblies

encouraged the courts not only to hold invalid acts regarded as contrary to

the express language of the written constitutions, but to construe implied

limitations supposed to be derived from the doctrine of natural and

inalienable rights and from the notion of fundamental individual rights.

Again the courts were encouraged and supported in a continuous line of

decisions, mostly rendered since the Civil War, to place other implied

limits on legislative powers in addition to the varied list of express

limitations added by vote of the people. By extending judicial review of

legislation through the developing doctrine of protecting vested rights,

through the change in the meaning of due process of law, to render it a

general limitation on legislative powers, and through giving new force and

meaning to the separation of power theory,[32] the courts have gradually

assumed a general right of censorship over legislation to see that it is not

arbitrary or unfair and that it does not violate any of the judicially

construed "fundamental principles" of the social order. A mild and

relatively unimportant practice of judicial review of legislation for nearly

a century has during the last few decades loomed up as the controlling

feature of the American system of constitutional government.


The judicial power to declare laws unconstitutional gradually introduced a

new concept of due process by expanding what the courts had been inclined to

regard as the inherent limitations on legislative powers. The doctrine of

inherent limitations on legislatures had been applied at first to the

protection of vested rights. It was a different matter to insist in the name

of due process of law upon an immunity of individual action from legislative

control.


It was such Justices as Field, Harlan, Brewer, and Peckham in the federal

courts and Justices Edwards, Comstock, and Denio in the state courts, the

champions of a revived eighteenth-century individualism, of the policy of

economic laissez faire, and of conservative political tendencies, who gave

the natural rights or modern higher law doctrine the peculiar trend which

now marks the process of constitutional interpretation in state and federal

courts.[33] As upholders of individualistic and laissez faire doctrines in

an age of unceasing legislative activities the courts were made censors of

economic and social legislation under the higher law doctrine of American

constitutional law -- the rule of reason.


Being rather insecure as a basis for legislative limitations, the former

doctrine held a precarious place in American constitutional law, especially

when the tendencies were in the direction of the extension of popular

control over all agencies of government. When, however, this doctrine was

absorbed in the general phrases "due process of law," "equal protection of

the laws," "public purpose for taxation," "public use for eminent domain,"

and "reasonableness," it was given the semblance of express constitutional

sanction. Henceforth judges and lawyers could confidently assert that courts

no longer passed upon the wisdom or expediency of legislative acts. They

merely applied in a mechanical way, it was insisted, the express words of

the constitution which by "indubitable demonstration" compelled the laying

of the axe at the root of legislative power. This change in basis has not

affected the character of the higher law doctrine which constitutes today

the central feature of American constitutional law. A new law of nature and

a new rule of reason were in process of development. Instead, however, of

serving as in Roman and in mediaeval times, as an agency for the

liberalization of the law, as an ideal toward which law was approximating,

it became the weapon of a fixed, immutable order which was designed to serve

as a check on progressive or radical measures, and to restrict within

well-defined limits the liberalizing tendencies which were characteristic of

an age of extensive lawmaking.[34]


The repeated assertions, then, by lawyers and judges in the United States

that the right to hold laws invalid because they are unwise or unjust, or

because they run counter to natural and inalienable rights, have never been

applied to concrete cases, may readily be explained.


Before the extensive implications of due process of law and other similar

phrases had been discovered, it was not uncommon for justices to refer to

fundamental principles or natural rights as a basis to invalidate acts.

Before the Civil War, when, on the whole, relatively few acts were held void

by the courts, certain of the decisions invalidating acts were based

definitely upon the doctrine of fundamental rights, the principles of free

government, or other implied limitations related in a sense to the higher

law philosophy. Sometimes constitutional provisions were held applicable;

other times there seemed to be little inclination to seek for appropriate

constitutional sanction other than the general clauses in the bills of

rights.[35] But the reason why it is claimed that the courts have not been

passing upon the wisdom or unwisdom of acts under a natural rights doctrine

is due to the fact that the due process clause was interpreted to include

and embody such a doctrine. From that time on, instead of referring to these

general limitations as inherent in all governments, or to the older theories

of natural law, the courts began to refer to "due process of law," "equal

protection of the laws," and other general terms interpreted to include

natural and inalienable rights.


When it is contended, then, that the courts do not pass upon the wisdom or

unwisdom, policy or impolicy, the reasonableness or unreasonableness of

legislative acts it merely means that in the determination of whether an act

is or is not due process of law there is involved the full content of the

old doctrine of natural and inalienable rights, of the principles of the

social compact, and of the former dogmas of free republican governments, all

of which involved questions of political expediency.[36] Having brought the

straggling and insecure phrases of "natural law" or "natural justice" and of

the "fixed principles of republican governments" into due process of law it

was confidently asserted that all decisions of the courts dealing with the

validity of legislative acts were based upon the express provisions of

written constitutions.[37]


The conclusion of the matter seems to be that beginning with the

eighteenth-century notions of natural rights and of limiting and dividing

powers, the states of the American union turned in the direction of

unrestricted powers in the hands of the legislative bodies, and then adopted

the policy of placing larger and more effective limits upon legislatures.

The reason for this can be found largely in the belief that legislatures had

unduly interfered with property rights and in the fear that property and

contracts were not safe unless many restrictions were imposed upon

representative bodies.


The courts, having invaded the legislative domain by the interpretation of

the general terms of the Fifth and the Fourteenth Amendments, in determining

whether legislation is in effect wise, expedient, or reasonable in its

object, we are now advised that it is futile to criticize what has been

done. It is asserted to be a "question of purely academic interest" whether

the court's version of due process of law was historically correct.[38] The

only profitable study is declared to be when and under what circumstances

does the amendment serve as a restriction on the states. Though the meaning

now given to due process of law requires the courts to deal with problems of

legislative policy it is thought to be idle "to criticize the courts for

invading the field of policy in deciding 'due process' cases. There is

nothing else that they can do as long as the doctrine prevails that these

clauses limit the subject matter of legislation. This might as well be

frankly recognized by all concerned."[39]


Such legal pessimism is indefensible. It is equivalent to saying that when

judges choose to take from the people their right of self-government with no

express sanction for such action, there is no remedy but servile submission.

It is possible to amend the Fourteenth Amendment and if the trend of the

past thirty years continues, sufficient groups and interests will be

confined by its limitations to create a sentiment which will render its

alteration possible. Whether such a radical step be desirable or not, the

bringing of constant pressure on the court through all the available avenues

of public opinion may secure a reversal of some decisions which have proved

most obnoxious. It does not seem impossible to secure on the federal bench

judges whose training and experience, according with the prevailing

sentiment of the community, may decide that the historic theory of the

separation of powers is still valid and applies to judges as well as to

other officers, and hence, that matters of social, economic, and political

policy belong of right to the legislative branch of the government. Due

process of law might then be retained in somewhat of its original meaning as

a limitation on procedural matters. If, as Professor Powell observes, the

vital matter in the interpretation of the due process clause of the

Constitution is not one of economics, of law, or of public policy, but of

the arbiters who ultimately decide cases,[40] is it not time that more

attention be given to the selection of the arbiters and to the influencing

of their work as final interpreters of the fundamental law? As the repeal of

the Fourteenth Amendment is a remote contingency, the concentration of

public attention in the direction of confining judges to their normal

function of deciding cases involving private rights in accordance with

previously determined legislative policies, rather than of determining the

wisdom or expediency of public policies, seems the only practical procedure.

Though it offers small hope of immediate relief for those who chafe under

the restrictions which now interfere with advances along the lines of social

and industrial reconstruction, at least it gives an objective for the

present to take issue with the supporters of the status quo and the juristic

pessimism which they espouse.[41]


3. Types of Natural Law applied in the United States. During the nineteenth

century natural law theories were applied in the United States by different

groups for a variety of purposes. There were occasional references to the

divine sources of law and to natural laws emanating therefrom which were

binding upon all men. In the early decades of the nineteenth century the

justices frequently made use of natural law as a liberalizing and creative

concept similar to its use in Roman times and in the later mediaeval

periods. But its use was creative only in the sense that it facilitated the

borrowing of legal precepts from European legal systems. Conceived as a body

of rational principles of which actual legal rules were only declaratory,

the natural law philosophy, Dean Pound thinks, "was at its best when courts

were called on to utilize the peculiar social and political institutions of

pioneer America in developing and supplementing the legal materials afforded

by the English common law, the Continental treatises on commercial law, and

comparative law."[42] When an attempt was made to put judicial decisions in

the fields of international law or of constitutional law into a

philosophical mold, the law of nature theories of Grotius, of Pufendorf, of

Vattel, or of Burlamaqui were given a meaning suitable to the legal and

political conditions of the time. At times natural law as a basis of natural

rights might be identified with the rights and duties of an abstract man in

a state of nature or perchance with the immemorial common law rights as

formulated by Coke and Blackstone. It might also serve to modify a rigorous

rule of the formal law. "The American variant of natural law was especially

an outgrowth of the review of legislative acts by the courts and the efforts

of the justices to deduce general principles of constitutional law from the

social compact, from the nature of free government, or from the fundamental

and inalienable rights of the individual."[43]


In the hands of American judges natural law ideas were a favorite refuge for

giving sanction to the negative and restrictive ideas of the eighteenth

century that governmental functions should be confined to a narrow sphere.

They formed the background for the American doctrine of civil liberty, the

chief purpose of which is to safeguard individual rights and to place

restrictions on political action to accomplish this end. A legal philosophy

was fostered, the chief aim of which was to support the existing order or to

recur to the past for standards to test the validity of new forms of

legislation. This philosophy assisted in forming what foreign critics have

called "the straight jacket" into which the powers of government had to fit

or be denied validity.


These natural laws negative and destructive in effect acquired by the end of

the nineteenth century a stamp of inexorability. They placed certain legal

phenomena beyond the realm of conscious human control and bred a philosophy

of juristic pessimism, which accords well with the practices and beliefs of

those who seek protection but not interference with their "private" affairs.

They became obstacles to the growth and improvement of the law.


American constitutional law is saturated with natural law ideas. The old law

of nature was crystallized into certain standard formulae in the bills of

rights in state and federal constitutions and then was given renewed vigor

in the construction of the general phrases which were made a part of the

fundamental law. Formerly when the statute, code, legal procedure, or some

formal rule in the administration of the law proved to be arbitrary and

unreasonable the law of nature was appealed to as an ideal law to require a

modification of the harsh or unfair rule or to have it set aside as void.

The new law of nature formulated by the justices in American courts affirmed

certain standards of reasonable and fair conduct on the part of government

officers which were presumed to be fixed in the fundamental written law

through such terms as "due process of law" and "the equal protection of the

laws." When legislators and executives undertook to enact or enforce rules

or laws to ameliorate some of the inequities or inequalities in the existing

economic or social order, to regulate conduct in the interest of classes

which are deemed to require special protection, or to regulate and restrict

uses of property in what is deemed to be the public interest, the justices

scanned these acts to see whether they were within the confines of

reasonable and fair conduct as were supposed to be rendered fixed and

unalterable in the written constitution.[44]


As a matter of fact, then, natural law flourishes in the United States

despite the insistence from many quarters that it belongs in the realm of

exploded vagaries.[45] But judges and courts are applying an historical

Naturrecht derived from the principles and precedents of the common law and

modified by the individualist natural law of the eighteenth century.[46]

Insistent efforts are made to deny the use of general principles or

standards based on natural law reasoning and fictions are used to conceal

the process. It is futile, however, to refuse to face the facts, and "to

hide from ourselves the general principles which we do in fact follow, and

to delude ourselves into the belief that we have no philosophy."[47]


4. Natural Law Theories as a Sanction for American Political and Legal

Conservatism. It is obvious that natural law thinking of various types has

played a significant rôle in the growth of private and public law in the

United States. There have been in this growth new applications of the

principles of fair conduct for a fiduciary, of reasonable conduct in the law

of negligence, of fair competition in business transactions, and of fair

value and reasonable return in public utility control. And in public law the

use of natural law theories for various purposes has been continuous from

colonial times to the present day. Conceived in the spirit of democracy and

liberalism, these theories gave sanction to those who attacked the existing

legal order and who through revolution gained the independence of the

American states. Throughout the early periods of American history the

natural law doctrines were employed mainly for idealistic, progressive, and

revolutionary purposes.


But the first stage in this development had not passed when similar

doctrines were approved in order to set limits to governmental action for

ends that were conservative, aristocratic, and authoritarian. As the

idealistic and progressive uses of natural law have declined the

conservative and aristocratic uses have been extended. And it is in the

review of legislation by the courts that the conservative, authoritarian

type of natural law has been fostered. The most significant applications of

such higher law ideas have arisen when the courts have become the

constitutional censors of the acts of legislative and executive action,

whether of federal or state agencies.[48]


It is customary to assert that it is a sheer mis-statement to say that

American courts in exercising judicial review of legislation assume a

supervisory power over the legislative and executive branches of the

government.[49] Such an observation had a modicum of accuracy when the

courts held few acts invalid and then only because they were regarded in

conflict with some clear and well-understood terms of a written fundamental

law. Such is the review exercised as a rule over legislation by the Canadian

courts and the Privy Council for Canada and by the Australian courts. It is

a different matter when the courts use phrases such as due process of law,

equal protection of the laws, fair return and reasonable rates for use of

property, acts not arbitrary or capricious or designed to shock the sense of

mankind as grounds for review of legislation. These phrases, applied as they

usually are to a complicated state of facts and used to test the validity of

some act regulating economic or social relationships, take judicial review

out of the inexorable and mechanical realm in which decisions follow

indubitable logic. The reasoning regarding judicial review, which Hamilton

and Marshall attempted to put on a plane of dry logic, fails either to

justify or to explain the practice when based on indefinable general

phrases.[50]


An analysis of the different provisions of written constitutions shows that

the courts have a variety of types of provisions to interpret. Some

provisions, such as that all political power resides in the people, are

political in character and cannot be tested by ordinary legal criteria. When

the legislature is inhibited from passing bills of attainder or ex post

facto laws or from interfering with individual rights by abolishing trial by

jury in criminal cases there are available to judges for guidance in

applying these provisions fairly definite legal precepts. But these

semi-political provisions and the clauses relating to criminal trials have a

relatively minor place in modern constitutional interpretation by the courts

of the United States. For it is rather legal conceptions derived from the

constitutions by interpretation such as the police power, liberty of

contract and of calling, and the general requirement that no one shall be

deprived of life, liberty, or property without due process of law which now

furnish the most important bases for the review of the validity of

legislative acts. And here judges have no legal rules to guide them. Passing

as they often do in these cases on the reasonableness of social legislation

they are essentially dealing with legislative questions -- not with a

mechanical legal technique.


The problem of what ought to be law, what is reasonable, arbitrary, or fair,

really is an exercise of veto power. As a matter of fact, the mechanical,

necessitous doctrine which became a tradition in the early period of

American constitutional law does not apply to the invalidating of acts on

the ground of lack of fairness or reasonableness under the Fifth and

Fourteenth Amendments of the federal Constitution or under similar

provisions of the state constitutions.


The acute controversies on the interpretation of the federal Constitution

for the last fifty years have arisen out of the interstate commerce and due

process of law clauses. It has been repeatedly pointed out that the

judgments of the court along these lines are primarily judgments on facts

and only secondarily on the law. Concepts like "liberty" and "due process"

are too indefinite to solve issues. They derive meaning only if referred to

human facts.[51] "Here is where the great practical evil of the doctrine of

immutable and necessary antecedent rules comes in," according to John Dewey,

"it sanctifies the old; adherence to it in practice constantly widens the

gap between current social conditions and the principles used by the courts.

The effect is to breed irritation, disrespect for law, together with virtual

alliance between the judiciary and entrenched interests that correspond most

nearly to the conditions under which the rules of law were previously laid

down."[52]


Only the misinformed or extreme partisans claim any longer that there was

any necessity in the adoption of a written constitution, as John Marshall

insisted, for courts to review the validity of legislative acts. Partisan

feelings and self-interest also account for the failure to admit that much

the more important phases of judicial review of legislation in the United

States are the result of judge-made limitations designed to give legal

sanction to conservative tendencies of the time. It is not surprising then

to find conservative leaders insistent on the maintenance and extension of

the powers of the courts. "There are today," said Justice Brewer before the

New York State Bar Association,


    ten thousand millions of dollars invested in railroad property,
    whose owners in this country number less than two million
    persons. Can it be that whether this immense sum shall earn
    a dollar or bring the slightest recompense to those who have
    invested perhaps their all in that business and are thus aiding
    in the development of the country, depends wholly upon the
    whim and greed of the great majority of sixty millions who
    do not own a dollar! I say that so long as constitutional
    guarantees lift on American soil their buttresses and
    bulwarks against wrong, and so long as the American
    judiciary breathes the free air of courage it cannot.... What
    then is to be done? My reply is, strengthen the judiciary.


Not only have the courts construed constitutional guarantees to protect the

property interests of corporations but in an epoch-making decision the

Supreme Court of the United States has also held that legislative and

administrative agencies in regulating public utilities and in fixing rates

must be subject to review by the courts on both the law and the facts in

order that governmental action affecting utility properties may not be

unreasonable and that their properties may not be confiscated. Such a

decision has placed upon the courts ultimately the examination of the

intricate processes of the valuation of public utilities, the determination

of what is a fair value of the property for rate making, what is a fair

return on this valuation, and what is reasonable regulation. Thus great

questions of legislative policy as to the regulation of utilities are

carried to the courts and what the ultimate methods of regulation may be are

determined by the standards which the justices lay down. Since courts are

better qualified to protect property rights than to preserve individual

privileges and the public good, the owners of public utilities have been

encouraged to defy the authority of the government.


In recognition of the influence of personal and individual factors in the

legislative activity of judges such standards as fair return, reasonable

care, and due diligence are applied in England by administrative boards or

by courts with a jury passing judgment on the facts. The English people have

never accorded to judges the authority to determine the validity of

legislative acts no matter how fundamental the rights of the individual

which might be invaded. There is in this regard a striking difference

between the practice of the English and of the American courts.


Because of the natural conservatism and the class bias of judges the English

people have surrounded judicial legislation with definite limitations and

have invariably preserved the corrective power of Parliament. The reasons

for these checks on the legislative powers of the courts are thus expressed

by two English commentators:


    The courts or the judges, when acting as legislators, are, of
    course, influenced by beliefs and feelings of their time, and
    are guided to a considerable extent by the dominant current
    of public opinion; Eldon and Kenyon belonged to the era of
    old Toryism as distinctly as Denman, Campbell, Erle and
    Bramwell belonged to the age of Benthamite liberalism. But
    whilst our tribunals, or the judges of whom they are
    composed, are swayed by the prevailing beliefs of a
    particular time, they are also guided by professional opinions
    and ways of thinking which are to a certain extent
    independent of and possibly opposed to the general tone of
    public opinion. The judges are the heads of the legal
    profession. They are advanced in life. They are for the most
    part persons of a conservative disposition. They are in no
    way dependent for their emoluments, dignity, or reputation
    upon the favor of the electors, or even of ministers who
    represent in the long run the wishes of the electorate. They
    are more likely to be biased by professional habits and
    feeling than by the popular sentiment of the hour. Hence,
    judicial legislation will often be marked by certain
    characteristics rarely found in acts of Parliament.[53]


    The habits you are trained in, the people with whom you
    mix, lead to your having a certain class of ideas of such a
    nature that, when you have to deal with other ideas, you do
    not give as sound and accurate judgment as you would wish.
    This is one of the great difficulties at present with Labour.
    Labour says: "Where are your impartial Judges? They all
    move in the same circle as the employers and they are all
    educated and nursed in the same ideas as the employers.
    How can a labour man or a trade unionist get impartial
    justice?" It is very difficult sometimes to be sure that you
    have put yourself into a thoroughly impartial position
    between two disputants, one of your own class and one not
    of your class.[54]


When due process of law and the equal protection of the laws are under

interpretation the determination of the issues involved depend "in large

part upon the composition of the court of last resort at the particular time

when the issue comes before it."[55]


Governments were in process of formation in the United States when

eighteenth-century ideas of checking and dividing powers were uppermost in

political thought. John Randolph thought it was necessary to base

governments on the doctrine of original sin and the natural depravity of the

human race and to devise restraints accordingly.[56] From such a philosophy

there was evolved the dictum that what was desired was a "government of laws

and not men" -- or in English phraseology the supremacy of the laws.


Professor Dicey regarded the supremacy or rule of law as a characteristic of

the English constitution and explained that "it means, in the first place,

the absolute supremacy or predominance of regular law as opposed to the

influence of arbitrary power and excludes the existence of arbitrariness, of

prerogative, or even of wide discretionary authority on the part of the

government."[57] That there is a decline in the recognition accorded to the

rule of law, Dicey recognizes.[58] Coincident with this change in the

English legal system there is a noteworthy effort to foster the sanctity of

this rule as the central principle of constitutional government in the

United States.


The doctrine of judicial review of legislative enactments is regarded as a

practical and effective device to extend the rule of law. It has become part

of the creed of those who desire to apply the rule of law to all spheres of

government or to limit the omnipotent sovereign by a higher law either of a

fixed and immutable kind or of a variable content. If Lord Acton is correct

in the assertion that "the great question is to discover not what

governments prescribe but what they ought to prescribe," jurists are likely

to turn to the American practice of judicial review of legislative acts as a

practical means of enforcing the principles of a variable natural law,

though few will favor the adoption of such a practice if a natural law of an

eighteenth-century type is to be applied by justices who regard the

principles of this law as immutable.


Denying that they are applying anything but the express terms of written

constitutions the justices of higher courts in the United States have in

effect created a super-constitution, a superior law which in certain

respects is regarded as unchangeable by the people themselves. Safely

intrenched as the sole interpreters of this super-constitution they have

determined what is wise or unwise for the representatives of the people to

undertake in the realm of political experiment.[59] When a type of political

action is not liked it may readily be condemned as capricious or arbitrary

or unreasonable.


The warnings of the great constitutional lawyer, James Bradley Thayer,

however, may well cause us to ponder on the tendency to lean too heavily on

the courts.


    Great and, indeed, inestimable, as are the advantages in a
    popular government of this conservative influence, -- the
    power of the judiciary to disregard unconstitutional
    legislation, -- it should be remembered that the exercise of
    it, even when unavoidable, is always attended with a serious
    evil, namely the correction of legislative mistakes comes
    from the outside, and the people lose the political
    experience, and the moral education and stimulus that come
    from fighting the question out in an ordinary way, and
    correcting their own errors. If the decision in Munn v.
    Illinois, and in the "Granger Cases," twenty-five years ago,
    and in the "Legal Tender Cases," nearly thirty years ago,
    had been different; and the legislation there in question,
    thought by many to be unconstitutional and by many more to
    be ill advised, had been set aside, we should have been
    saved some trouble and some harm. But I venture to think
    that the good which came to the country and its people from
    the vigorous thinking that had to be done in the political
    debates that followed, from the infiltration through every part
    of the population of sound ideas and sentiments, from the
    rousing into activity of opposing elements, the enlargement
    of ideas, the strengthening of moral fibre, and the growth of
    political experience which came out of it all, -- that all this
    far more than outweighed any evil which ever flowed from
    the refusal of the court to interfere with the work of the
    legislature.


    The tendency of a common and easy resort to this great
    function, now lamentably too common, is to dwarf the
    political capacity of the people, and to deaden its sense of
    moral responsibility. It is no light thing to do that.


    What can be done? It is the courts that can do most to cure
    the evil; and the opportunity is a very great one. Let them
    resolutely adhere to first principles. Let them consider how
    narrow is the function which the constitutions have conferred
    on them, -- the office merely of deciding litigated cases;
    how large, therefore, is the duty entrusted to others, and
    above all to the legislature. It is that body which is charged,
    primarily, with the duty of judging of the constitutionality of
    its work. The constitutions generally give them no authority
    to call upon a court for advice; they must decide for
    themselves, and the courts may never be able to say a word.
    Such a body, charged, in every State, with almost all the
    legislative power of the people, is entitled to the most entire
    and real respect; is entitled, as among all rationally
    permissible opinions as to what the Constitution allows, to
    its own choice. Courts, as has often been said, are not to
    think of the legislators, but of the legislature, -- the great,
    continuous body itself, abstracted from all the transitory
    individuals who may happen to hold its power. It is this
    majestic representative of the people whose action is in
    question, a coordinate department of the government,
    charged with the greatest functions, and invested, in
    contemplation of law, with whatsoever wisdom, virtue, and
    knowledge the exercise of such functions requires.


    To set aside the acts of such a body, representing in its own
    field, which is the highest of all, the ultimate sovereign,
    should be a solemn, unusual, and painful act. Something is
    wrong when it can be other than that. And if it be true that
    the holders of legislative power are careless of evil, the
    constitutional duty of the court remains wholly untouched; it
    cannot rightly undertake to protect the people by attempting
    a function not its own. On the other hand, by adhering to its
    own place a court may help, as nothing else can, to fix the
    spot where responsibility rests, viz., on the careless and
    reckless legislators, and to bring down on that precise
    locality the thunderbolt of popular condemnation. The
    judiciary, today, in dealing with the acts of co-ordinate
    legislatures, owes to the country no greater or clearer duty
    than that of keeping its hands off these acts whenever it is
    possible to do it. That will powerfully help to bring the
    people and their representatives to a sense of their own
    responsibility.[60]


Under no system, Thayer thinks, can the courts go far to save the people

from ruin. We are much too apt to think of the judicial power of

disregarding acts of the other departments as our only protection against

oppression and ruin. But it is remarkable how small a part this played in

any of the debates on the federal Constitution. The chief protections were a

wide suffrage, short terms of office, a double legislative chamber, and the

so-called executive veto.[61]


The judges have insisted that when in doubt the courts should interpret

constitutional provisions favorable to legislative powers. If this principle

had been followed there would have been scant foundation for the

construction of implied limitations on legislatures; and due process of law

would have had slight effect on substantive legislative powers. Numerous

opinions of the Supreme Court give indisputable evidence that the Fourteenth

Amendment need not have been interpreted so as to greatly narrow the field

of state legislation. A continuous line of dissents by the justices of the

court in due process cases indicates that on a fair interpretation of the

language of the amendment the states might have been allowed much greater

freedom in the realm of social and economic legislation. The distinction is

sometimes not clearly recognized that the construction of an implied power

doctrine by which constitutional provisions are adapted to new conditions is

justifiable as a principle of legal growth, whereas the interpretation of a

doctrine of implied limitations as a means to retard and confine legal

development is indefensible.


Though the religious and metaphysical concepts of natural law, since the

eighteenth century, have had relatively slight influence in the growth of

law in the United States, natural law as an ideal has been a not

insignificant factor in the minds of judges and legislators as they were

molding into a system the legal materials at hand so as to meet the social,

economic, and political conditions of the day. And at the time that the

theories of the Positivist School of jurisprudence were prevailing, which

denied the potency of any natural law ideas, a pragmatic trend in American

legal philosophy was giving a new turn to the application of natural law

theories. When, through the prevalence of pioneer ideas and ideals,

governments were made more democratic and were gradually encouraged to

extend their control over many heretofore unregulated phases of economic

life restraints were sought to place restrictions on the zealous activities

of popularly elected representative bodies. It was then that the moral

obligation to govern reasonably and justly was translated into legal

phraseology by means of the old common law precept -- due process of law.


But instead of conceiving the moral duty to govern reasonably as an ideal to

which law was expected to conform in meeting the needs of a growing

community as conditions changed, it was thought of as a standard to protect

the interests of certain classes. Due process of law was to accord justice

not as required by the varying conditions of an increasingly complex

economic life but justice designed to make more secure the property or other

interests of those intrenched in power. By requiring certain formal criteria

for all legislative and administrative action the status quo economically

would not be too rudely or radically disturbed. Social and economic

conditions might be regulated within limited areas as long as due care was

taken to leave certain classes of property rights undisturbed. Due process

of law became the weapon for the application of a class reason and a class

justice.[62]


Building on the foundations of Wilson, Hamilton, Marshall, and Webster,

Justices Chase, Kent, Story, Cooley, with the aid of other justices in state

and federal courts, constructed a check which the conservative classes were

demanding. In applying Marshall's notable dictum that this was "a government

of laws and not of men" a criterion was evolved by which judges exercised a

selective process as to what were, in their judgment, properly called "laws"

and in this selective process the courts had in mind "a background of

fundamental principles" which are beyond the reach of any legislative

power.[63]


The modern American theories of natural law embodied as integral parts of

constitutional due process of law and equal protection of the laws are

essentially theories in terms of "the self-interest of the socially and

economically dominant class." Former theories, which were used to good

advantage when the English common law and the principles of Continental law

were adapted to the conditions of pioneer rural American conditions, have

become obstacles to change, devices to sanctify the existing legal order,

and sanctions for the maintenance of the status quo in the regulations of

economic and social conditions.[64]


                      APPENDIX


The avowed use of reasonableness and other concepts related to natural law

by the Justices of the Supreme Court of the United States in a single year

(October term, 1924) demonstrates the prominent place such ideas have

acquired in federal constitutional interpretation.


The fee fixed by a state act is arbitrary and the number of shares is not a

reasonable basis for the classification of foreign corporations for the

determination of an annual fee.[65]


There is no suggestion of a flagrant abuse or purely arbitrary exercise of

taxing power.


The Court will review a case only-when there is a question of law or when

action under a law is "clearly arbitrary or capricious."[66]


An assessment is not inherently arbitrary -- no unreasonable result.[67]


State assessments are valid unless "palpably arbitrary or a plain abuse of

power" or result in a "manifest and unreasonable discrimination."[68]


The action of a state utility commission must not pass beyond the bounds of

what is reasonable and suitable.[69]


The order of a utility commission is not "inherently arbitrary." [70]


An award of the Secretary of the Interior is held not "arbitrary or

capricious or fraudulent or an abuse of discretion."[71]


An order of a utility commission is held "arbitrary" and "capricious."[72]


The Fourth Amendment condemns unreasonable searches and seizures. A search

of an automobile for probable cause is held reasonable.[73]


The method of classification adopted in the Federal Income Tax is held not

"merely arbitrary and capricious."[74]


There is not an unreasonable interference with the liberty of contract.[75]


Classification for state taxation is held reasonable and valid when it does

not result in flagrant and palpable inequalities.[76]


A power exercised by Congress must be reasonably adapted to the effective

exercise of delegated powers.[77]


A provision was not so "unreasonable as to be a purely arbitrary mandate."

[78]


An inference allowed by law is held not "fanciful, arbitrary or

unreasonable."[79]


A rule of a utility commission is declared arbitrary and unjust. Utility

rates if unreasonable need not be confiscatory to be invalid.[80]


The court will give relief for arbitrary, unreasonable, and unlawful

interference with business and property and unreasonable interference with

the liberty of parents and guardians in bringing up children.[81]


There was no evidence of arbitrary or unfair action .[82]


State acts are unconstitutional only when they are arbitrary or unreasonable

attempts to exercise authority vested in the state. A statute is not an

arbitrary or unreasonable exercise of police power.[83]


Claims of unreasonable and arbitrary action, hostile discrimination, or

purely arbitrary exercise of power were made in numerous other cases passed

on by the court.


                   October Term, 1924


Total cases under the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments 45 cases


    A. Denial of due process of law under the Fourteenth Amendment
    distributed as follows: 27 cases
         State act or part of act held valid 8 
         State act or part of act held invalid 3 
         State administrative proceeding or order held valid 11 (relief
         denied 1) 
         State administrative proceeding or order held invalid 3 
         Judicial proceedings held valid 1 
         Denial of equal protection of laws 1 
    B. Denial of due process of law under the Fifth Amendment
    distributed as follows: 16 cases
         Act of Congress held valid 4 
         Act of Congress held invalid 0 
         Administrative proceedings held valid 7 
         Administrative proceedings held invalid 3 
         Judicial proceedings held valid 2 
         Decisions based on other provisions of Constitution (due
         process of law incidental) 2 cases 
    C. Grounds for appeal under due process provisions
         1. Attempt to protect personal rights


                         Proceedings     Proceedings
                         Valid           Invalid
               Fourteenth  7               3
               Amendment


               Fifth       7               2
               Amendment



              Individuals are granted relief in 5 cases 
         2. Corporations attack tax proceedings 11
              Corporations attack public utility regulations 7 
              Corporations secure relief in 10 cases 




1. A. J. Beveridge, The Life of John Marshall, III, 109.


2. F. N. Thorpe, "Hamilton's Ideas in Marshall's Decisions," Boston

University Law Review, I (1921), 9.


3. Edward Q. Keasbey, "The Courts and New Social Questions," Maryland State

Bar Association Proceedings (1911), p 105.


4. Dillon, Laws and Jurisprudence of England and America, p 204.


5. Pound, "The Growth of Administrative Justice," Wisconsin Law Review, II

(January, 1924), 327.


6. George C. Gorham, Biographical Notice of Stephen J. Field, p. 63.


7. Gorham, op. cit., p. 64.


8. Felix Frankfurter, "Twenty Years of Mr. Justice Holmes' Constitutional

Opinions," Harvard Law Review, XXXVI (June, 1923), 909; Pound, "Liberty of

Contract," Yale Law Journal, XVIII (May, 1909), 454, 470; and The Spirit of

The Common Law, p. 49.


9. Ex parte Wall, 107 U. S. 265 (1882).


10. Bartemeyer v. Iowa, 18 Wall. 129 (1873).


11. An able associate of Justice Field during the short term he served on

the court was Justice Strong. He not only joined Field in his dissents

condemning the legislative power to control property rights, but also became

an advocate of the federalist doctrine favorable to the protection of vested

rights, which, he claimed, "no matter how they arise, they are all equally

sacred, equally beyond the reach of legislative interference." Sinking Fund

Cases, 99 U. S. 700 (1878).


12. F. B. Clark, The Constitutional Doctrines of Justice Harlan, Johns

Hopkins University Studies, XXXIII (Baltimore, 1915), 4, 15.


13. Taylor v. Beckham, 178 U. S. 548, 601 (1899), and Clark, op. cit., p.

75. "The doctrine of legislative absolutism is foreign to free government as

it exists in this country," thought Justice Harlan. Ibid., p 609.


14. Norwood v. Baker, 172 U. S. 269 (1898).


15. Clark, op. cit., p. 144.


16. Justice Hough comments on the changing personnel at this time which

brought to the court in Justice Brewer "a powerful reinforcement of the

school of Field." Harv. Law Rev., XXXII, 228.


17. Obviously this was not thought to be the case with those who drafted the

instrument, or those who directed political affairs when it was put into

operation. Nor was this belief prevalent among the federalist leaders who

controlled the government during the fifty odd years that this party was in

power in one or more branches of the federal government. It remained for the

period after the Civil War, and for such defenders of the individualistic

faith as Justices Field and Brewer, to discover that the Declaration was the

cornerstone of the Constitution. See Carl Becker, The Declaration of

Independence (New York, 1922).


18. People v. Gillson, 109 N. Y. 389, 398, 399 (1888).


19. 198 U. S. 45 (1904).


20. For approval of the doctrine of this case see the opinion of Justice

Sutherland in Adkins v. Children's Hospital, 261 U. S. 525 (1922).


21. See Edward S. Corwin, "The Extension of Judicial Review in New York,"

Michigan Law Review, XV (February, 1917), 285.


22. James M. Rosenthal, "Massachusetts Acts and Resolves Declared

Unconstitutional by the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts,"

Massachusetts Law Quarterly, I (August, 1916), 303 ff.


23. Corwin, op. cit., pp. 303, 304.


24. Rosenthal, op. cit., p. 317.


25. Justice Woodward commented on the caution of the courts prior to the

Civil War in exercising the right to invalidate acts in Pennsylvania as

follows: "For nearly fifty years of our political existence under the

Constitution of 1790, no act of assembly was set aside for

unconstitutionality; judges claimed the power, and said they would exercise

it in clear cases, but in all that period no case arose which in their

judgment, was clear enough to justify the exercise of the power; and it is

well known that that great light of this bench so recently extinguished

[Chief Justice Gibson] stood opposed for many years to the existence of any

such power. Since the Constitution of 1838 was adopted several acts of

assembly have been declared unconstitutional, but they were all clear

cases." Sharpless v. Mayor of Philadelphia, 21 Penna. St. 148, 183 (1853).


26. Dr. Mott thinks the courts regard the Fourteenth Amendment as "a

constitutional ideal." Due Process of Law, p. 360. This is equivalent to the

view that the amendment is used to write into the fundamental law the ideals

which the justices believe ought to prevail. According to Justice Holmes due

process of law ought not to become "a pedagogical requirement of the

impracticable." Dominion Hotel v. Arizona, 249 U. S. 265, 268 (1918).


27. Le gouvernment des juges et la lutte centre la legislation sociale aux

États-Unis (Paris, 1921), pp. 32, 33, 41; also pp. 220, 221. See also,

Edouard Lambert and Halfred C. Brown, La lutte judiciaire du capital et du

travail organisés aux États-Unis (1924).


According to Professor Powell the "law of constitutional due process is

therefore as much judge-made law as any common law is judge-made law." "The

Judiciality of Minimum Wage Legislation," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVII, 545, 546.


28. Lambert, op. cit., pp. 53, 55, 60.


29. Cuthbert W. Pound, "Constitutional Aspects of Administrative Law," in

The Growth of American Administrative Law (St. Louis, 1923), p. 103.


30. A. M. Kales, "'Due Process,' the Inarticulate Major Premise and the

Adamson Act," Yale Law Jour., XXVI (May, 1917), 519.


31. According to Stephen Leacock, "American democracy, having by its

degradation of the legislature repudiated its first born child has set up

for itself the Mystic Worship of Judicial Interpretation." "The Limitations

of Federal Government," American Political Science Association Proceedings

(1908), p. 51.


32. Warren H. Pillsbury, "Administrative Tribunals," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI

(February and March, 1923), 405, 583.


33. For laissez faire theories, see People v. Coler, 166 N.Y. 1, 16-18,

23-25 (1901), and Ives v. South Buffalo Ry. Co., 201 N.Y. 271, 285-287,

203-295 (1911). The right to take property by will was held to be an

absolute and inherent right in Nunnemacher v. State, 129 Wis. 190, 198, 203

(1907); and the right of privacy was considered as "derived from natural

law" by Justice Cobb in Pavesich v. Life Ins. Co., 122 Ga. 190, 194 (1905).


34. Speaking of the dangers of socialism and communism, Mr. Guthrie says,"

Much is to be dreaded and guarded against in the despotism of the majority

wielding and abusing the power of legislation, and ignorantly or

intentionally undermining the foundations of the Constitution itself ... the

Fourteenth Amendment is the bulwark on which we place our reliance."

Lectures on the Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution of the United

States, pp. 30, 31. He admonishes the lawyers "to realize their duty to

teach people in season and out of season to value and respect individual

liberty and the rights of property." Ibid., p. 32.


35. For a summary of leading decisions, see "The Law of Nature in State and

Federal Judicial Decisions," Yale Law Jour., XXV (June, 1916), 617.


36. In declaring a law unconstitutional, a court must necessarily cover the

same ground which has already been covered by the legislative department in

deciding upon the propriety of the enactment. Cooley, Constitutional

Limitations (8th ed), I, 334.


37. "The Justices of the United States Supreme Court have taken counsel

together regarding the present political tendencies, so far as they seem to

the Justices to menace the Constitution, and have determined that upon the

Supreme Court rests the burden of standing between the Constitution and

popular passion." Quoted by Richard Olney, in "Discrimination against Union

Labor -- Legal?" American Law Review, XLII (March-April, 1908), 161; sec. 43

Cong. Rec. Pt. I, 20-22, message of President Roosevelt.


The change in the meaning of the terms "liberty" and "property" as used in

the Constitution from the narrow implications of physical liberty and

property to economic liberty, was "the reflection in the minds of the judges

of the business revolution which followed the extension of markets and the

political revolution that liberated the slaves." John R. Commons, Legal

Foundations of Capitalism, p. 283.


38. Ray A. Brown, "Due Process of Law, Police Power, and the Supreme Court,"

Harv. Law Rev., XL (May, 1927), 947. Cf. emergence of the court's doctrine

through Slaughter-House Cases, 16 Wall. 36 (1872); Bartemeyer v. Iowa, 18

Wall. 129 (1873); Missouri Pacific Ry. v. Humes, 115 U. S. 512 (1885), and

Mugler v. Kansas, 123 U. S. 623 (1887).


39. Henry Rottschaefer, "The Field of Governmental Price Control," Yale Law

Jour., XXXV (February, 1926), 438.


40. Thomas Reed Powell, op. cit., p. 545.


41. The real object at present of the due process clauses of the federal

Constitution is to enable the Supreme Court to determine whether acts of

Congress or of the state legislatures are reasonable. Cf. Willis, op. cit.,

pp. 338, 339. Mr. Willis suggests an addition to the Fourteenth Amendment to

the effect that the due process clause shall not be interpreted to include

matters of substantive law. Ibid., pp. 343, 344.


42. "The Theory of Judicial Decision," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI (May, 1923),

808.


43. Cf. Pound, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (New Haven, 1922),

pp. 50-52.


44. "The objection to this view is that the court must judge by a standard

of fairness that is not, and could not be, definitely expressed in the

Constitution. This, of course, is the fundamental difficulty in all due

process cases. Groping for some standards, the courts are tempted to revert

to the old language of natural rights, as though such rights were an

over-law above the Constitution itself." Note on the case of Moore v.

Dempsey, Harv. Law Rev., XXXVII (December, 1923), 250.


"No state can make or enforce any laws which shall, upon proper proceedings,

be deemed unreasonable by a majority of the Supreme Court ... the rule of

reason alone governs. What are fair profits, what are excessive taxes, what

are proper health laws, what is confiscation and what discrimination; --

these are questions which cannot be answered in the abstract, nor can they

be adequately defined by precedents." Collins, The Fourteenth Amendment and

the States, p. 109.


45. "All nineteenth century theories of judicial decision," says Dean Pound,

"in one way or another grow out of the natural law thinking of the

seventeenth and eighteenth centuries." "The Theory of Judicial Decision,"

Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI (May, 1923), 802.


46. Cf. Pound, The Spirit of the Common Law, p. 37. "With us the basis of

all deduction is the classical common law -- the English decisions and

authorities of the seventeenth, eighteenth and first half of the nineteenth

centuries. Our jurists have made of this a very Naturrecht. They have asked

us to test all new situations and new doctrines by it.... More than this,

through the power of courts over unconstitutional legislation and the

doctrine that our bills of right are declaratory, courts have forced it upon

modern social legislation." Pound, in Harv. Law Rev., XXIV (June, 1911),

601.


47. M. R. Cohen in Introduction to Pierre de Tourtoulon, Philosophy in the

Development of Law, trans. by Martha Read, Modern Legal Philosophy Series,

XIII (New York, 1922), 24.


48. "The influence of the conception of natural rights on legal development

in the United States has been to support the position of a reactionary,

dominant, propertied class." James Mickel Williams, The Foundations of

Social Science (New York, 1920), p. 245.


49. John H. Clarke, "Judicial Power to Declare Legislation

Unconstitutional," American Bar Association Journal, IX (November, 1923),

691.


50. For the claim that logic alone guides judges in reviewing the validity

of legislative acts see opinion of Justice White, that "no instance is

afforded from the foundation of the government where an act, which was

within a power conferred, was declared to be repugnant to the Constitution,

because it appeared to the judicial mind that the particular exertion of

constitutional power was either unwise or unjust." McCray v. United States,

195 U. S. 27, 54 (1904). "August as are the functions of the Supreme Court,"

says John W. Davis, "surely they do not go one step beyond the

administration of justice to individual litigants." "Present Day Problems,"

Amer. Bar Assoc. Jour., IX (September, 1923), 557.


51. Cf. Felix Frankfurter, "A Note on Advisory Opinions," Harv. Law Rev.,

XXXVII (June, 1924), 1002, and especially list of cases turning on facts;

also Henry Wolf Biklé, "Judicial Determination of Questions of Fact

affecting Constitutional Validity of Legislative Action," Harv. Law Rev.,

XXXVIII (November, 1924), 6.


52. "Logical Method and Law," Cornell Law Quarterly, X (December, 1924), 26.


53. A. V. Dicey, Lectures on the Relation between Law and Public Opinion in

England during the Nineteenth Century (New York, 1905), pp. 361, 362.


54. Lord Justice Scrutton, "The Work of the Commercial Courts," Cambridge

Law Journal, I, 6, 8. For the opinion that the House of Lords as a supreme

judicial body is "in entire good faith, the unconscious servant of a single

class in the community," see Harold J. Laski, "Judicial Review of Social

Policy in England," Harv. Law Rev., XXXIX (May, 1926), 848.


55. Powell, Harv. Law Rev., XXXVII, p. 546. Combating the doctrine that the

judges should be made the ultimate arbiters of all constitutional questions,

Jefferson wrote: "This is a very dangerous doctrine indeed, and one which

would place us under the despotism of an oligarchy. Our judges are as honest

as other men and not more so. They have, with others, the same passions for

party, for power and the privilege of their corps. Their maxim is 'boni

judicis est ampliare jurisdictionem,' and their power the more dangerous as

they are in office for life, and not responsible, as the other functionaries

are, to the elective control." To William Charles Jarvis, Sept. 28, 1820;

also to William Johnson, June 12, 1823.


56. Cf. 10th Cong., 1st Sess. (Nov. 13, 1807), Jefferson also observed: "In

questions of power, then, let no more be heard of confidence in man, but

bind him down from mischief by the chains of the constitution."


57. A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution

(8th ed., London, 1915), p. 198.


58. Ibid., Introduction, pp. xxxvi ff.


59. "The American democracy in political and social matters is made to

accord strictly with extreme conservatism and considers its foundation at

the same time as an eternal divine moral and legal order." Ernst Troeltsch,

Naturrecht und Humanitat in der Weltpolitik (Berlin, 1923), p. 6.


60. Thayer's Marshall, pp. 103, 110, and Legal Essays (Boston, 1908), pp.

39-41.


61. Ibid., p. 64; Legal Essays, pp. 11-12. For weaknesses of Marshall's

reasoning in the Marbury Case, consult Thayer, Legal Essays, p. 15.


62. Speaking of the theories which justices have read into the Fourteenth

Amendment, Dean Pound says, "A theory that legislators and courts are but

the mouthpieces through which the dominant class makes its will effective, a

theory of law in terms of the self-interest of the socially and economically

dominant class, a theory that the jurist may do no more than observe and

record the phenomena of the transitional stage of hopeless conflict while

one class is gaming the upper hand at the expense of its predecessors in the

economic and social order -- such a theory is more threatening to the

general security than any of the recent modifications and adaptations of the

atomistic individualism of the eighteenth century of which recent

legislation has been so fearful." Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI (May, 1923), 824.

See also G. C. Henderson, The Position of Foreign Corporations in American

Constitutional Law (Cambridge, 1918), p. 163.


63. A. M. Kales, op. cit., p. 526.


Referring to the decisions of the Supreme Court in the Hitchman and Coppage

Cases, Professor John R. Commons says, "It is the judge who believes in the

law and custom of business and not the judge who believes in the law and

custom of labor, that decides." And, he notes, it is not logic but beliefs

which are the determining factors in such decisions. Op. cit., p. 298.


64. Cf. Pound, "The Theory of Judicial Decision," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI

(May, 1923), 808, 824.


65. Airway Electric Appliance Corporation v. Day, 266 U. S. 71.


66. Missouri Pacific R. R. v. Road Dist., 266 U. S. 187; Silberschein v.

United States, 266 U. S. 221.


67. Bass, Ratcliff and Gretton Ltd. v. State Tax Commission, 266 U. S. 271.


68. Kansas City Southern R. R. et al. v. Road Improvement Dist., 266 U. S.

379.


69. Michigan Public Utilities Commission v. Duke, 266 U. S. 570.


70. Fort Smith Light and Traction Co. v. Bourland, 267 U. S. 330.


71. Work v. Rives, 267 U. S. 175.


72. Ohio Utility Co. v. Public Utilities Commission, 267 U. S. 359.


73. Carroll v. United States, 267 U. S. 132.


74. Barclay and Co. v. Edwards, 267 U. S. 442.


75. Yeiser v. Bysart, 267 U. S. 540.


76. Stebbins and Hurley v. Riley, 268 U. S. 137.


77. Linder v. United States, 268 U. S. 5.


78. Yee Hem v. United States, 268 U. S. 178.


79. North Laramie Land Co. v. Hoffman, 268 U. S. 276.


80. Banton v. Belt Line Ry., 268 U. S. 413.


81. Pierce v. Society of the Sisters, 268 U. S. 510.


82. Maple Flooring Manufacturers Association v. United States, 268 U. S.

563.


83. Gitlow v. People of New York, 268 U. S. 652.



                     PART IV


  THE REVIVAL OF DROIT NATUREL, NATURRECHT, AND
SUPERIOR LAW DOCTRINES IN THE JURISTIC PHILOSOPHY
                OF EUROPEAN WRITERS


                    CHAPTER IX


 THE BACKGROUND FOR RECENT THEORIES OF NATURAL
  LAW AND THE GERMAN DOCTRINE OF A RECHTSSTAAT


1. Continuance of Natural Law Theories in Europe. A brief resume of the

stages in the evolution of higher law concepts has shown that for centuries

after the Reformation natural law theories, as expounded in the

authoritative works of the time, were commonly accepted as the basis of law

both public and private. When positivists' theories of law were gaining

ground over mediaeval conceptions the American and French Revolutions gave

an impetus to another version of the natural law theories and to the

rechristened dogma of the natural and inalienable rights of man, which it

was the prime duty of the state to protect. But the reaction which followed

these revolutions tended to discredit the idea of natural rights both in

Europe and in America. During the middle of the nineteenth century there was

a decline in the emphasis placed on natural law thinking and on the

importance attributed to higher law concepts. Throughout the nineteenth

century ideas of higher law, however, had many supporters in Europe among

jurists and statesmen.


Modern theories of law were greatly influenced by the contributions to

philosophy of two German thinkers, Kant and Hegel. Kant sought to discover

principles which were above all codes and legislative enactments and to

furnish a criterion to estimate the validity of all legal rules.[1] Though

Kant, like Rousseau, predicated certain limits to the powers of the state he

also ended by conceding practically limitless power in the ruling forces of

the state. His categorical imperative -- "Act on a maxim which thou canst

will to be law universal" -- involved a combination of the idea of personal

duty and of universal law. The state he conceived as a formula whereby the

authority of the general will is made consistent with the perfect freedom of

the individual will. It is only by means of a social contract after the

pattern of Rousseau that such legal legerdemain can be consummated. But

Kant's individualism prevented him from going to the limit of Rousseau in

subordinating the individual will to that of organized society.


To Hegel the individual finds his existence in the state. The individual is

free only by merging his will with that of the state. He rejected entirely

the American and French doctrines of natural and inalienable rights. Liberty

can be realized only through the state.[2] Like Rousseau and Kant, Hegel

claimed that the individual has rights in the true sense only when they come

from the state. While the philosophy of Rousseau, of Kant, and of Hegel

tended in the direction of absolute authority in the state there were

noteworthy lines of legal thought leading in the opposite direction.


Among the political thinkers of the early nineteenth century who sought to

secure guaranteed juridical limitations upon the sovereignty of the state

was Benjamin Constant, who claimed that sovereignty exists only in a limited

and relative manner. At the point where the independence of the individual

begins, he asserted, the jurisdiction of sovereignty ends.[3] He defended

the natural and indefeasible rights of the individual which form the basis

of the juridical limitations on sovereignty. "I maintain," he said, "that

individuals have rights and that these rights are independent of social

authority, which cannot curtail them without becoming guilty of

usurpation."[4] He believed that the individual had a right to refuse to

obey a law contrary to the incontestable rights and pointed the way to a

supreme court whose duty it should be to preserve these rights and to

prevent the public powers from encroaching on them.[5]


After the completion of the Code Napoleon a school of legal philosophers

again recurred to the earlier natural law notions. The rules elaborated in

the codes were thought to be derived from man's nature and were regarded as

independent of observation and experience. These natural laws were

considered universal and invariable and positive laws to be valid should

emanate from them.[6]


Among the leading natural law exponents in the nineteenth century were Karl

Christian F. Krause who conceived of law as a postulate of reason and based

his philosophy of law and justice essentially upon the doctrine of natural

law,[7] and Heinrich Ahrens, who accepted the philosophy of law of Krause

and gave it wide circulation throughout Europe. His leading work,[8]

originally published in French and German, passed through many editions and

became the authoritative textbook of a modernized version of the ancient

doctrine. To Ahrens the philosophy of law and natural law are

interchangeable terms and comprise the science which analyzes the first

principles of law as conceived by reason. This science is based on the

belief common to humanity, that principles of justice exist independent of

law and of positive institutions, suitable for adaptation to all of the

changes to which human nature is susceptible. Ahrens distinguished between

the will of the legislature (mens legis) and the reason of the law (ratio

legis) which renders law in accord with the eternal principles of the true

and the good. These higher or natural principles of law, he thought, are

deduced from the nature and destiny of man.[9] The principles of the French

Revolution developed in these works gradually introduced natural law ideas

into the standard treatises and commentaries on French law.[10] Dalloz gives

an extensive account of the natural rights which are regarded as belonging

to man as an individual.[11] To Laurent "a right [droit] is anterior to a

law; it is based on the nature of men and of civil societies... there is an

eternal law [droit], an expression of absolute justice. This law or right

[droit] reveals itself to the human conscience, in a measure as man

approaches divine perfection. This law is progressive as are all

manifestations of the human spirit. It tends continuously to realize

absolute truth. It is necessary for the legislature to follow the progress

which is made through the general conscience of man."[12]


Catholic or Traditionalist leaders repudiated the natural rights theories

of the Revolution but predicated a higher law of another type. Saint Martin,

De Maistre, De Bonald, Ballanche, and Lamennais set in opposition to the

Declaration of the Rights of Man a Declaration of the Rights of God.[13] For

these leaders of the Theocratic School political authority emanates from God

and not from a mythical state of nature or from inherent qualities of the

individual. To the rights of man De Bonald opposed as superior and paramount

the rights of God and to the sovereignty of reason he opposed the

sovereignty of faith.[14] The reconciliation of man to the ways of God was

made under the directing influence of nature or natural rights as belonging

to the individual, which appealed to the Traditionalists for they directed

their attacks against eighteenth-century individualism and the doctrines of

the Declaration of Rights. That there is no sovereignty is also the

underlying principle of Royer-Collard's political theory.[15] In order to

limit the powers of the state and in order to preserve individual liberty he

regarded it necessary to discard the concept of sovereignty. Guizot, who

supported the doctrine of limitations upon the state based on a higher law,

was a follower of Royer-Collard.[16] In fact, Victor Cousin, Royer-Collard,

and Guizot appealed to reason as a basis to support aristocracy and the rule

of the wisest.[17] Since the Traditionalists made religion the basis of

political stability and the following of the laws of God the first requisite

for the rulers and the people in a well-ordered society, their doctrines

were quite acceptable to a large group in French society which has always

been influential in political circles. The modern revival of the

Traditionalist type of thinking, which will be considered in a later

section, justifies the comment of Laski that "the authoritarian tradition is

far from dead."[18]


Except for the Catholic Schools there were few in France during the middle

of the nineteenth century who publicly supported the theories of natural

rights, which held such a prominent place during the French Revolution. In

the latter part of the century A. Boistel, Beudant, and Henri Michel tried

to revive interest again in the former ideas of individual natural rights.


Boistel used the philosophy of law, the law of reason, and the law of nature

as approximately interchangeable terms.[19] Natural law or the droit

rationnel was defined as "the group of rules which in the light of reason

ought to be sanctioned by an exterior constraint." He regarded the principle

at the basis of law which justifies its maintenance as "the inviolability of

human personality."[20] From this individualistic principle he sought to

develop an entire legal system.[21] This point of view led to an

overemphasis on the individual moral personality and to a depreciation of

the social and collective influences in the development of the law.[22]


Beudant, returning to the Declaration of Rights of 1789 and to the former

schools of natural law, "based law upon reason, opposed individual rights to

the state, and even exaggerated that opposition by seeing in every case of

state intervention a restriction of individual rights."[23] Human rights,

he thought, exist before the law and they are above the laws.[24]


After a survey of the political and economic thought of France during the

nineteenth century in which one of the dominant ideas was the reaction

against the individualistic philosophy of the French Revolution, Michel

defends the essential doctrines of the individualistic school. He believes

there is "an individualism based on the living sentiment and the dignity of

the human person" which is at the very foundation of the social and

political order.[25] State action, he thinks, must continuously be

subordinated to the rights of the individual. "Individualism, as we

conceive it, is alone capable of furnishing a rational foundation for the

philosophy of law as well as for political liberty and for the sovereignty

of the people."[26] Michel contended that not only was the state obligated

not to interfere with the natural rights of man but it was also its duty to

render positive services in the way of furnishing work, assistance, and

instruction.


Boistel, Beudant, Michel, and other legal philosophers aimed to turn legal

thinking again either to the natural law theories of St. Thomas, transformed

to meet the conditions of nineteenth-century Europe, or to the inherent

rights of man which, according to the Declarations, were above and beyond

the sphere of state authority. But these efforts to restore higher law ideas

to a measure of their former prestige and influence were not generally

approved owing to the dominance of the Positivist concepts both in legal

theory and in political practice. The attempts to turn legal thinking in the

channels of natural rights as conceived by the leaders of the French

Revolution and to emphasize again the rights of the individual proved futile

at a time when political and economic thought was beginning to be dominated

by a social point of view. It remained for a modern school of jurists to

adapt the natural law concepts to radically different economic and social

conditions.


By the end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of the modern era the

efforts to revive natural law thinking interested so many jurists and legal

philosophers in Europe that a revival of this mode of thinking has become a

phase of a national and an international movement. The nature of this

movement can best be comprehended through the presentation of some of the

salient views of representative thinkers belonging to the new school. Though

the representatives selected differ widely in their approaches to the

problem and formulate divergent phases of the necessity of a return to

higher law theories, they have elements in common which make it appropriate

to consider their contributions to this phase of legal thought.


2. German Doctrine of a Rechtsstaat. The inspiration for some of the most

suggestive higher law theories of modern times may be found in the thorough

and stimulating investigations of Otto Gierke. Not only have his works

furnished a clue for an attack on the absolute theories of sovereignty in

Europe but also they have given an impetus to a new school of political

theorists, the Pluralists, who deny the unity, inclusive, and thoroughgoing

supremacy of political sovereigns.


Gierke, as previously noted, analyzed distinctly the mediaeval doctrine as

to the relations of law and the state. The state, according to the

mediaevalists, was not based on law but on moral necessity; its aim was the

promotion of human welfare and the realization of law was one of the

appropriate means to this end.[27] The state and the law were of equal rank

and one did not depend upon the other. A distinction was made between the

natural laws, which were above the state, and the positive laws, which could

in no way bind the sovereign.[28] And there was everywhere a tendency to set

limits to the growing powers of sovereignty. These limits might be ascribed

to the overruling natural law, to vague theoretical limits arising from the

necessity of the consent of the community, or to the insistent claims for a

recognition of rights by smaller groups within the confines of the state.

With this background Gierke was led to regard it as "impossible to make the

state logically prior to law [Recht] or to make law logically prior to the

state, since each exists in, for and by the other."[29] Though today the

state is a lawmaking authority, it does not become, Gierke asserted, either

the final source of law or a unique organ for its making. The real source of

law is to be found in the common feelings or sentiments of the people. And

while it is the chief function of the state to express in law the juridical

conscience of the people other organs than the state participate in the

lawmaking process.[30] A philosophic basis was established for a

Rechtsstaat, or a state founded on justice, which has received the support

of some of the foremost jurists of Germany.[31]


Though modern natural law theories are advocated for extremely divergent

purposes and in strikingly varied forms, the influence of Gierke's views may

readily be discovered in many of the recent attempts to revive the higher

law philosophy.


3. Current Views Relating to Natural Law in Germany. Despite the espousal of

natural law theories by prominent German jurists and philosophers during the

eighteenth and the nineteenth centuries, the influence of Kant, Hegel, and

Von Ihering combined with the growing sentiment of nationalism turned legal

thought in a direction which fostered state omnipotence and led to the

repudiation of every type of higher law philosophy. Hence, most contemporary

German legal philosophers have rejected the system of natural law and have

asserted that law is derived exclusively from the state. "It is without

doubt a great advance of modern philosophy of law, as distinguished from the

earlier law of nature," observed Ihering, "that it has recognized and

forcibly emphasized the dependence of law upon the state."[32] To Ihering

the state is society exercising coercion and law is the policy of force; or

in the principles of Treitschke: "Der Staat ist Macht."[33]


Joseph Kohler from a different standpoint joined the critics of natural law

concepts. Natural law, which had protected the nations against the caprice

of princes and the papal power and had upheld the demands of what was

reasonable in the face of what had become historical, since Hugo Grotius, he

thought, has done scarcely more than to serve as the basis for an emerging

international law. "At the beginning, natural law may have had significance

as a protection against arbitrary rule, but this it soon lost, at least in

Germany and France, and became instead the hobby of well-meaning absolutism

which undertook to maintain natural law by setting its foot on the neck of

the nation and trying to force it to be good, just, and happy."[34] On the

other hand, the patriots of the French Revolution made use of it in

unfurling the banner of rebellion. There is, he maintains, no eternal law --

the law that is suitable for one period is not so for another.


Ehrlich also criticizes the Naturrecht philosophy as invariably resulting

in an individualistic jurisprudence. There is, he insists, no individual

right -- every right is a social right.[35]


The prevailing German doctrine, which is based on the repudiation of natural

law and of inalienable rights, results in the denial that constitutions are

laws and that such written enactments[36] have any superior validity. At

best it accords limits to the powers of the state based on self-denying

ordinances or auto-limitations which rest for their enforcement with the

consciences of those who control the destinies of the state.[37] Hence, the

Naturrecht philosophy, though frequently defended by German jurists, was

vigorously attacked by the Positivists and by the Sociological School of

jurisprudence. It is significant, however, that in the wake of a thorough

repudiation of the natural rights theories German legal thinkers are again

leading the movement for a revival of natural law.[38]


At the same time that legal philosophers and jurists of continental Europe

regard the eighteenth- and early nineteenth-century notions of fixed and

immutable natural or higher laws as repudiated, there has arisen a juristic

movement which may be termed "a revival of juridical idealism" which is

bringing to the forefront again the doctrine of natural law. One of the

best-known exponents of this juridical idealism, Rudolf Stammler, gave the

clue to the new movement when he insisted that he was not an advocate of a

fixed and immutable natural law but of "a natural law with a variable

content."[39] Stammler believes that law comes before the state and that the

state is a creature of law.[40]


In setting for himself the problem of finding the "just law" or "richtige

Recht" Stammler repudiates the a priori principles of the old natural law

and instead aims to determine a formal criterion by which law may be

evaluated. The concept of just law is based on a fundamental characteristic

of the social order, namely, a feeling for right or a longing for

justice.[41] Stammler, as a follower of Kant, sought to formulate by pure

reason "a formal method of general validity." Though he recognized that

purely formal law may for the time being prevail over "fundamentally just

law" in due course such formal law must be tested by and subordinated to the

higher conception of "richtige Recht."[42] Hence, he turned to what he

regards as a "fundamentally and eternally true idea of natural law, which

implies a content in agreement with the nature of law rather than with the

nature of man."[43]


It is interesting to note that Stammler's theory of just law has nothing to

do with the validity of any particular law. "Just law" is to be used for the

interpretation of legal rules only when the legislature grants such

authority. To allow judges or other officers to refuse to enforce laws

because they consider them as unjust, Stammler thinks, would substitute the

arbitrary will of a few individuals for the regular and orderly authority of

established legal rules.[44] Geny, who regards Stammler as the foremost

legal philosopher of modern Germany, believes that the great defect of his

speculations lies in the failure to relate "richtige Recht" to the positive

law of a given country.[45] His efforts seemed to be exhausted in making

distinctions and in laying down criteria. What appears to many to show the

utter impracticability of his theorizing is to be found in the observation

that "the principles of just law do not contain in their idea and form

anything of the specific content of positive law." [46]


That there is a law in agreement with nature or reason and which should

remain once and for all absolutely just, Stammler denies. But he advocates a

law of nature which may serve as a formal criterion or standard to test the

justice of a given law and insists that the standard or criterion is not a

law; by it primarily legal concepts are judged and characterized as just or

unjust. "Just law, like the law of nature, is a law or laws with specific

legal content which is in accord with the standard. It is then objectively

just, but not absolutely just; for the moment the circumstances change, the

same legal content will no longer be in accord with the standard and hence

will cease to be just."[47]


Efforts to direct attention again to the Naturrecht philosophy in Germany

have received their chief support either from those who belong to schools

imbued with religious or metaphysical speculations or from those who are

seeking a basis for a new international law outside of conventional legal

rules. Each of these tendencies will be considered in subsequent sections.


The modern revival of natural law philosophy is frequently advocated in

France and it will be of interest to give a condensed account of the views

of a few representative French authorities.




1. Metaphysik der Silten: Metaphysische Anfangsgrunde der Rechtslehre (2d

ed., 1798). Kant's legal doctrines may be found in The Philosophy of Law, An

Exposition of the Fundamental Principles of Jurisprudence as the Science of

Right, trans. by W. Hastie (Edinburgh, 1887). Cf. also Duguit, "The Law and

the State," Harvard Law Review, XXXI (November, 1917), 40 ff., and Michel,

L'ldée de l'état, pp. 49 ff.


2. Hegel's Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, oder Naturrecht und

Staatswissenchaft im Grundrisse (1821); Hegel's Philosophy of Right, trans.

by S. W. Dyde (London, 1896). Hegel's theories of the state, sovereignty,

and law were well designed to support a monarchy of the Prussian type.

Duguit, op. cit., pp. 57 ff.


3. Cours de politique constitutionelle, 4 vols. (Paris, 1819), I, 177, 306;

Michel, op. cit., pp. 299 ff.


4. Cf. Duguit, op. cit., pp. 105 ff.


5. Duguit speaks of Constant's doctrine on this point as "the French

classical doctrine." For the advocacy of a similar doctrine by a German

writer, consult Gerber, Grundzuge des deutschen Staatsrechts (3d ed., 1880).

Duguit, op. cit., pp. 119 ff.


For a defence of the rule of reason as a superior legal principle, consult

Victor Cousin, Cours d'histoire de la philosophie morale au 18e siècle

(1839).


6. Progress of Continental Law in the Nineteenth Century, Continental Legal

History Series, p. 26.


7. See his Grundlage des Naturrechts, oder philosophischer Grundriss des

Ideals des Rechts (Jena, 1803), and Abriss des Systems der Philosophie des

Rechts oder des Naturrechts (Göttingen, 1828).


8. Cours de droit naturel ou de philosophie du droit (Brussels, 1836-39). M.

Roder was also a disciple of Krause; see his Grundzuge des Naturrechts und

der Rechtsphilosophie (2d ed., 1860).


Josef Kohler thinks that books like those of Ahrens, Krause, and Röder "are

not even worth enumerating; they are products of utter banality and poverty

of ideas." Philosophy of Law, p. 25. This harsh judgment, like similar

judgments of Kohler, does not do justice to the influence of these men on

legal thought.


9. Ahrens, op. cit., I, (6th ed., Leipzig, 1868), 1 ff., 96 ff.; II, 1 ff.,

146.


10. For a consideration of natural rights sanctioned by the Code Napoleon,

consult Duguit, Les transformations du droit privé (Paris, 1912).


11. See Répertoire de legislation de doctrine et de jurisprudence, XIX (new

ed., 1852), 11 ff., and Supplement, VI (Paris, 1890), 425 ff.


12. F. Laurent, Principes de droit civil (5th ed., 1893), I, pp. 50, 51.

Pothier used natural law to supplement and modify Roman law rules as to

contracts in laying the basis for a principle of modern Continental European

law, that deliberate promises, being morally binding, were legally binding.

Traité des obligations, Pt. I, chap. 1. Cited in Pound, Law and Morals, pp.

91, 92.


13. See De Bonald, Discours préliminaire a la legislation primitive; also

Theories du pouvoir politique et rellgieux dans la société civile (1796),

and Essai analytique sur des lois naturelles de l'ordre social (1817).

Harold J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (New Haven, 1919), chap. 2

and chap. 3 on Lamennais. Joseph De Maistre, Considerations sur la France

(1796); Essai sur le principe générateur des constitutions politiques et des

autres institutions humaines (1810). For summary of the theocratic theories

in the reaction against the political philosophy of the French Revolution,

consult Michel, op. cit., pp. 99 ff., and Harold J. Laski, "De Maistre and

Bismarck," in Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (New Haven, 1917).


14. Laski, Authority in the Modern State, p. 130.


15. Laski, Authority in the Modern State, chap. 4; Michel, op. cit., pp.

200-209.


16. Michel, op. cit., pp. 203 ff.


17. Cf. Alfred Fouillee, Idée moderns du droit, trans. in Modern French

Legal Philosophy, Modern Legal Philosophy Series, VII (Boston, 1916), 152.


18. Laski, Authority in the Modern State, p. 167.


19. A. Boistel, Cours de philosophie du droit I (Paris, 1899), 1. The

original work based on the principles formulated by Rosmini was issued in

1870.


20. Ibid., pp 72 ff.


21. Geny criticizes Boistel's work as based on artificial reasoning to

which the author attaches objective validity. It has the result, he thinks,

"to give an assured place only to a small number of general ideas, derived

from a very exalted sphere, but scarcely capable from these alone to lead to

anything else than an inspiration of justice." Francois Geny, Science el

technique en droit privé positif (Paris, 1915), II, 292-294.


22. Cf. M. Hauriou, "Philosophie du droit et science sociale," Revue du

droit public, XII (1899), 462.


23. Charmont, La Renascence du droit naturel (Paris and Montpellier, 1910).


24. Cf. his work on Le droit individuel et l'état.


25. Michel, op. cit., p. 628. "The idea of the sublime dignity of the human

person is what the eighteenth century has bequeathed to us." Ibid., pp. 60,

644.


26. Michel, op. cit., p. 630.


27. Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Ages, p. 74.


28. Ibid., p. 78.


29. Gierke, op. cit., Maitland's Introduction, p. xliii.


30. There is between law and the State [says Gierke] a reciprocal

penetration of a particularly close and intimate nature. The law is innate

in the State. Law is no more begotten by the State than the State is

begotten by law. But, although each has its own reasons for being, each is

developed by the other.... Today the State acts as an organ in the formation

of law. But for that reason the State does not become either the ultimate

source of law or the sole organ in its formation. The ultimate source of law

resides rather in the common consciousness of the social being. The common

belief that something is right needs, for its external realization,

materialization by a social expression, as for instance, in a rule of law

... not infrequently this expression takes place through and by means of the

State, which has for its principal role the shaping of the juridical

consciousness of the people in the form of law. But social organisms other

than the State can formulate law.... Juridical life and the life of the

State are two independent sides of social life. While power is a rational

condition of the State because a State without omnipotence is not a State,

it is immaterial, so far as the notion of law is concerned, that there

exists for it means of external power; for law without power and without

action always remains law. Gierke, "Die Grundbegriffe des Staatsrechts und

die neuester Staatstheorien," Zeitschrift für die gesammte

Staafswissenschaft, p. 306; quoted by Duguit, op. cit., pp. 159, 160. Cf.

comments by Gierke in Zeitschrift fur die gesammte Staatswissenschaft

(Tubingen, 1874), p. 179.


31. See also Gierke, Johannes Althusius und die Entwickelung der

naturrechtlichen Staatstheorien (3d ed., Breslau, 1913), chap. 6.


32. Der Zweck im Recht (1877), trans. in part in Law as a Means to an End.

Modern Legal Philosophy Series, V (Boston, 1913), 178. For a criticism of

the eighteenth-century natural rights theories, see L. von Savigny, "Das

Naturrechtsproblem und die Methode seiner Lösung," Jahrbuch fur

Gesetzgebung, Vervaltung und Volkswirtschaft im Deutschen Reich, G.

Schmoller, XXX, 407-417.


33. Treitschke, Politik (Berlin und Leipzig, 1890-1900). Cf. Duguit, op.

cit., pp. 126 ff.


34. Kohler, Lehrbuch der Rechtsphilosophie, trans. as Philosophy of Law in

Modern Legal Philosophy Series, XII (Boston, 1914), 5, 6, 10.


35. Eugene Ehrlich, Grundlegung der Soziologie des Rechts (Leipzig, 1913),

P. 34; "Es gibt kein Individualrecht, jedes Recht ist ein Sozialrecht. Das

Leben kennt den Menschen als einem aus dem zusammenhange gerissenen

einzelnen und einzigen nicht, und auch dem Recht ist ein solches Wesen

fremd."


36. This is the doctrine which Hauriou styles the "brigandage juridique" in

"Le droit naturel et l'allemagne," Le Correspondant, CCLXXH (September 25,

1918), 913.


37. Ihering, Der Zweck im Recht (1880), pp. 318, 344, and Law as a Means to

an End, pp. 267, 314; Jellinek, Allgemeine Staatslehre (1900), pp. 303, 330

ff.


38. Erich Jung, Das Problem des naturlichen Rechts (Leipzig, 1912); Alfred

Manigk, Wo stehen wir heute sum Naturrecht? (Berlin-Grunewald, 1926).


39. Cf. Stammler, Wirtschaft und Recht (2d ed.), pp. 165, 176, 181, 456;

Theorie der Rechtswissenschaft (Halle, 1911), pp. 124 ff.; Die Lehre von dem

Richtigen Rechte, 2 vols. (Berlin, 1902-07), I, pp. 93 ff., 196 ff. The last

of these volumes has been translated in the Modern Legal Philosophy Series

under the title, The Theory of Justice (New York, 1926).


40. "Fundamental Tendencies in Modern Jurisprudence," Michigan Law Review,

XXI (April, 1923), 623, 765.


41. The Theory of Justice, pp. 22, 116.


42. See F. Geny, "Critical System of Stammler," in The Theory of Justice,

pp. 508 ff.


43. Ibid., p. 516.


44. The Theory of Justice, pp. 81, 511 ff.


45. Ibid., p. 548.


46. Ibid., p. 211; and Alfred Manigk, Die Idee des Naturrechts (Berlin und

Leipzig, 1926).


47. Isaac Husik, "The Legal Philosophy of Rudolf Stammler," Columbia Law

Review, XXIV (April, 1924), 373, 387, 388, and Stammler, Mich. Law Rev.,

XXI, 638. Says Stammler, "absolute validity is possessed by the system of

pure forms, by which alone the intellectual life in general can be

methodically ordered." Illustrations of the pure form of legal speculation

are "the notion of law" and "the idea of law." For an analysis of the

theories of Kohler and Stammler, consult William Ernest Hocking, Present

Status of the Philosophy of Law and of Rights (New Haven, 1926), p. 30.



                   CHAPTER X


    FRENCH THEORIES RELATING TO SUPERIOR LAW 
          HIGHER LAW DOCTRINES OF KRABBE


1. Views of Saleilles and Charmont. One of the French jurists who aided

materially in the development of the legal and philosophical bases for a

revival of natural law was R. Saleilles.[1] Saleilles refers to one of the

objects of the Historical School of jurists which was designed "to set aside

forever what was called the chimera of natural law founded on reason" or of

anything permanent and immutable in the nature of man which might become an

object of law. Not only was it their purpose to reject the classical

conception of natural law but also to discredit all references to general

principles or to juridical constructions which were thought to smack of

natural law or of metaphysical connotations. The tendency on all sides was

to turn in the direction of a "practical empiricism" which Saleilles

regarded as deceptive and disturbing to the conscience. Following some of

the tendencies of the thought of Savigny jurists were inclined to limit the

function of the judge and to deny that in his decisions he had any concern

with concepts of the rational, equitable, or just. Similarly they aimed to

limit the legislator to a considerable degree to the interpretation of

pre-existing customs only -- customs which might be discovered, noted, and

translated into legal formulae. Hence in the minds of such jurists natural

law had been discarded to its last consequences, to the three degrees of

juridical function: legislative, scientific, and judicial.


In the face of the dogmas of the Historical School and of the dominance of

the tendencies toward practical empiricism Saleilles sought to discover

evidences of the application of the old ideas of natural law appearing under

new or concealed forms. Noting the hurried and confused processes in the

ordinary making and applying of law in which the use of natural law ideas is

likely to be slight, he says: "Recent theorists no longer think of an ideal

or natural type of law applicable to all civilized peoples." But the general

lines of a new natural law are to be discovered in the realm where the

scholar, the legislator, and the judge evaluate first what the law is and

then indicate the rules which ought to apply, following the principles of

abstract reason. It is in this process that the judge, through his

independence and his large powers of interpretation, participates actively

in lawmaking.


    How can it be believed in fact if not in law [observes
    Saleilles] when the text is doubtful, that the judge will not
    allow himself to be guided, even if unconsciously, by his
    rationalising tendencies, even when legislation has not made
    it a prescribed duty as is the case for example in Art. 7 of
    the Austrian Civil Code? When all the arguments, as was
    said formerly, are exhausted, as well as deductive reasons,
    analogy, juridical construction, the Austrian Code makes it
    obligatory for the Judge to decide according to natural law;
    the latter thus acquires a subsidiary value. The modern judge
    will not wait, undoubtedly, until all the arsenal of logical
    processes has been exhausted to obey what was wont to be
    called the light of reason. It is really then that the question of
    natural law assumes a practical importance of the first
    order.[2]


In the judgment of M. Geny, the jurist is expected "to have the right to

orient himself and to direct his interpretation toward a future postulate

which is dictated to him by his conscience and by his reason." Saleilles,

following Geny's point of view (in speaking of a revival of natural law),

has in mind principles "deduced from abstract reason and from philosophical

intuition." It is not a question, he says,


    of the principles which are at the source of a legal rule itself
    but of simple processes of juridical technique, necessary to
    establish harmony in a legislative system, in order to
    coordinate the scattered parts and to allow the interested
    parties to guide themselves, in the applications which they
    make of the law, by reasonings which can give them a
    degree of certainty. It is a question of putting the provisions
    of the law or of a group of laws in harmony with the whole,
    and then to deduce, with this aim in view, certain directory
    rules implied by concrete solutions of the text. In this way
    the scattered findings are gathered under a certain number of
    abstract principles, which will be used as a point of
    departure for new developments and which the law can
    adopt in relation to questions not previously provided for.[3]


Bierling's analysis is then followed, which distinguishes between principles

of juridical technique which have no bases in absolute truth and principles

of a philosophical character which have objective validity and may be used

as a rational means to test legal rules. And attention is directed to the

emphasis on a revived natural law in the works of Geny, Duguit, L. von

Savigny, and Stammler. The failure of the Historical School to recognize the

creative force of reason and the guiding influence of principles is regarded

as in part responsible for a reaction from the tenets of the school which

has taken jurists in the direction of Stammler's "natural law with a

variable content." Stammler recognizes the existence and the legitimacy of

this natural law of a variable content, which does not pretend to be

absolute and immutable, but which nevertheless has its place in the

successive stages of historical evolution.[4]


Recognizing that there is a revived natural law and that it is the duty of

the judge to make use of such a law in guiding his interpretations[5]

Saleilles sees a danger in that a judge is likely to be influenced by his

individual conceptions and his decisions may become subjective and

arbitrary. Hence if natural law is to find its place as a factor for

rendering justice some objective grounds for its applications must be found.

The objective criteria are to be found, he thinks, in the development of

doctrines and principles which, when tested by the facts and conditions of

the time, are well enough recognized to be accepted as a consensus of

current opinion.


Great caution is to be taken in selecting these objective bases for

Saleilles thinks the judge in applying principles of jurisprudence should

exercise unusual care in introducing new ideas into his decisions "unless it

is a question of the application of one of the natural laws -- which are

supposed to be conceived instinctively by whoever expresses accurately the

collective conscience of a time."[6] And he observes:


    That which must be placed in the foreground, and the point
    on which I am in complete agreement with M. Geny, is that
    the judge must accept as the basis of his methods of
    interpretation the idea and the conviction that there is an
    individual justice existing objectively, which ought to be in
    accord with the social justice of which the law is for him the
    imperative expression; that, as a result, if he has the duty to
    guide the changing interpretation of a law, outside of his
    formal texts, he must take for a guide this absolute
    conviction of the idea of justice in its adaptation to the
    exigencies of the social order.


    But what concrete conceptions shall he form of this idea of
    justice and how between two possible solutions shall he
    objectively decide which one will correspond to this idea,
    applicable to the historic conditions of the time, I mean to
    the conception of justice which one should adopt in the
    historical milieu of a given time and under the social
    conditions which it presents. Will he find in his conscience
    solely from the innate idea of natural law of which all the
    partisans of ideal law speak, a definite and precise answer
    such as all the judges, supposedly equally impartial, equally
    devoid of any personal bias, would themselves give? It is
    only necessary to present the question in order to see that
    considering the conditions in the progress of humanity and
    the complexity of diverse clashing interests, the relationships
    of which are often necessarily reversed by the law of history,
    this objectivity is impossible even in an ideal sense. The
    answer would be given by the subjectivism of each whether
    political, economic, philosophical or religious. We find
    ourselves face to face with the worst dangers of what we
    have sometimes called, not without a certain irony, judicial
    equity.


    The judge has the right to make a concrete application of the
    ideas of absolute justice that an ideal of abstract natural right
    can suggest to him, only if these conceptions have already
    found an objectivity exterior to him and susceptible to a
    juridical command; only if, by some experimental method,
    analogous with the process of legal verification which is his
    first duty, the judge finds, outside of himself, some elements
    of a juridical command imperative, which he only needs to
    note and apply, in order to remain within his function, which
    is, in other words, to ascertain the law and to declare that it
    be respected.[7]


    ... But again in cases where the judge should find, at any rate
    in actuality, no support in the law, where he would be the
    first to recognize this new principle of ideal justice which has
    not yet become accepted as substantive law and to make a
    concrete application of it, thereby paving the way for the
    legislator, in such cases it is from the juridical conscience of
    the collective body that he will have to borrow its elements;
    and in this regard I could only repeat what I have elsewhere
    said -- consequently I content myself with merely a
    reference -- about the juridical value accorded to sound
    customs and the conception of them the judge must form
    wherever the law forces him to take them into account in
    order to pass upon the validity of private acts. It would
    appear that in such cases it is the law itself which yields
    before natural law, prompting the judge, as it does, to have
    recourse to the latter. It would indeed seem so, if one has in
    mind a natural law in process of evolution having objective
    bases in the popular conscience; the contrary would appear
    true if one saw in it an invariable moral formula; or, at the
    least, assuming it could vary, if it was used as an ideal, it
    would be the personal and purely subjective system of him
    whose duty it is to make its application, that is to say, of the
    judge himself.[8]


These objective criteria, Saleilles believes, can be formed only by means of

legislative analogy, the collective juridical conscience, and comparative

law, by which the interpretations of judges may be guided. In this process

the work of legal scholars in what the French call the development of

"juridical doctrines" has a large place and the judge's function would be a

restricted one, for


    when general opinion, under the form it takes and under
    which it adapts itself gradually to the economic and social
    changes of a period, becomes unanimous as to certain
    concepts of justice, and when this conception is such, I have
    said elsewhere, that those to whom it is presented are ready
    to recognize its worth, the judge has the right to make of
    himself the organ, not blind and purely passive, of this
    inorganic sentiment of the collective conscience, but the
    interpreter who becomes saturated with its inspiration in
    order to adapt it to the legal juridical order of which he is the
    guardian and the defender. He has not the authority to
    substitute at one stroke one ideal system for another; but his
    mission is to draw inspiration from it, when he is sure of his
    ground, in order to infuse it into his interpretation of the
    general characteristics of the law, and to make of the conflict
    of the systems, when these become opposed in the abstract,
    a workable system of justice, which in the domain of the
    concrete guarantees acquired rights, giving satisfaction at the
    same time to new rights which claim recognition.[9] 


The safest and scientifically the most satisfactory method of discovering

these objective bases for a revived natural law, Saleilles claims, is

through comparative law whereby the ideals of the jurists are put to the

test by legislators and judges. In the practical juridical applications may

be found their permanent and enduring qualities, at least, for the

particular time and place. It is in this connection that Saleilles gives a

warning, if too large powers are accorded to the judges in applying

principles of justice, that there is grave danger that personal and

political views, not having objective validity in the juridical conscience,

may be applied as if they were immanent truths. Thus comparative law because

it brings together different juristic concepts of natural law and reduces

them to concrete formulae of juridical application is hailed as a method of

establishing a common law of humanity. Though natural law will always serve

in an auxiliary and supplementary rôle in any national system of law it is,

however, regarded as the chief source of guidance for scientific judicial

evolution.


Charmont credits the school of natural law and of natural rights with the

laying of the foundation of modern constitutional law, with the

determination of the basic principles of private and public international

law, and with certain contributions to the amelioration of criminal

laws.[10]


According to Charmont, "natural law, as the old school conceived it was

universal, immutable; for all questions of positive law it offered the ideal

solution, satisfying in every respect; and the human reason could and should

find this solution."[11] Positive law, then, was conceived as contingent and

imperfect; natural law as the ideal, the absolute. The new view considers

natural law as variable and not incompatible with the law of evolution. It

has, in the words of Stammler, a "variable content." In conclusion, says

Charmont,


    the idea of natural law, then, is differently conceived from
    the way it formerly was. It rests upon another foundation,
    and at the same time it undergoes certain transformations. It
    reconciles itself with the idea of evolution, with the idea of
    utility. It loses its absolute and immutable character; it
    possesses only a variable content. It takes account of the
    interdependence of the individual and of the community. It
    thus tends to bring into accord the individual conscience and
    external law instead of setting them into opposition. In this
    transformation juridical idealism is not weakened; on the
    other hand it has been consolidated and enlarged.[12]


Though Charmont is an advocate of the modern theory of natural law, he

conceives the theory as a sort of an ideal standard for juristic

philosophers and legal thinkers and not as a formal rule of law to be

followed literally by the courts and the judges. In reviewing Geny's theory

of free legal decision, Charmont indicates the weakness in the former

attempts to apply the theory of natural law. "The idea of a right conceived

by reason," he says, leads "logically to the rule of formal law, to an

exaggeration of the element of legality. Law is formulated and sovereign

reason; it can and it should foresee and decide all things. The sole

function of the judge is to assure its application."[13] And, he continues,


    the traditional doctrine that the legislator settles everything in
    relation to a phase of legal relations and that the judge's sole
    business is to discover the legislative will has incontestable
    advantages. It strengthens the interpreter in making him the
    mouthpiece of the law; it satisfies the demands of our
    classical spirit and it seems to give great stability to our legal
    doctrines. But as against these advantages, it is necessary to
    note inconveniences.


    We are bound at the moment the law is made. The law,
    which is regarded sufficient to itself, is isolated from the
    other sciences and loses all contact with life. The respect of
    the interpreter for texts is only a vain appearance, for he
    himself in reality creates the principles which, in order to gain
    for them a semblance of authority, he ascribes to the
    lawgiver. These so-called principles which are only
    subjective conceptions are developed so as to become
    tyrannical, embarrassing science and forming an obstacle to
    progress.[14]


Charmont thus recognizes some of the difficulties and gives the basis for

the criticisms which have resulted in the application by American justices

of the so-called rule of reason as a standard to test the validity of

legislative acts. The decision of a judge, thinks Charmont, "who acts as a

law-maker will always appear individual, arbitrary, and partial; it will not

have the authority of law."[15]


A French authority, whose works are better known than those of Charmont,

also seeks to discover a new juridical idealism in which the ideal of the

epoch supplants the absolute ideal. Demogue conceives natural law as an

ideal concept rather than as a rule of positive law -- as a law to be sought

in the struggle to secure harmonious adjustments of social life. He aims to

find an ideal law in the presence of certain facts, historical, economic,

and political, which appear as a result of the investigations of social

science and from the aspirations of humanity.[16]


2. Views of Duguit and Hauriou. Though Léon Duguit was one of the foremost

critics of natural rights theories, he was one of the ablest advocates in

France of the principle that there is a law superior to the state.

Originally presented in his L'Etat, le droit objectif et la loi positive,

which appeared in 1901, Duguit's doctrines were amplified and developed

since this date. He repudiates the notion that rights may be based on the

"high dignity of the human being"[17] and rejects the implications of the

theories of Ihering, Laband, and Jellinek that law is comprised solely of

rules established by society with the coercion of the state behind them.


Duguit sets out to demonstrate that law can be anterior and exterior to the

state. Those who recognize a law beyond the realm of state action find the

origin of this law in a deity, or in the individual, or in society.

Rejecting a religious and metaphysical basis for a superior law, and

discarding the philosophy of individual rights, Duguit turns to the social

basis for a law exterior to the state. He finds the origin of those superior

rules of law in certain norms which condition man's living in society and

which form the basis of other norms sanctioned and enforced by the

state.[18]


"We believe firmly," says Duguit, "that there is a rule of law above the

individual and the state, above the rulers and the ruled; a rule which is

compulsory on one and on the other; and we hold that if there is such a

thing as sovereignty of the state, it is juridically limited by this rule of

law."[19] He denies, however, that there are subjective individual rights or

natural rights which furnish a basis for these superior laws. The postulate

of individual natural rights involves, he thinks, two contradictions -- the

sovereignty of the state and the autonomy of the individual. An individual

right superior to the state is considered as a pure hypothesis and not a

reality. It implies a social contract at the origin of society which is

deemed a manifest contradiction.[20] Rights, it is maintained, can arise

only from social conditions. They may be acquired only through membership in

a society.


To Duguit the basis of law is not subjective but objective and is based on

the facts of social solidarity.[21] Conformity to this solidarity is not a

rule of ethics but a rule of law. In accordance with these views Duguit

opposes the doctrine of unlimited powers of the state or the doctrine of

self-limitation of sovereign powers which is, he thinks, a form of

omnipotence in disguise. If there are limits on the powers of the state

there can be no sovereignty and if the doctrine of sovereignty prevails

there can be no limits to state action. The German doctrine of

auto-limitation[22] is regarded as a farce, since the unlimited sovereign

who agrees to limits may break his agreement at any time with impunity.[23]


Therefore, he becomes a defender of the theory of the separation of powers

which has prevailed in America and of the practice of American courts in

reviewing legislative enactments in order to annul acts which are regarded

as contrary to the provisions of written constitutions, or to implied

limitations interpreted as inhibiting arbitrary acts. Judicial review of

legislative enactments, Duguit believes, follows logically from the theory

of the separation of powers.


The philosophy of Duguit is of such interest and significance that brief

extracts from his recent work, Traité de droit constitutionnel, will present

more effectively his advocacy of a superior law (droit) to which all valid

positive laws must conform.[24] Presenting the dominant idea of the entire

treatise Duguit says:


    The older I become, the more I study and search into the
    problem of the law [droit], the more I am convinced that
    law is not a creation of the state, that it exists independent of
    the state, that the notion of law is altogether independent of
    the notion of the state and that the rule of law [la règle de
    droit] governs the state as it governs individuals. It will be
    seen later that this work is dominated by this idea that the
    state is limited in its action by the rule of law, that this ought
    to be the case, that it cannot be otherwise, and that the
    social order would be impossible if it were not so. Now, this
    would be impossible if law were an exclusive creation of the
    state or the rule of law existed only when an economic or
    social rule is formulated or accepted by the state.[25]


The characteristic ideas in relation to this higher law are more explicitly

developed in sections dealing with laws regarded as contrary to right.[26]


    I call contrary to right every formal law which contains a
    command contrary, either to a principle of superior right,
    such as is recognized by the collective conscience of the
    people ... or to a provision written in the declaration of
    rights, or whether finally to a provision of a rigid
    constitutional law, in the countries, such as France and the
    United States, which have adopted such a hierarchy of laws.
    To facilitate the exposition I would qualify simply as an
    unconstitutional law every law contrary to a superior
    principle of right, written or not in a law superior to the
    ordinary law, declaration of rights, or rigid constitutional law.
    In a word, I use the expression "unconstitutional law," as a
    synonym of a law contrary to a superior law [droit] written
    or unwritten.


    From what I have said ... it follows that the legislator as a
    matter of fact does not have the power to create law, that he
    can only establish and announce constructive rules in order
    to put them into effect. The logical consequence of this is
    that a law which is contrary to objective right or which does
    not have for its end to put into effect a rule of law [droit]
    and to assure its execution is a law without value, a law
    without executive force.


    But one discerns with difficulty the practical means to
    repress a violation of a law by the legislature. Since the
    legislature is charged with the duty to formulate the law and
    to assure its sanction, one can scarcely understand how
    there can be organized against it a system designed to
    repress the violations of law committed by it. As will be seen
    a little farther on, the devices which have been established in
    France toward this end have proven ineffective. On the
    other hand, although it is not impossible to accomplish this
    end in any country, the establishment of a similar
    organization has been considered only in the countries which
    recognize the distinction of two or more categories of law in
    hierarchical form as the United States or as France, where
    we have three categories of law: the declarations of rights
    which formulate the superior principles of right or law which
    cannot be transgressed either by the ordinary legislature or
    by the constituent legislative body and the constitutional laws
    which the ordinary legislature can neither modify nor
    abrogate. In a country such as England, which does not
    recognize the distinction between constitutional laws and
    ordinary laws, one never has occasion to think of an organ
    authorized to test the conformity of laws with right. Besides
    in England public opinion is the best guarantee against
    arbitrary legislative acts.


    Whether there is or is not in a country an organ authorized
    to determine the conformity of laws with objective right and
    to declare of no effect the laws contrary to such right one
    need not hesitate to accept all of the consequences of the
    preceding proposition and to say that to refuse obedience to
    a law contrary to right is perfectly legitimate. It is the
    principle of resistance to oppression affirmed distinctly by
    the declaration of rights of 1789 (Art. 2) as one of the
    natural, inalienable, and imprescriptible rights of man and by
    the declaration of rights of 1793 in the well-known Articles
    33 to 35. When one advocates this proposition he is in
    general classed as an anarchist, because it is claimed no
    society would be possible if all of the citizens could refuse to
    obey laws under the pretext that they are contrary to right. I
    reply that there are laws to which no one would think of
    refusing obedience because they formulate or carry into
    effect a rule of right which is contested by no one. And the
    affirmation of the right of resistance to oppression is the best
    guarantee against the arbitrary power of the legislature which
    would endeavor hereafter, to make only those laws which
    would be given an almost unanimous acceptance.[27]


That there is a higher law to which all governmental acts must conform

whether a constitution be rigid or flexible is Duguit's main thesis. Even in

England, he finds, where the omnipotence of Parliament is considered as an

essential principle there are superior rules which the conscience of the

English people themselves would not permit to be violated by Parliament. The

existence of rigid constitutional laws superior to ordinary laws then is

regarded, not as the foundation of limits to the legislative powers, but

only a positive guarantee, of the restrictive rules which necessarily bind

the legislature of the state.


Duguit regards it necessary to go a little further and to say that


    every state which recognizes the principle of its
    subordination to law, which recognizes that there are laws
    which cannot be enacted in order to respect this principle
    completely, ought to create a high court having every
    possible guarantee of independence and of ability and being
    authorized to annul laws contrary to right, or following a
    formula less general and less exact, which would be
    competent to pass on the constitutionality of laws and to
    annul unconstitutional laws.[28]


Such high and extraordinary powers, Duguit thinks, ought not to be entrusted

to an organ established and controlled on a political basis and because of

the political influences dominating French courts he doubts whether they

should be accorded such powers.


After describing certain devices in French constitutions to establish

special courts to deal with acts regarded as contrary to the constitution

and some recent unsuccessful attempts to revive the plan of a constitutional

court Duguit defends the American doctrine as to the review of legislative

enactments:


    If there is no reason to establish a supreme court before
    which recourse could be taken tending to have a law held
    void on the ground of unconstitutionality ought we not to
    grant courts the authority to consider the constitutionality of
    a law attacked before them and to refuse to apply it if they
    judge it unconstitutional? In considering the question
    theoretically, taking into consideration the nature of positive
    legislation and the difficulties which arise in practice one
    must reply affirmatively. The courts ought above all to apply
    the law -- that is to say, to decide in conformity with the
    law all questions of right which are presented to them. They
    are bound by the law evidently, by all laws in force in a
    given country, by the ordinary laws without doubt, but also
    and for greater reason by the superior laws written or
    unwritten, particularly by the rules inscribed in the
    declaration of rights and in the constitutional laws. In a
    country where there exists such a hierarchy of laws it is
    incontestably logical that in a case of a contradiction
    between an inferior and a superior law it is the latter which
    the courts ought to apply, as a result of which on the same
    ground they refuse to apply the inferior law. If there is a
    contradiction between an ordinary law on the one part and a
    constitutional law or the declaration of rights on the other,
    the court ought not to apply the ordinary law. Moreover, if
    there is a contradiction between a constitutional law and a
    provision of the declaration of rights the court ought to apply
    the latter and to refuse to apply the former.


    Theoretically, then, every person ought to be permitted to
    contest before any court a law as unconstitutional, that is to
    say, to be permitted to claim that the law invoked against
    him cannot be applied by the court because it is contrary to
    a superior law [droit] written or unwritten, to which the
    ordinary legislature is subordinated.[29]


This doctrine follows, in Duguit's judgment, as a matter of course from a

written constitution with a theory of a separation of powers. Referring to

the provisions which have been interpreted as preventing the French courts

from passing on the validity of legislative acts, Duguit believes the

doctrine and jurisprudence of the French courts on this matter are clearly

wrong. These texts, in his opinion, were only an application of the

principle of the separation of powers and this implies that the judges can

consider the constitutionality of laws and refuse to apply all

unconstitutional laws. Referring to doubts expressed in the first edition of

his treatise that courts might consider the validity of legislative acts,

Duguit says:


    I was in error and today I accept without hesitation the
    solution which has been accepted and followed by the
    eminent jurists which I have indicated. It appears to me
    evident that it is a necessary and logical consequence of the
    hierarchy of laws. I consider, moreover, that among the
    texts of French positive law there is none which is opposed
    to the recognition of this power as belonging to French
    courts. On the contrary, as I have said above, the texts
    which establish the principle of the separation of powers
    give them this authority implicitly. I may add that a country in
    which one does not recognize this authority as belonging to
    the courts cannot directly be said to be under the regime of
    law. This system has always been practiced in the United
    States. Certain inconveniences without doubt have been
    presented in its application, and the Americans are the first
    to recognize them. These inconveniences, however, prove
    rather that the difficulty lies in the manner of the practical
    application of the principle by the American courts and their
    method of appointment rather than in the system itself. After
    all, the advantages are much superior to the inconveniences
    and this is sufficient to require its application in our
    country.[30]


After summarizing some of the difficulties and inconveniences in the

application of the American system of the judicial review of legislative

acts discovered by Professor Lambert,[31] Duguit concludes:


    Whatever may be thought of political tendencies which may
    have appeared in the jurisprudence of the American
    Supreme Court, there is in the power which American
    courts have to consider the constitutionality of laws an
    institution highly protective of individual liberty against
    arbitrary legislation. I have been able to assure myself that
    some of the ablest and most independent Americans retain a
    profound attachment for this institution and that the prestige
    of the Supreme Court is not growing less in the public spirit.
    There are some who speak of government by judges. The
    expression is applied by certain American authors and it is
    the title which Lambert gives to his work. It is not exact.
    One cannot say that in America the courts of justice, even
    the Supreme Court, are truly associated with the
    government. One cannot even say that they exercise in a
    true sense control over Congress, or that they can exercise a
    sort of veto of laws passed by this chamber. These take all
    their force from the vote of Congress and the promulgation
    by the President, which alone can exercise a suspensive
    veto. The Supreme Court following the expression of
    Larnaude does not pass upon, to speak accurately, the
    process of the making of a law. It gives a decision to a
    particular litigant, but this decision requires that the court
    decide on the constitutionality of the law. Evidently, the
    constitutionality is considered in this large sense; and the
    Supreme Court ought not to be blamed, on the contrary, for
    refusing to apply not only the laws which violate a written
    rule of the constitution but also a fundamental principle of
    American law. It recognizes and sanctions a superior law
    [droit] of which I have often affirmed the existence, which
    imposes itself on every legislator and of which, to their
    honor, American jurists are unanimous in recognizing the
    existence and force.[32]


The doctrine that the positive rules and enactments of the state cannot

interfere with the rights which are pre-existent to all social organization

-- certain absolute rights which are superior to the law itself, because

they are inseparable from human personality -- is supported by different

groups of French thinkers.[33] Many agree with Duguit that whenever a law

violates a rule of right it should be regarded as an act of oppression and

be resisted as such. Law is, then, conceived not as a creation of the

legislature; it exists in and of itself.


The rule of right gives to positive law its imperative force.[34] Whenever a

law conforms to a rule of right it is valid and should be carried into

effect; whenever it is opposed to such a rule its enforcement should be

resisted, and particularly so when it infringes in a serious way upon the

rights of the individual. To establish and preserve such rights it is

necessary to maintain the doctrine of limits upon sovereign powers. A number

of writers on public law in France believe that the only effective guarantee

for individual rights can be established through the judicial control over

legislative and administrative acts which do not conform to the higher law

or rule of right.[35] Certain principles formulated in the Declaration of

Rights of 1789 are, therefore, considered as immutable and pre-existent to

all social organization, and any enactments contrary thereto are necessarily

unconstitutional.[36] To protect individual rights and to give validity to

the written provisions of the constitution it is regarded as necessary to

have an unconstitutional law declared inapplicable. In the judgment of M.

Wohlgemuth,


    this remedy can best be accorded by the courts and this
    form of judicial control ought logically to follow from the
    nature of the laws relating to individual rights.... In refusing to
    apply such a law, the judge does not exercise political
    power, but confines himself to the interpretation of the law,
    just as he does each day, in the application of ordinary laws
    ... individual rights are each day menaced by laws contrary
    to the rule of right and contrary to the principle of social
    solidarity. These laws do not have the force of law, if they
    have not in themselves certain imperative qualities. It is
    logical as we have insisted for the judge to refuse to apply
    them. This is one of the established features of democratic
    government.[37] 


"We believe, with L. Duguit, that there exists a rule of law [droit]

anterior and superior to the state, -- a rule of law founded on solidarity

and on justice. It is from this rule of law that are derived objective law

and subjective rights."[38] According to Guillemon this is not an

ideological principle but an enforceable limit on the exercise of state

powers. "From this idea that the state is bound and limited by law follows

naturally this other idea, that in the case of a violation of law [droit],

by the state, the subjects have the duty not to obey the illegal acts and

even to rebel against the state."[39] The criminal code is silent as to the

effect of the resistance by an individual to an illegal act of an

officer.[40] Guillemon believes that impliedly the article requires passive

obedience. Referring to the comments of Esmein that the principles of the

French Declarations of Rights have no constitutional significance today in

France,[41] Guillemon claims that they have a "super-constitutional"

significance. There are in France, he asserts, three categories of laws:


    (a) Super-constitutional laws.


    (b) Constitutional laws.


    (c) Ordinary laws.


The super-constitutional laws pertain chiefly to the principles of the

Declaration of Rights, which are beyond change by the ordinary processes of

legislation or constitutional amendment.[42]


When such individual rights are violated Guillemon thinks the courts ought

to grant a remedy by checking the illegal act.[43]


Duguit's repudiation of the concepts of natural law, of the personality of

the state, and of national sovereignty is criticised by many French jurists

as running counter to the almost universally accepted basis of French legal

thought.[44] Accepting the individualistic basis for natural law Professor

Gavet notes how the conceptions of this school have been misinterpreted and

then condemned. He finds the development of natural law in the progressive

evolution of sentiments of law and justice among men. "We remain," he says,

"believers in the natural and imprescriptible rights of man and, therefore,

in the law of nations."[45]


A member of the Positivist School of jurisprudence summarizes as follows the

propositions implied in Duguit's writings:


    1. That the state is no longer sovereign.


    2. That the doctrine of the unity of the state is inconsistent
    with modern associational tendencies.


    3. That in legal no less than in political theory law is justified
    by reference to the end which it serves.


    4. That there is a droit objectif superior to all governments
    and legally binding them.


    5. That the rulers are under a legal duty to govern well, but
    have no legal right to govern.


Justice Brown criticizes these propositions in turn and claims Duguit's

droit objectif is merely the concept of natural law socialized, and that the

basis of his legal thought involves "a hopeless confusion of legal and moral

ideas." Though most Positivists in France and elsewhere unhesitatingly

reject the main tenets of Duguit's legal philosophy, his writings have had a

profound effect on all current legal thought.[46]


Geny thinks that Duguit in effect turned again to the essential idea of

natural law only under a new form,[47] and that seemingly repudiating the

metaphysical approach to the law he constructed a system essentially founded

on vague metaphysical hypotheses. Referring to Duguit's principle of social

solidarity Saleilles calls it a "principle of natural law after all"

according to the accepted terminology of this phrase.[48]


However one may classify the règle de droit it is one of the most

interesting and important forms of higher law philosophy which are affecting

European political and legal thinking.


M. Hauriou is among those in France who defends the doctrine of a higher law

above ordinary written enactments and constitutions. He speaks in defence of

this doctrine under the title superlégalité constitutionnelle. "It is an

error," he thinks,


    to believe that the superlégalité constitutionnelle
    comprehends only that which is written in the constitution; it
    comprehends equally other things, as for example, all of the
    fundamental principles of organization, that is, all the
    principles of the individualistic order which are at the basis
    of the state and the political principles on which governments
    are founded ... these principles constitute a sort of légitimité
    constitutionnelle, and which have force over and above
    even the written constitution.


Despite the failure of the constitution of 1875 to include a bill of rights,

Hauriou says:


    the principles of our public liberties are not in the written
    constitution; this is certain, but they are, however, in the
    superlégalité constitutionnelle, for they are part of the
    légitimité constitutionnelle, which is above the written
    constitution itself.... This is very important, for it signifies that
    no one's liberty can be completely suppressed either directly
    or indirectly by the establishment of the state monopoly.[49]
    Other principles can also be ranged in the category of
    légitimité constitutionnelle; the principles of equality and
    of publicity in taxation, and the principle of the separation of
    powers between the administrative and judicial
    authorities.[50]


It is quite necessary, Hauriou concludes, to substitute for the narrow

conception of the written constitutional law that of a superlégalité, which

allows an addition to the constitutional text of all the fundamental

principles of the state understood as forming a légitimité. Hauriou

practically agrees with Duguit in supporting the doctrine of a law superior

to the state and also the principle that the courts should review

legislative acts to test their conformity with the terms of written

constitutions. In a limited manner Hauriou and Duguit take the judiciary out

of its normal and classical position and set it up as the power of ultimate

sovereignty.[51] With certain reservations they approve the American

doctrine of judicial supremacy.


3. Higher Law Doctrines of Krabbe. H. Krabbe, the Dutch juristic

philosopher, discarding an omni-competent sovereign which is the basis and

source of law, defends the proposition that positive law is valid only by

virtue of the fact that it incorporates the principles of right (Recht).[52]

The principles of right are then traced to what Krabbe regards as the

feeling or sentiment of the people. In contrast with a sovereign who alone

can make law he formulates a theory of the sovereignty of law.[53]


    There is [according to Krabbe] only one source of law, --
    the feeling or sense of right which resides in man and has a
    place in his conscious life, like all the other tendencies that
    give rise to judgments of value. Upon this all law is based,
    whether it be positive law, customary law, or the unwritten
    law in general. A statute which does not rest upon this
    foundation is not law. It lacks validity even though it be
    obeyed voluntarily or by compulsion. It must be recognized,
    therefore, that there may be provisions of positive law which
    lack real legal quality.


    The legislative organ runs the risk of enacting rules which
    lack the quality of law either because the organization of the
    legislature is defective or because it mistakes what the
    people's sense of right demands. On the other hand, it may
    happen even more easily that what is embodied in a statute
    ceases to be law and so is no longer valid because it has lost
    the basis of its binding force. In such a case compulsion, --
    the punishment or legal judgment which disobedience to the
    statute entails, -- is irrelevant. Constraint is justified by the
    necessity of maintaining the law but it can never bestow legal
    quality upon a rule which lacks it. Mere force, whether
    organized as in the state or unorganized as in an insurrection
    or revolution, can never give to a rule that ethical element
    which belongs essentially to a rule of law. On the contrary,
    constraint can gain an ethical quality only when used in the
    service of law. Thus the rule must have the definite character
    of law and can derive this only from the feeling or sense of
    right which is rooted by nature in the human mind.[54]


There is, in the opinion of Krabbe, only one ruling power -- the power of

law. Along with other modern juristic writers he predicates an ethical and

moral basis for law. We are convinced, he says, "that in basing the validity

of law upon the sense of right we stand upon the firm foundation of fact, --

only by establishing the authority of law in this manner, moreover, can full

account be taken of the ethical character of law."[55]


Finding that there is no place for a sovereign in modern society and that

law may not be traced to any such source, Krabbe seeks a basis of law which

is regarded as better fitted to the views of modern social life.


His theory involves an insistence on the ethical foundations and emotional

sanctions for law, on the theory that the real source of law is in the

"sense for right" or "feeling for right." The spiritual sense of man is

regarded as the support of law and legal thinking. The intellect, it is

claimed, must lose its primacy in the development of law; feminine

emotionalism must offset masculine intellectualism.[56] The so-called sense

of right, it is contended, has binding force, and rules not based on it are

not law. The inherent obligatory authority arising therefrom is due to its

emanation from an absolute, or from what is conceived as universally valid

standards of right and of law. These valid standards are built on a uniform

standard of right which exists in each individual, though the idea or the

expression of the sense of right may be obscured by unfavorable

circumstances.[57]


In order to secure unity from a diversity of opinions as to the "sense of

right" superior sanction and validity is attached to the opinion of the

majority. That "rule is to be obeyed which has quantitatively the highest

value." In order to render feasible the rule of the majority it is contended

that the majority sense of right must be conceded to be better for the

minority than their own interpretation. There is an emphatic denial of

supremacy or of superior power through organization. This is indicated in

the dictum "no power on earth can control the action of the sense of right."

There is then no authority other than the law. Law is defined as the

judgment of the community on the rightness or wrongness of conduct.


In comparing the theories of Duguit and Krabbe it is apparent that both

reject eighteenth-century natural rights theories and the absolute

sovereignty theory, as bases of law and of legal principles. Both claim that

the legal foundation which is described is developed from facts and a

logical interpretation of social phenomena. Each in turn condemns the

Positivist's theory of the state with its accompanying legal dialectics.

Both believe in the superiority or "sovereignty" of rules of right (droit or

Recht).


Krabbe does not clearly dispose of implications which result from the

enactment of positive laws which lack true legal validity, such as the

attitude of the individual toward a positive legal rule which does not

conform to the sense of right or the duty of officers toward a statute

contrary to popular conceptions of right. Apparently the author regards

the feeling or sense of right as an ideal or standard toward which actual

laws may only approximate. Though he does not advocate explicitly a

doctrine of natural law he finds the source and sanction of all positive laws

in a higher law doctrine which has certain similarities with the theories of

natural law and of inalienable rights. This theory, however, differs in the

source and foundation of these rights, tracing them directly to the people,

rather than to any immutable and absolute standards to which man's legal

concepts must conform.


Discarding the concept of sovereignty for the state in the field of private

law and basing all law on the sense or feeling for right Krabbe predicates a

similar foundation for international law.[58] The difference between

national and international law results chiefly from the fact that the latter

is applicable to a larger domain and that in the international realm the

sense of right is immature.[59]




1. "École historique et droit naturel d'après quelques ouvrages récents,"

Revue trimestrielle de droit civil (1902), pp. 80-112. For Saleilles' views

regarding the lights of the individual and of social groups, consult De la

personnalité juridique (Paris, 1910), and Georges Davy, Le droit,

l'idéalisme et l'expérience (Paris, 1922), pp. 5 ff.


2. "École historique et droit naturel," par M. le Professeur Saleilles,

Revue trimestrielle de droit civil (1902), No. I, éditée par la Société du

Recueil Sirey, Paris, pp. 84, 85. I am indebted to the Société du Recueil

Sirey for permission to use translations of parts of this article.


3. Saleilles, op. cit., p. 87.


4. Saleilles notes that Geny wishes the judge to go directly, without

indirectness, fictions, or equivocations to the only realities which exist

outside of the text, to the inspirations of the idea of justice, which at

once takes him into the realm of natural law.


5. There is, says Saleilles, "a juridical and social order in which the

solution, entirely opposed to the one given formerly as the immanent

expression of justice, is going to appear as incarnating in its turn the

natural law of the times." Op. cit., p. 98.


6. Saleilles, op. cit., pp. 101 ff.


7. Saleilles, op. cit., pp. 105, 106.


8. Ibid., p. 108.


9. Saleilles, op. cit., pp. 108, 109.


10. J. Charmont, La renaissance du droit naturel (Montpellier, 1910), p.

167, and Modern French Legal Philosophy, pp. 106 ff. The natural law school,

Charmont claims, was founded by Hugo Grotius, 1583-1645; Pufendorf, 1632-94;

and Burlamaqui, 1694-1748. Cf. Charmont op. cit., pp. 10 ff., for a brief

summary of the theories of the different schools of natural law or natural

rights.


11. Op. cit., pp. 6, 54.


12. Op. cit., pp. 217, 218.


13. Ibid., p. 174, and Modern French Legal Philosophy, p. 112.


14. Op. cit., pp. 175, 176; Modern French Legal Philosophy, pp. 113, 114.


15. Saleilles, op. cit., p. 189; Modern French Legal Philosophy, p. 123.


16. Les notions fondamentales du droit privé, trans. in part in Modern

French Legal Philosophy (Boston, 1916); see p. 345, and especially pp. 370

ff.


17. "The affirmation that man because he is man, taken isolated and by

himself, separated from other men, in the state of nature, as they said in

the eighteenth century, is endowed with certain rights, peculiar to his

nature as man -- this affirmation is purely gratuitous; it cannot be

supported by any direct proof. It is a purely metaphysical proposition with

respect to the nature, or, as the schoolmen used to say, the essence, of the

human being. This affirmation might suffice in a period of metaphysical

belief, but it is purely a verbal expression -- nothing more -- in a

positivist and scientific epoch like ours. It can satisfy a believer, but it

is void of all scientific and positive value." Duguit, "The Law and The

State," Harvard Law Review, XXXI (November, 1917), 23.


18. See Traité de droit constitutionnel (2d ed.), I, 11 ff. The chief works

of Duguit, all of which have a common purpose, are: L'État, le droit

objectif et la loi positive (Paris, 1901); L'État, les gouvernants et les

agents (Paris, 1903); Manuel de droit constitutionnel: Théorie générale de

l'état-organisation politique (Paris, 1907; 4th ed. 1923); Le droit social,

le droit individuel et les transformations de l'état (Paris, 1908; 3d ed.

1924); Traité de droit constitutionnel (2 vols., Paris, 1911, 2d ed., 5

vols., 1921-25); Les transformations générales de droit privé depuis le Code

Napoléon (Paris, 1912); Les transformations de droit public (Paris, 1913);

Souveraineté et liberté (Paris, 1922).


For a summary of Duguit's doctrines, see Roger Bonnard, "La doctrine de

Duguit sur le droit et l'état," Revue Internationale de la théorie du droit,

1 (1926-27), 18 ff.


19. Duguit, L'État, le droit objectif et la loi positive, p. 12, and Modern

French Legal Philosophy, pp. 246-248; also "The Law and The State," Harv.

Law Rev., XXXI (November, 1917), 23.


20. Cf., for Duguit's views in opposition to subjective natural rights,

L'État, le droit objectif et la loi positive; Traité de droit

constitutionnel, 1, 9-13; Le droit social, le droit individuel et les

transformations de l'état (2d ed.), pp. 3-5, 10-17; Transformations

générales du droit privé, pp. 9-15; Revue du droit public, XXIV (1907), 419.


21. Traité de droit constitutionnel, I, 22 ff. For the contention that

except for some surface differences Duguit is stating old doctrines akin to

the Natural Rights School, see Charmont, La renaissance du droit naturel, p.

98, and Modern French Legal Philosophy, p. 131. On the other hand, Duguit

insists that a profound difference separates his conception of a rule of

society which he calls a rule of right from the former conception of natural

rights. See Le droit social, le droit individuel et la transformation de

l'état (Paris, 1911), pp. 6-9.


22. See Ihering's Der Zweck im Recht and trans. in Modern Legal Philosophy,

vol. V; Jellinek's System der subjektiven offentlichen Rechte and Allgemeine

Staatslehre (1900). Cf. Duguit, "La doctrine allemande de l'auto-limitation

de l'état," Revue du droit public, XXVI (1919), 161.


23. "The Law and the State," Harv. Law Rev., XXI (November, 1917), pp. 123

ff. For Duguit's criticisms of the dogma of sovereignty, see Traité de droit

constitutionnel, I, 408 ff.


24. These extracts have been translated and reprinted with the permission of

Professor Duguit and of M. de Boccard, editor of his works.


25. Duguit, Traité de droit constitutionnel (2d ed.), I, 33.


26. Ibid, III, 659 ff. Duguit claims if there is no rule of law (règle de

droit) above the powers of the state there is no public law and Treitschke's

characterization "Der Staat ist Macht" is an unescapable truth. "The Law and

the State," Harv. Law Rev., XXXI (November, 1917), 6.


27. Traité de droit constitutionnel, III, 661.


28. Ibid., p. 664.


29. Traité de droit constitutionnel, III pp. 667, 668.


30. Ibid., pp. 673, 674. Cf. Beauregard, Monde économique (November

seventeenth, 1894), p. 505; Jèze, "Du contrôle des délibérations des

assemblées délibérantes," Revue générale d'administration (1895), p. 411;

Signorel, "Du contrôle judiciaire des actes du pouvoir législatif," Revue

politique et parlementaire (June, 1904), p. 526.


31. Edouard Lambert, Le gouvernement des juges et la lutte contre la

législation sociale aux États-Unis (Paris, 1921).


32. Traité de droit constitutionnel, III, pp. 678, 679. "The American

solution creates in a singular manner a positive sanction for enforcement of

the obligation resting upon the legislature, namely, to respect the superior

principles of right [le droit supérieur] imposed upon it." Duguit, "The Law

and the State," Harv. Law Rev., XXXI (November, 1917), 18.


33. Edouard Lambert, op. cit., Introduction and chap. 11; Wohlgemuth, Des

droits individuels et de leur garantie judiciaire specialement contre le

pouvoir législatif.


34. Wohlgemuth, op. cit., pp. 22-23. To M. Wohlgemuth, "every act which does

not carry into effect a rule of right and which creates a pretended rule of

positive law, is theoretically an arbitrary act, without force, and no one

is bound by it." Ibid., p. 20. Cf. also H. Berthélemy, "Le fondement de

l'authorité politique," Revue du droit public, XXXII (1915), 663, 664.


35. Ibid., pp. 95 ff.; Hauriou, "Conseil d'état (August 7, 1909)," Sirey

(1909), III, 145; Jèze, in Revue générale d'administration, II (1895), 241,

and Revue du droit public, XXIX (1912), 140; Albert Angleys, Des garanties

contre l'arbitraire du pouvoir législatif, par l'intervention du pouvoir

judiciaire (Chambery, 1910); Henri Desfougères, Le contrôle judiciaire de la

constitutionnalité des lois (Paris, 1910).


36. Ibid., p. 144, and Jules Coumoul, Traité du pouvoir judiciaire de son

role constitutionnel et de sa réforme organique (Paris, 1911), pp. 214, 215.


37. Wohlgemuth, op. cit., pp. 149, 150, 156; see also Angleys, op. cit., Pt.

IV, and Desfougeres, op. cit., pp. 115 ff.


38. Pierre Guillemon, De la rébellion et de la résistance aux actes illégaux

(Thesis, Bordeaux, 1921), pp. 6, 71 ff.


39. Guillemon, op. cit., p. 8.


40. Cf. art. 209.


41. Esmein, Droit constitutionnel (5th ed), p. 492.


42. Guillemon, op. cit., pp. 10, 11. Cf. art. 11 of Declaration of Rights of

1793 to which a super-constitutional value is attributed.


43. See Guillemon, op. cit., p. 12, and the following: Duguit, Manuel de

droit constitutionnel, pp. 304-307; Reglade, La coutume en droit public

interne, p. 263; and G. Jèze in Revue générale d'administration, II (1895),

411. Cf. also extract from Duguit, Traité de droit constitutionnel, II, 13,

14, in which he speaks of the Declaration of Rights as

"super-constitutional" law.


Harold J. Laski notes that M. Berthélemy, a French authority on

administrative law, adopts Duguit's methods and conclusions, whereas M.

Hauriou, another French publicist, seems to reach not very different

results. "A whole school of the more brilliant younger jurists, M. Maxime

Leroy, M. Georges Cahen, M. Paul-Boncour," he observes, "are clearly

influenced at every stage of their work by M. Duguit's speculations. In

England and America its influence is already being felt." "A Note on M.

Duguit," Harv. Law Rev., XXXI (November, 1917), 188. Cf. M. Hauriou, "Les

idées de M. Duguit," Recueil de législation de Toulouse (1911), pp. 6 ff.,

and H. Berthélemy, "Le fondement de l'autorité politique," Revue du droit

public, XXXII (1915), 663.


44. Gaston Gavet, "Individualism and Realism," Yale Law Journal, XXIX (March

and April, 1920), 523, 643. Esmein calls Duguit's doctrine "chimère

anarchiste," Éléments de droit constitutionnel (4th ed.), p. 40. To Hauriou,

Duguit is an "anarchiste de la chaire," Revue du droit public, XVII (1902),

348, 353, and Michaud regards his theory as "anarchistic and incompatible

with social necessities," Théorie de la personnalité morale, I, 52. Malberg

relegates Duguit's rule of law to the realm of ideal justice or of morality

and denies that it has a juridical basis. Théorie de l'état, I, 212.


45. Gavet, op. cit., pp. 529, 530.


46. W. Jethro Brown, "The Jurisprudence of M. Duguit," Law Quarterly Review,

XXXII (April, 1916), 168, 172, 179-181.


47. Science et technique en droit privé positif, II, 191, 252, 262-264, and

IV, 159 ff.; for similar conclusions, see M. Deslandres, Revue du droit

public, XXV (1908), 10; J. Charmont, La renaissance du droit naturel (Paris,

1910), pp. 198, 199; and W. Y. Elliott, "The Metaphysics of Duguit's

Pragmatic Conception of Law," Political Science Quarterly, XXXVII (December,

1922), 637.


48. Gaston Jèze objects to Duguit's deductions because, as he sees it, he

fails to distinguish between "le droit positif" and "le droit naturel." Les

principes généraux du droit administratif (3d ed., Paris, 1925), p. 33.

Duguit replies to his critics in the Traité de droit constitutionnel, I, 17,

35, 59, 397, 497, and II, 68.


49. Droit constitutionnel (Paris, 1923), p. 298; also by same author, Précis

élémentaire de droit constitutionnel (Paris, 1925), pp. 81 ff.


50. In the United States, Hauriou believes, that where the control of the

constitutionality of laws is confided to the judges, they have progressively

developed "the absolute legitimacy of the individualistic principles of the

ancient Anglo-Saxon common law." Précis élémentaire de droit

constitutionnel, p. 82.


51. Principes de droit public (2d ed., Paris, 1916), pp. 31 ff., and Précis

de droit administratif et de droit public (9th ed., Paris, 1919), p. 996.


52. Die Lehre der Rechtes-souveränität (1906), and Die moderne Staatsidee

(1919); the latter has been translated in The Modern Idea of the State, with

an Introduction by George H. Sabine and Walter J. Shepard (New York, 1922).


53. The Modern Idea of the State, pp. 8, 9, 39 ff. Cf. also W. W.

Willoughby, "The Juristic Theories of Krabbe," American Political Science

Review, XX (August, 1926), 509. We find in Krabbe as in Duguit, says

Willoughby, the same mistaken idea, "that an inquiry into the idealistic or

utilitarian validity of law, as determined by its substantive provisions and

the purposes sought to be achieved by its enforcement, has a relevancy to,

and that its conclusions can affect, the validity and usefulness of the

purely formalistic concepts which the positive or analytical jurist

employs."


54. Krabbe, The Modern Idea of the State, pp. 47, 48. Krabbe insists that

"the whole legal system under which people live finds the basis of its

authority, its binding force, and its effectiveness in the operation of the

feeling or sense of right." Ibid., p. 126.


55. Ibid., p. 49.


56. Krabbe, The Modern Idea of the State, p. 197.


57. Ibid., p. 88.


58. Cf. Krabbe, The Modern Idea of the State, chap. 10.


59. Ibid, p. 247; cf. also Edwin M. Borchard, "Political Theory and

International Law" in C. E. Merriam and H. E. Barnes, A History of Political

Theories, Recent Times (New York, 1924), pp. 130, 131.


For a criticism of the views of Krabbe by a modern exponent of the

Positivist or Analytical School, see Willoughby, op. cit., pp. 520 ff.



                  CHAPTER XI


   REVIVAL OF NATURAL LAW IN METAPHYSICAL AND
            THEOLOGICAL SPECULATIONS; 
  NATURAL LAW THEORIES AND INTERNATIONAL LAW


THE modern revival of natural law theories is the result of a variety of

tendencies in legal, political, and moral thinking. Jurists of the most

diverse points of view, inclinations, and interests join in the advocacy of

higher law theories. One of the foremost movements in modern thought which

is bringing natural law out of its seeming state of disrepute is connected

with renewed efforts to seek the sources and sanctions for legal rules in

religious and metaphysical speculations. Taking as a standard the mediaeval

concepts of natural law, when jurisprudence was a branch of theology, and

following the metaphysical analyses of Thomas Aquinas in. relation to law,

modern juristic writers, mainly adherents of the Catholic faith, aim to

restore natural law again to its position of primacy in the political and

legal world. In fact, certain phases of the Thomist system, namely, that

natural law was "nothing else than the rational creature's participation in

the eternal law" and that it comprised rules of conduct essentially

prescribed by the Creator, have never ceased to be one of the main tenets of

thought among jurists interested in theological speculations. During the

nineteenth century, when the natural rights philosophy was repudiated by

politicians and by certain jurists the ancient theories, as molded under

mediaeval influences, continued to receive careful analysis, exposition, and

defence by Catholic writers.[1]


We can make no greater mistake [says Dean Pound], than to suppose that the

speculations of the metaphysical jurists were without practical effect upon

the law. We should be put on our guard, if by nothing else, by the wealth of

literature from this standpoint in the first three quarters of the century.

When a popular exposition thereof, such as Ahrens' Cours de droit naturel,

could go through twenty-four editions in seven languages between 1837 and

1892, men must have been finding satisfaction in the metaphysical theory of

law in more lands than one.[2]


1. Natural Law Doctrines of Del Vecchio. There are evidences of a return to

natural law theories in most of the European nations but in none is the

tendency more marked than in Italy, where the Catholic or Traditionalist

School has had a prominent position in legal thought.[3] Among the many

Italian advocates of the theories of natural law Professor Georgio del

Vecchio of the University of Rome is a leader among an active group who aim

to turn juristic philosophy in the direction of higher law ideas. Del

Vecchio insists that there must be in jurisprudence an element not derivable

from experience and he conceives a natural law based upon the common

elements in man's nature.[4] The war against natural law concepts, unless it

aims merely to correct errors and omissions, he regards as unjust and

irrational. To him the conception of absolute justice is one of the

fundamental needs of the human mind. Says del Vecchio:


    Natural law exists, therefore, as a system of the highest
    truths, not sensible but rational, and is, then, independent of
    the existence of common institutions in all nations ... the idea
    of natural law, which has withstood the attacks of skeptics
    and empiricists of past times will resist those of modern
    positivists, and will guide humanity in the future.[5]


Del Vecchio conceives as a universal element in the law what he calls its

logical form (Forma dat esse rei). This logical form is a metaphysical and

an a priori essence of the law. On the basis of these norms certain

principles of law are regarded as deducible a priori from human nature.[6]

Natural law is not, then, merely rationalized law; it constitutes "a special

order of juridical rules founded upon a definite criterion." In predicating

these universal norms of legal reasoning Del Vecchio suggests a

philosophical basis similar to the fundamental principles and the abstract

rule of reason permeating much of American constitutional law.[7]


Del Vecchio explains in detail the prevalence, in the Italian system of law

and in other legal systems based essentially on Roman ideas, of principles

of law or of basic notions which condition all legal thinking.


    Besides the multitude of special laws and of the decisions
    relating to particular cases and to definitely determined
    relations, there exists in our legislation [he says] notably in
    the Constitution and in part also in the preliminary provisions
    of the Civil Code or in other laws, positive affirmations of a
    general character which reflect in a measure more or less
    large, the rational elaborations concerning the law
    accomplished by the preceding schools of philosophy.[8]


Permeating the Code, legislative acts, and the interpretations of the judges

are the applications of such natural law concepts as the principle of

equality before the law, the respect for persons or individuality, the right

of privacy, the right to use one's faculties, and the right of property.[9]

The peculiar results derived from the applications of these concepts, it is

claimed, can by no means be understood by reference alone to the formal

provisions of the laws. But rather,


    there are, among all peoples, some fundamental convictions
    regarding modes and aims of conduct, which represent the
    common exigencies of human nature, displayed according to
    the degree of their development, and in relation to certain
    elements of outward fact. Such convictions determine
    generally all the forms under which life shows itself, and
    accordingly the juridical system among others, although they
    are not found written in the provisions of any code.[10]


The historical basis of right arises, Del Vecchio believes, from the

exigencies and aspirations of individual consciences. But it is not an

entirely variable concept, rather a form of right, which, "analogous to that

of morality, does not depend on facts, but rather tends to control them;

whence neither can it be limited by the institutions actually in vigor, of

whatever kind they may be; rather it sets its affirmations naturally beyond

these, and sometimes against them."[11]


When the rules of positive law come into conflict with the principles of

natural law, Del Vecchio asserts, it is the duty of the judge to apply the

positive rules. In such a case the principles of natural law, in his

judgment, remain alive and active and in the end will be recognized by the

positive law.[12] Formal rules and maxims contrary to reason may be imposed

temporarily but in the end equity, reason, and good faith will prevail

despite formal prescriptions to the contrary.


The following extracts will indicate Del Vecchio's point of view in his

effort to revive interest in natural law principles of a metaphysical type,

somewhat similar to the Kantian hypotheses.


    The idea of the natural right [law] is truly one of those which
    accompanies humanity in the course of its history; and
    though some schools, as it has happened very often,
    especially in our day, try to exclude it or to ignore it, the idea
    is affirmed powerfully once more in life. Consequently, it is
    rationally incorrect to try to discard it, and it is still more so
    when it is a question of interpreting a legislative system,
    under the dominance of this idea. Of this we have the proof,
    not so much in the preparatory works of which we would
    not want to exaggerate the importance from the standpoint
    of interpretation, as from the fact that our legislation
    concerning private law, is derived for the greater part from
    the Roman law, entirely developed about the idea of
    naturalis ratio, and that concerning public law, from the
    constitutional systems of England and of France which have
    for their fundamental bases a Bill of Rights and a Declaration
    of Rights, real and typical expressions of jus naturae.


    Whatever judgment the interpreter wishes to make from his
    point of view on this great doctrinal tradition, and on its
    actual significance, which is by many signs shown to be
    inexhaustible, one cannot, however, deny that this doctrinal
    tradition had a real existence and a vigorous efficacy at a
    time which corresponds to the formation of our present legal
    system. Hence the necessity of not neglecting its study and
    running the risk of refusing to understand the real and exact
    significance of the system.


    This study, which integrates that of the particular norms to
    which we have already alluded, constitutes also a check as
    well as an aid for individual thought in the reconstruction of
    the law now in force. It facilitates above all the seeking for
    origins concerning this part of the general principles of law
    which the legislator had the opportunity of recognizing and
    of formulating, without, however, giving them a complete
    and definite expression; also, this study makes easier the
    seeking for the principles which are not formulated, but
    which nevertheless actually exist in the system, where they
    are buried, so to speak, under the mass of particular norms,
    which are derived more or less from the application of these
    rules. The tie which exists between the general theories of
    law that prevail in the thought of a given period, and in the
    legal provisions which, in the same period, are organized
    and drawn up, can be discovered more or less direct, and
    more or less easy. Such a tie must exist, if it be true that the
    world of civil affairs has been made by men, and
    consequently these principles must be found in our human
    mind; in other words, if the human mind gives birth to the
    law as a phenomenon and as an idea. It is easy to
    understand, therefore, that the work of the interpreter, when
    he tries to comprehend and to integrate a system determined
    by history, cannot be wholly evolved from within, that is,
    arbitrarily and individually; it cannot consist in the affirmation
    of a natural right "which each one shapes for himself
    according to his individual whim," against which the logic of
    the jurist would have good reason to protest. The
    appropriate support and assurance, in our quest for
    principles, are given us by the entire general theories which
    envelop the law and which are not the artificial work of an
    individual thinker, but which correspond to a strong and true
    scientific tradition intimately linked in the genesis of the laws
    actually applied. And this consideration which is necessary
    to give to the doctrinal traditions does not prevent the
    elaboration of the ulterior elements which compose the
    whole; on the contrary, it facilitates their interpretation, in the
    sense that it indicates, by means of principles already
    assured, the direction in accordance with which their
    progress and ulterior development should move.[13]


    The school of natural law intended and intends essentially to
    uphold the non-arbitrary character of the law, that is to say,
    the existence of a necessary relationship between the
    intrinsic substance of things and between the rules of law
    which are connected with them.


    Even the principle upon which we are all particularly agreed,
    the principle of the innate and absolute right of the individual,
    agrees with this fundamental tendency; by this principle, in
    fact, one affirms that the true nature of man implies an
    element of transcendentalism, a faculty which cannot be
    suppressed, and which is consequently inalienable, to
    dominate the order of phenomena and to find in itself its own
    determination, in a word, to affirm the autonomy of the
    human being. The law cannot fail to recognize such a fact,
    nor refuse to take from it all the consequences and
    applications which are in its wake.


    According to the same criterion the way is open for the
    research of law corresponding to each kind of juridical
    reality, in so far as it contains relations between individuals.
    This inquiry, which is accomplished by means of the reason
    ("ex ratiocinatione animi tranquili"), as Thomasius said, has
    its normal period of comparison in the positive juridical rules
    which represent already, in fact, an attempt at a solution of
    the same problem. Numerous cases, and especially when it
    is a question of recognizing purely logical necessities of the
    immediate exigencies of our being, and of conditions of
    natural law, or of the naturalis ratio, manifest themselves,
    in a given moment, as elements of the positive law and form
    precisely its substratum, a substratum which is retained, and
    which is transmitted, through the changes of positive law.
    That, for example, no one can transfer to any one else more
    right than he himself enjoys; that it is legal to oppose strength
    and that, consequently, every one has the privilege to defend
    himself against any aggressions; that, in all matters, the
    advantage must belong to the one who has been
    inconvenienced; that no one can enrich himself unjustly at the
    expense of others. All these criteria, and many others that
    are similar to them, come from the natural juridical reason
    and have been in a sense already stated by the Roman
    jurists. They indicate the formative principles of the laws
    actually in force today, whether these laws express these
    principles precisely, or whether they are regarded as implied
    in the form of maxims, the disappearance of which would
    cause many particular legal provisions to lose all of their
    meaning.


    The necessity of having recourse to such criteria and, in
    general, to the natural juridical reason, is kept very active
    and very urgent by the incomplete nature which inevitably
    belongs to the positive law; it is so urgent, indeed, that one
    could not avoid such a recourse even if an expressed
    reference to general principles similar to the one offered by
    Art. 3 of the preliminary provisions of the Italian Civil Code,
    were lacking, as it happens in other systems (for instance, in
    the Code Napoleon and in the German Civil Code). This
    fundamental exigency which inspires the theories of natural
    law and which is called, in a wider sense, "equity," a
    consideration of all the elements of reality necessary to
    determine the equilibrium in the transactions between two
    persons, cannot be repudiated by positive legislation. This
    legislation itself, after having attempted to supply what is
    necessary in a measure for such an exigency, must admit
    finally that it is directly applied through the conscience alone
    of the judge, in all cases not determined by precise rules, nor
    likely to be determined by them, at least by analogy. It is
    noteworthy that, in certain cases, the legislator himself
    abstains deliberately from fixing a rule and acknowledges
    that he has recourse to this criterion of natural reason, which
    is presupposed as the intrinsic basis of law.[14]


The ancient adherents to doctrines of jus naturale, Del Vecchio thinks, were

wrong in so far as they attempted to identify natural law with the laws

common to different peoples and hence the reaction of the empiricists

resulted in an over-emphasis on the historic variability of law. This

conflict, it is thought, is obviated by conceiving a series of positive laws

as


    unified by the tendency toward the development of natural
    law. This tendency, grasped by the mind a priori as an
    absolute and universal necessity, superior and anterior to
    any application in experience, develops through a long and
    laborious historical evolution. This should not be taken to
    mean that natural law begins to be true or becomes law only
    at the moment when it is recognized and actualized (for this
    would throw us into the old error); the additional positive
    recognition does not result in value or truth, but is, at the
    most, a consequence or result of its value or truth.
    Observance or non-observance per se, as facts of the
    empirical order, do not affect the intrinsic significance of the
    principle, which is essentially transcendental, and which is
    self-sufficient in its sphere regardless of its unrecognition or
    violation in fact.[15]


It is difficult for one trained in Anglo-American legal ideas and traditions

to appreciate or understand the point of view of Del Vecchio. But it is a

point of view through which alone much of the legal thinking of Continental

European nations becomes intelligible. Though the traditionalist or

metaphysical approaches to an understanding of the law have had little vogue

in England and in America, these legal systems have been far from free from

metaphysical or transcendental legal notions.


Among the many modern exponents of religious and metaphysical theories of

natural law only a few can be briefly mentioned. A summary of some of the

views of a few representatives of this school may suggest the

characteristics of the higher law philosophy in its religious and

metaphysical garbs.


2. Theological Interpretation of Natural Law by Victor Cathrein. One of the

special advocates of the religious and metaphysical approach to natural law

is Cathrein.[16] Cathrein classifies the opponents of the natural law

philosophy in three groups: first, The Evolutionists, comprised of

pantheistic monists such as Paulsen, Wundt, Kohler, and Berolzheimer, or of

materialists such as Darwin and Spencer, or the economic determinists such

as Marx and Engels -- all of whom deny the existence of concepts or

principles of general and immutable value; second, The Empiricists, such as

Binding and Merkel, who recognize concepts and general principles but

pretend to discover them through the sole avenue of pure experience and

comparison; and, third, Formal a priorism of the kind of Stammler, who,

following the inspiration of Kant, wishes to bring back the immutable

essence of law in a pure form, exclusive of all predetermined content.[17]


Cathrein contends, in opposition to these tendencies, that every science and

notably juridical science implies the necessity of concepts and general

principles, in reality recognized by all, even by those who pretend to deny

their existence.[18] Referring to the point of view of Savigny and of the

Historical School that the real source of law is to be found in the spirit

or conviction of the people Cathrein claims that if one denies that there

are general principles of law controlling the actions of men, one is led in

a sort of circle to a supreme source of law in a "general consensus of

right," the "convictions of the people," or custom.[19] And these sources do

not in fact carry one to the real origins of law, for natural law is "the

indispensable foundation of positive law, since without it, one cannot

conceive of any regular authority or of any legal protection, of which the

state is the necessary instrument."[20]


Law is an essential part of the moral order to Cathrein and from the

concepts of the moral order juridical systems are evolved. Tracing the

ultimate sources of law to divine origins he embodies much of his analyses

in obtuse theological and supernatural notions which have tended to

discredit the work among jurists inclined to view their field scientifically

and practically.[21]


The position of Cathrein as to natural law may be summarized as follows:

There is a law of nature which governs the life of man, whether it is

discovered and followed or whether man attempts to defy it; God is the

primary source of this natural law and its secondary source is in its

revelation of its principles to man; all human enactments to be valid are

merely declaratory of this law.[22] This natural law (Recht) is the

indispensable foundation of positive law. It is universal and immutable.

Though its rules may be discovered by reason, they do not arise from reason

but from the superior will of the Creator.[23]


Contrasting the modern German political-historical thinking with the

characteristics of West-European and American political thinking, Ernst

Troeltsch finds two lines of thought dominant in Western Europe -- one

progressive, democratic, and revolutionary; the other conservative,

aristocratic, and authoritative -- both based upon the Ancient and Christian

ideas of an eternal-divine natural law. These ideas involve doctrines of the

homogeneity of human beings, of the uniform destiny of humanity, and an

abstraction of equality among men. Though many Germans, Catholics and

Lutherans alike, follow the conservative, aristocratic, authoritative

tradition, there is a new school which supports a religious-aesthetic ideal

placing the emphasis upon the individual human intellect as a positive and

creative force. In opposition to the rule of reason in the creation of the

state and doctrines of equality and homogeneity among men, these modern

German thinkers would found social and political organizations on

individualistic and pluralistic hypotheses. In this romantic ideology

natural law, whether progressive or conservative, has little place.[24]


3. Metaphysical Doctrines of Geny. Based only partially on religious and

doctrinal grounds a more effective exposition and defence of natural law

principles from the metaphysical standpoint are to be found in the writings

of Francois Geny.


Geny, who like Duguit ranks as one of the foremost jurists of France, has

been laboring many years to have his countrymen value more highly the

superior law concepts, which he conceives as the source and sanction of

positive law. The former rationalist type of natural law, Geny thinks,

suffers from an "aridness of analysis" and needs to be supplemented by "the

pliant and rich fecundity of intuition."[25] In fact Geny, along with others

of the Metaphysical School, gives much emphasis to the rôle of intuition, or

what is termed "intuitive understanding," in the determination of the

ultimate purposes and the end of the law. Man, considered as he is, living

amidst nature and society, finds himself, according to Geny, surrounded by

an ensemble of "necessary relations which are derived from the nature of

things." These arise from the physical, psychological, moral, social, as

well as the metaphysical or transcendent factors which control and confine

human actions. From these factors arise natural laws, some of which are

transcendent to all experience. Man can acquire a knowledge of these

transcendent rules and can be guided by them, though he cannot successfully

resist them. To Geny these natural laws have a distinct relation to the

religious and moral life of man.[26] The fundamental problem of the jurist,

no matter under what forms it maybe disguised, Geny thinks, is "the eternal

problem of natural law [droit]. And while the doctrines of natural law have

taken various forms, some of which continue to hold sway today, one no

longer pretends to build through reason an ideal system of law, eternal and

immutable, which is equally applicable to all times and all countries."[27]


Though Geny recognizes a theoretical supremacy of natural law and suggests

that in the case of an absolute conflict natural law must be superior to the

written law he realizes the impracticability of this conclusion,[28] and he says, "I believe for myself, that plain good sense,

elementary observation, and universal testimony, acknowledging the primary

necessity of order and recognizing that order can be established only by a

rule emanating from an effective authority, suffice amply to justify to the

reason the legitimate preeminence of the written positive law."[29] The main

obstacle, he thinks, which prevents the maintenance of the principles of

natural law when they come into conflict with the positive written law is

that these principles of natural law, however firm their basis, consist only

of general directions of conduct. They are too abstract and too evanescent

for the concrete circumstances of social life, especially when they clash

with the definite judgments of formal authorities. It is his belief that

this vagueness can in part be overcome by bills of rights in written

constitutions wherein are expressed the essential principles of immutable

natural law. This expedient, however, is regarded as unsatisfactory, for

either the written constitution becomes over-rigid and an obstacle to

legitimate progress[30] or it loses its rigor in an indefinitiveness that

discredits the value of a written instrument.[31]


In his judgment, however, a rigid constitution judiciously used and broadly

interpreted might be useful, if it could be given an effective sanction and

if its precepts could be placed beyond the reach of ordinary law. Hence some

method must be found to temper practically "the brutal power of the written

laws, in order to stop their action or impair their results every time that

they attempt to interfere with justice, to slight the objective factors of

the social life, or to pass beyond the injunctions or prohibitions of

natural law."[32]


Among the devices to temper arbitrariness in the enforcing of the law Geny

commends the "exception d'inconstitutionnalité," the declaring of a law

invalid by the judiciary, which he believes could be adopted, in a measure

at least, without contradicting any essential principle of French public

law. On the contrary it is his judgment that such authority wielded by

judges would serve to assure a guarantee of the indispensable application of

the principles of public law.[33] Admitting the difficulties and the

weaknesses of the American plan of judicial review of legislative enactments

to test their validity, which has led critics to speak of it as a

"government by judges," Geny concludes that the organization of the

judiciary in France and the traditions of the country would prevent such

excesses and that it would be in "perfect harmony with the essential bases

of the French constitution" to adopt a similar plan. To those who claim that

the existing courts of France would be unequal to the responsibilities of so

great a power and that a special court should be created for this purpose,

Geny replies that such a proposal is wholly unnecessary and that from every

standpoint the matter could be left to the jurisdiction of the regularly

established tribunals.[34]


Where no effective means are provided to check arbitrary authority on the

part of the government Geny regards the right of resistance as legitimate,

but the right must be surrounded by some obvious limitations in the

direction of maintaining the individual rights of man. Admitting that when a

conflict arises between positive law and natural law, positive law must

prevail, he aims to modify the rigor of the strict enforcement of the

written law and to suggest remedies whereby the flagrant injustice of its

provisions may be prevented. In his judgment every possible device should be

provided to check abusive applications of the law, which may lead, if not

prevented, to forcible resistance.


To keep governmental agencies within reasonable bounds Geny says he agrees

with Duguit and Hauriou that it is necessary to establish superior

principles of law and right as a restraint on the majorities who make the

law.[35] As he sees it, concepts of justice must be sought which represent

"a higher reality existing outside of ourselves."


It is necessary, Geny believes, to find the source of the law in natural

law, which has developed from ancient times and has persisted in spite of

all opposition and criticisms.[36] He thinks it is not, as is often

suggested, a means of supplying omissions in positive legal rules but the

very foundation upon which positive rules rise and develop.


Speaking of the necessity of natural law, Geny says:


    The problem of the existence of natural law remains today
    as always, the center of gravity of the positive juridical
    system. And, whether one acknowledges it or not, one
    perceives it underlying all the efforts which are pursued, in
    order to realize in an effective manner a better and more
    complete justice among men. On what bases would the state
    be established, which preserves in all its powers the positive
    rules of the social order, and from whence are the powers
    derived which form it, whether from a simple fact or from a
    group of principles. Those who make the law, the
    legislators, are they free to create this law to their liking,
    following their ideas, their interests, their passions or rather
    ought they to conform to a superior norm dominating all
    subjective impressions? Those who engage in the work of
    positive law, as administrators, those who interpret or apply
    it, in the capacity of judges, are they bound by this form, by
    the text of the law; ought they not to look beyond this, to
    penetrate to the sources, intimate and substantial, from
    whence they are derived, and those who obey the law, who
    ought to observe its precepts, to avoid its penalties, are
    these obligated to submit without recourse to its injunctions?
    Can they not understand, discuss, criticise the established
    rules, I mean not only as electors but as subjects; and do
    they not have the right to interpret, to modify, to transform
    the existing law, indeed, in extreme cases to rebel against it;
    this implies that they appeal to aspirations defying by their
    nature the variations of particular legal formulas? And, in the
    international domain also, where would the necessary rules
    be found to establish the relations between states, if there is
    no place for the reality of precepts, outside of the above
    positive rules, which are here always small and
    precarious.[37]


On the whole, Geny has presented a thorough and suggestive analysis of

natural law, with a leaning toward the religious and metaphysical points of

view.[38] He differs from Cathrein, however, in that he presents and

criticizes the views of other natural law philosophers and attempts

throughout to make practical applications of his theories.


The metaphysical types of natural law of Del Vecchio and of Geny, though

differing in certain respects from the realistic approach to higher law by

Duguit, have some characteristics in common with the rule of law (règle de

droit). The higher laws to which all human civil enactments must conform are

traced to different sources, the methods of their discovery vary, but

substantially the same results follow. Legal norms which may be discovered

by the reason or by the intuition of men stand above and guide the entire

process of law-making and law enforcement. It is the duty of legislators,

judges, and administrators to seek these norms and conform their

interpretations to their superior directive force.[39]


4. Natural Law Theories and International Law. A significant phase of the

revival of natural law in Europe is apparent in the efforts to find an

enduring basis for international law. Realizing the insecurity of

international rules and agreements based solely on treaties, conventions, or

a general consensus among the rulers of existing states there is a tendency

to recur to general and universal principles of justice as discovered and

interpreted through reason according to the methods of Gentilis, Grotius,

and Pufendorf. Scholars and jurists are again raising the question whether

in the international field, at least, there does not exist a natural or

objective law, independent of the will of any state or group of states, and

whether the action of states in this field is not limited to ascertaining

and giving sanction to this natural law. This phase of the revival of

natural law theories has so many ramifications that it is quite impossible

to deal with it adequately in this treatise. Some representative opinions

maybe cited to indicate one of the noteworthy trends in the efforts to

establish international law on a more secure foundation.


The trend of thought today regarding the relation of natural law theories to

the growth of international law is indicated in a symposium of views by

well-known authorities on public law. The following questionnaire was

submitted to a representative group of teachers and jurists:


    Is the theory of natural law in relation to the law of nations,
    jus naturae et gentium, as advanced by Grotius, and
    developed in the course of the seventeenth and eighteenth
    centuries, in force today? -- That is to say, ought
    international and national courts as well as courts of
    arbitration to follow the principles of this theory, to interpret
    and to complete positive international law, in order to
    establish an accord of views among states?


    In case of an affirmative reply to the question proposed
    above, is it the law of morality which forms the basis of the
    practical application of said theory or is it the objective
    solidarity of the interests of each of the states carefully
    considered? Or what other formula would be preferred?


The answers to the queries show a wide diversity of opinions. Most of the

replies, referring chiefly to the first query, may be classified under a few

groups.[40] One group would discard natural law theories entirely because

they "tend to confuse thought and to encourage loose and vague

conceptions."[41] Principles of natural law, according to this view, are

valid only when accepted by the nations as a part of the customary

international law.[42] Another group regard natural law useful to assist

justices and arbitrators, when interpreting existing rules of law and when

there are deficiencies and uncertainties in the rules of international law

applicable to controversies. Some in this group would prefer the use of the

phrase "principles of equity" or "principles of morals and justice" to the

term "natural law."[43]


Others favor the use of natural law not only to interpret but also to

supplement positive international law.[44] Among this group Gustav Radbruch,

German Minister of Justice, thinks international justices should have

authority similar to the Swiss judges to fill gaps when written rules are

inapplicable, and when necessary to use natural law as a guide. In fact,

this authority is regarded as more necessary in international affairs

because of the grave dangers arising from legal uncertainties and from

unsatisfactory decisions. "The fact is of the greatest importance that even

today natural law is not dead, is not a repudiated idea," he asserts,


    but a reality which is active in a powerful way. Ernst
    Troeltsch has shown in a way that cannot be forgotten how
    the ideas of natural law and of humanity are powerful
    influences in the Western-European and American, as well
    as in the Catholic world of thought, and that a new approach
    for the German historical-organical-positive school to the
    natural law theory is desirable and inevitable.


    If in international legal agreements, reference is made to the
    "highest fundamental principles of international politics," or to
    the "international moral law," or to the "fundamental
    principles of justice and humanity which cannot be
    renounced" as to something that is evident, what is really
    meant is the legal principles comprised in natural law. Not as
    a necessity of reason but as a forceful fact of history, a form
    of appearance of "approved teachings and traditions," these
    natural legal methods of thinking have to serve as a guiding
    star for the further development of international law just as
    they were decisive for its formation. But one is not allowed
    to regard these ideas of natural law as an arsenal from which
    the legal thoughts of international law can be taken as a
    finished product, but rather as an atmosphere in which such
    legal thoughts are formed. To make it clearer one may call
    this atmosphere with another word, "civilization."[45]


Eugen Schiffer, German Minister of Justice, also insists that there is a

place for natural law in the development of international law:


    I have, to be sure, the heretical point of view, that is, that in
    the classification of the different elements of the
    administration of justice, the personality of the judge is
    foremost, the formulation of a method, comes second, and
    the positive law, last. An able judge almost always manages
    to get along with a defective method and an insufficient
    positive law; and, even if he has available a good method, he
    will mostly obviate the lack or the faults of the law at hand.
    On the other hand, the best formal law is of no use, if it is
    paralyzed in its realization by an unfit method, or if it is put
    into the hands of an unqualified judge.... Therefore, I have
    no doubt about it that a high international court will not be
    stranded by the lack of actual law which it has to administer,
    it will rather be its main task and its greatest worth to guide
    the wavering materials of international agreements and of
    legal international practices by a usus fori, and to bring them
    from the sphere of occasional actions of a political character
    to the level of firm and constant legal norms.


    Naturally I would not have it understood that the question of
    actual law is not of farreaching importance for the highest
    courts. Furthermore I do not overlook the difficulties which
    are the result of the composition of these courts, with the
    political, cultural, and social points of view of their members
    who come from the most different fields of law, for the
    production of a common positive legal basis. Therefore, the
    question of the necessity of such a basis is absolutely
    justified, and, through the nature of international law, the
    positive parts of which have been badly diminished and
    shaken by the last world events, the problem of subsidiary
    law becomes very urgent. To my mind only the fundamental
    principles of natural law can be taken into consideration for
    such a law. I, at least, do not know any other law that could
    fill the gaps of positive international law. But these
    fundamental principles of natural law I would neither
    measure with the rule of international solidarity of interest
    nor with the scale of the recognized subjective interests of
    the states.[46]


Professor Louis Le Fur of the University of Paris answered these questions

in the affirmative and his views may well be quoted as indicative of a point

of view gaming adherents in Continental Europe.[47]


"The theory of jus naturae et gentium of Grotius," Le Fur observes,


    is none other than the application to international relations of
    the traditional theory which is very old, since it goes back far
    beyond Christianity, and which distinguishes between the
    law laid down by men, the positive law, and a law anterior
    and superior to the will of man. In the century in which
    Grotius wrote, there was at times hesitation to apply to the
    sovereign state the principles of law, whether for reasons of
    pure abstract logic drawn from the nature of sovereignty, or
    for political considerations similar to those which inspired
    Machiavelli; as soon as the state was involved, which is
    always the case in international law, it appears that the
    question of law was no longer considered as it was when
    individuals were concerned. Now, the state is only a group
    of men governed by men; it can through its governors deny
    morality and law and be motivated only by its interests, that
    is to say, practically speaking, by its strength; but if the state
    recognizes juridical and moral rules, the bases of these rules
    cannot be different from the bases of those which apply to
    individuals. This is the truth of which Grotius caught a
    glimpse, but very often with less clearness than his
    predecessors of the Spanish school, such as Vittoria or
    Suarez; when applied to international law, it appears as the
    ultimate consequence of this truth established by experience
    that man is what has been called a "juridical being," a being
    whose characteristic it is to be ruled by law.[48]


Le Fur thinks that man, being gifted with reason and a moral sense or

conscience, and having social tendencies, possesses certain juridical

characteristics which grow out of his life as a social being and from his

own nature. When these rules acquire a sanction to compel obedience to them

they become laws. Those are in error, he says, who confuse the state and the

law and who consider the former a necessary condition of the latter. The

state, he claims, cannot make law arbitrarily. The nature of human beings

must be taken into account and their characteristics as beings gifted with

reason and with a moral sense.[49] This, in his judgment,


    is the profound truth which has been expressed, under
    diverse names, by the wisdom of all the ages; if one has
    been able to speak of a philosophia perennis, there is in
    regard to essential principles a jus perenne which controls
    legal phenomena with more clearness. These diverse names
    signify none else than natural, or rational, or objective law,
    all these terms expressing the same truth, which is that law,
    the rule of life in society, the only life possible for man, is not
    an arbitrary creation of man. No being formulates for himself
    the laws which govern his life. Whatever the form of
    government of a people, be it monarchical or democratic,
    those who govern can do no more than recognize the law,
    deduce it from facts interpreted by the reason, and
    harmonize it with the circumstances of time and environment.
    For, although immutable in its fundamental nature -- which
    is no other than a moral principle, the idea of justice, itself
    the soul of law -- the law is very variable, on the contrary,
    in its application since, according to the degree of
    civilization, the circumstances of life in society are apt to
    vary quite considerably, from a three-fold point of view, that
    is an economic, an intellectual, and a moral point of view,
    and these three are far from always keeping abreast.[50]


Conceiving natural law in the role of an ideal law, which is regarded as the

traditional use of the term, Le Fur finds that there is no question about

its place in a legal system. "To deny that there can be no other law than

the positive law under pretext, for example, that there can be no law

without a sanction, and that the positive law is the only law which has a

sanction, -- is," he maintains, "to assert that the positive law is

necessarily what it ought to be, and is to withdraw in this respect all law

from criticism."[51] He continues:


    From what precedes it follows that all juridical relations must
    be conceived in two ways, or, if preferred, that there exist
    two kinds of law: a rational or natural law, with a moral
    basis, which is in itself an abstract truth as are all natural
    laws, existing objectively, as the latter, but unsuspected by
    men as long as it was not deduced by the effort of the
    human mind -- and a positive law by which those who
    govern attempt to make it effective, both having as an end
    the common good of the group to be governed, be it a
    patriarchal family, a tribe, a city, or a state.[52] 


In his opinion, just as there are limits which a state must recognize in its

relations with individuals, so there are limits which bind states in their

international dealings. Hence


    one is under the necessity either to deny international law, to
    admit that the nations live in a pre-juridical state, without
    objective or conventional rules which bind them, war, the
    expression of the right of the strongest, being the only
    solution in conflicts -- or to recognize the existence of a
    natural or objective international law, which is not a pure
    form covering any sort of content, but rather a just and
    useful law, corresponding to the common good, and the
    common good is here that of the entire international
    community. Exactly as in the case of internal law, it is not
    arbitrary human wills, but really an historical, economical,
    and moral complex, which conditions international law.[53]


Just as in the case of private law, arbitral courts and international

tribunals must be guided, he thinks, not only by the interests of the states

involved but also by principles of justice and of natural equity which are

the background of all positive enactments. And, just as a national judge is

authorized to make a rule where the written law is defective, international

judges, when a pre-existing rule is lacking, must to a limited extent

perform the functions of an international legislature.[54]


The natural law to be applied by these judges is not of an immutable kind

according to the eighteenth-century model nor of a variable type such as

Stammler describes but a form of the concept with both permanent and

variable characteristics.[55]


"With regard to international law," says Sir Frederick Pollock, "it is

notorious that all authorities down to the end of the eighteenth century,

and almost all outside of England to this day, have treated it as a body of

doctrine derived from and justified by the Law of Nature."[56] "Here as

elsewhere," he suggests, "we must apply the principle of Aristotle, and deem

that to be reasonable, which appears so to competent persons. There must be

a competent and prevalent consent, and the best evidence of such consent is

constant and deliberative usage."[57] There are those in England as

elsewhere who vision a Magna Carta for the field of international relations

which shall set the world on the path of legality rather than that of force

to settle disputes between nations and which shall limit the scope of the

arbitrary powers of sovereigns.[58]


Though little progress has been made in formulating the rules and principles

of natural law applicable to international relations it is a common belief

that in the drafting and the interpretation of an international code

modernized versions of the law of nature or law of reason will have a

directive influence.[59]


5. Theories of Natural Law Prevalent in Europe. In the extensive use which

was made of the natural law philosophy in Continental European legal

thinking since the eighteenth century there are apparent a variety of types

of superior law theories. The inheritance of the Middle Ages furnished a

form of higher law concept in the nature of law fundamental which was

designed to keep rulers within recognized legal channels. Not only was there

a foundation for a resistance to arbitrary rule which gave sanction to the

leaders of rebellion and revolution but there was in this concept an

ever-present criterion for judges and administrators to hold in check

over-zealous officials. Such a higher law philosophy was supported by the

continuance of the eighteenth-century theories of natural rights which

result from notions either of the laws of God or of qualities inherent in

the individual. The nineteenth-century concept of civil liberty -- a realm

within which the individual is secure from political interference -- which

emerges into a doctrine of limited government under constitutional

sanctions, owes much to this form of the natural law philosophy.


The theologians and those influenced by the philosophy of the church,

conceived natural law after the model of Thomas Aquinas, as an emanation

from God. Its principles, which were eternal and universal, might be

discovered through reason and revelation. Religion, morality, and politics

were therefore only different phases of the same basic ideas. Civil

enactments which failed to conform with the religious and moral standards

revealed by the Church were denied validity.


Some jurists who no longer emphasized the religious background found for

natural law a priori and metaphysical bases. They conceived a logical form

or juridical norm to which all valid civil enactments must conform. Such a

norm was in its essence universal -- an ideal becoming objective and

directive as it conditioned all the processes of law-making and law

enforcement. Not discoverable in any existing legal rules, it was inherent

as a formal principle in all such rules which were just and valid.


As speculation on legal matters was fostered by the universities and courses

in the philosophy of law were offered, natural law and the philosophy of law

were thought of as identical. Thus natural law became synonymous with a

series of ideal moral and legal principles which might be commented upon

extensively. The philosophical mold into which natural law thinking was cast

in the early nineteenth century gave it a wide currency in intellectual

circles and brought it increasingly into contempt among politicians and

practical lawyers. Certain treatises appearing at this time not only aimed

to combine natural law and the philosophy of law but also to explain both of

these in the light of religious and moral principles. Political practices

and legal rules were put to the test of standards derived from this curious

compound of speculations. No wonder that the very name of "natural law"

became anathema among those who were seeking a scientific basis for social

phenomena.


At all times natural law has been considered as a body of principles or

doctrines, sufficiently well known and approved to be used by judges in

molding the law to suit concrete cases or in filling gaps in the written

rules as applicable to controversies. And at the same time it has been

regarded as a body of doctrines or ideas available for jurists and legal

writers as a standard for the criticism of existing laws and decisions, in

the development of what Continental jurists call the jurisprudence and the

doctrines of the law. In such a rôle natural law comprises a series of

subjective and objective standards which may be used to determine the

justice or reasonableness of legal rules. To some, these standards are

universal and immutable. Sociological jurists, on the other hand, find in

the natural law with a variable content standards adapted to the times and

conditions which measure the reasonableness or justice of the rules enforced

in a given society.


The political thought of the Middle Ages was affected by the ideas of

government based on popular consent, of natural rights belonging to the

individual, and of theories of contract as a basis of civil society. From

such ideas arose a belief in higher laws which result from the common

feelings and sentiments of the people. Concepts of law and of rights were

traced to this popular source. The Historical School of jurists, though

repudiating earlier doctrines of natural law, merely paved the way for

another type of higher law doctrine -- one arising from the settled customs

and traditions of the people.


The adherents of natural law fall into three main groups. First, those who

place superior laws of a fixed, immutable character, usually religious or

ethical in origin, over and above all the acts and rules of mankind.

Following the Absolutists in their approach to philosophical problems they

look upon lawmakers and judges as seekers "among divine sources for

pre-existing truth."[60] The inexorable rules of natural law may be

discovered or not, but failure to abide by them will, in the course of time,

result disastrously. Some of the theories of natural rights also predicated

an immutable order with eternal laws, but rights and laws were among the

inherent qualities of man in such an order. These rights, too, were to be

discovered and applied but not changed. It is interesting to see how the

absolutist concepts of natural law and natural rights keep recurring in

legal thought whether founded on religious sanctions or on the inherent

qualities of man.


The second group of thinkers undertake to find the underlying principles

of law in the customs and the social life of man, or in the interests and

duties of man as a human being. Recently theorists with this approach

have sought the fundamental legal rules in community sentiment, the feeling

for right (Rechtsgefühl), or in the concept of social solidarity. With a

slight turn in emphasis this method of finding natural law leads to a "natural

law with a variable content." Viewing higher law notions in a broad sense

this group comprises some of the foremost analysts of legal phenomena

on the Continent of Europe.[61]


Natural law as an idealistic, progressive, and critical concept is what the

third group is expounding. Interested in the philosophy of the law, they

seek "the rational element which enters into the complex product of the

legislation of every nation.... In practice, it is still often called by the

name 'natural law,' which is opposed to the term 'positive law.' ... It is

the ideal of the positive law, the type which the lawmaker ought to realize,

and almost always pretends to realize."[62] When, as with Stammler, the

philosophy of law becomes the theory of propositions about law which have

universal validity, one is in the field of natural law ideas.[63]


In European political thought it is the ideal, progressive, and critical

function of natural law which is uppermost. Whatever its sources or

sanctions maybe the chief proponents of higher law ideas are not engaged in

a search for final legal rules to which all mankind must yield obedience.

They are directing their efforts to the discovery of fundamental principles,

of directing norms, or of established standards by which the reasonableness

or justice of legal rules may be measured. The absolutist, dogmatic concepts

of natural law have been largely replaced by those characterized as

"idealistic criticism."


It is, therefore, in the realm of jurisprudence and in the development of

legal doctrines that natural law thinking prevails in European legal

thought. Its functions are to guide, to criticize, and to measure the law as

made by legislators and applied by judges so as to keep it in reasonable and

just channels. The natural law concepts, then, whether used by judges or

commentators are, to a large extent, as they were with the Roman jurists,

creative forces in an epoch of progressive law-making.




1. See Tancrède Rothe, Traité de droit naturel théorique et appliqué, 6

vols. (Paris, 1885-1912). Rothe's work indicates in its incomplete form the

inclusive features of natural law as conceived by certain Catholic writers.

Among the subjects considered in the six volumes of the treatise are: the

definition and nature of law and the state; the duties of men towards others

and towards God; the relations of the individual to government; marital

relations, the family and education; social and individual services,

including the conditions and the rights relating to labor; and the rights of

corporate organizations of labor and capital. A theological school composed

of Protestants and Papal representatives led a reaction against the autonomy

of the reason in religious, moral, and legal matters. For a defence of a

metaphysical basis for natural law and for the philosophy of law, see

Boistel, Cours de philosophie da droit (1899), Appendix.


Vareilles-Sommières, Dean of the faculty of law of Lille, in his Les

principes fondamentaux du droit (Paris, 1889), divides the laws which are

directly divine into natural laws and positive divine laws: "the natural

laws are those which result as necessary consequences and as [forcement]

willed by God, from the nature which he has given to us, and which manifest

themselves to our reason alone....


The natural laws are universal and immutable since they are the necessary

result of the nature of man and of those beings with whom he is in

relation." Pages 20 ff.


Cf. also Theodor Meyer, Institutiones iuris naturalis, 2 vols. (1886-90).


2. Interpretations of Legal History, p. 33.


3. Vico frequently referred to the idea of a law of nature. He was one of

the first to insist that it was not a fixed but a progressive law -- "a law

varying with the stage of growth reached by a given community." Cf. G. de

Montemayor, Storia del diritto naturale (Naples, 1911), especially chap. 11;

Croce, The Philosophy of Vico, trans. by Collingwood (London, 1913);

Benvenuto Donati, Domat e Vico, ossia del sistema del diritto universale

(Macerata, 1923).


4. I presupposti filosofici della nozione del diritto (1905); Il concetto

del diritto (1906); Il concetto della natura e il principio del diritto

(1908), translated under the title The Formal Bases of Law in Comparative

Legal Philosophy Series, X (Boston, 1914); cf. chap. 3.


5. The Formal Bases of Law, p. 18.


6. Ibid., pp. 76 ff., 258, 321, 333. For citations to Italian articles and

works defending natural law, see ibid., p. 19.


7. See H. J. Randall, "An Italian Exposition of the Law of Nature," Law

Quarterly Review, XXXIII (April, 1917), 161.


8. "Sui principi generali del diritto," reprint from Archivio Guiridico,

XXXV, 4th ser., vol. I, fasc. 1, pp. 21 ff. I am indebted to Professor Del

Vecchio for reprints of several of his articles and lectures on natural law.

He has kindly consented to the use of translations of portions of his "Sui

principi generali del diritto."


9. Del Vecchio, op. cit., pp. 34-42.


10. Georgio Del Vecchio, "Positive Right," Law Magazine and Review, XXXVIII

(May, 1913), 297.


11. Del Vecchio, "Positive Right," op cit., p. 306. Positive right is that

which at any given moment effectively governs the life of a people and hence

is not restricted to rules established by statute.


12. The Formal Bases of Law, pp. 52 ff.


13. "Sui principi generali del diritto," pp. 23-25, or "Les principes

généraux du droit," trans. into French by E. Demontes with a Preface by R.

Demogue (Paris, 1925), p. 25, or "Die Grundprinzipien des Rechts," trans. by

Albert Hellwig, pp. 24-26.


14. "Sui principi generali del diritto," pp. 47-49; "Les principes généraux

du droit," pp. 50-52.


15. The Formal Bases of Law, p. 326. For other recent Italian

interpretations of natural law, consult G. Brunetti, "Il diritto naturale

nella legislazione civile," Rivista del diritto commerciale, XX (1922), Nos.

8-9, and M. Cordovani, "Il diritto naturale nella moderna cultura italiana,"

Rivista internazionale di filosofia del diritto, IV (1924), No 2.


16. V. Cathrein, Recht, Naturrecht und positive Recht, Eine kritische

Untersuchung der Grundbegriffe der Rechtsordnung (2d ed., 1909). Geny speaks

of this work as "imbued with the pure tradition of the Catholic Church,"

Science et technique en droit privé positif, II, 295; see also G. Platon,

Pour le droit naturel -- Apropos du livre de M. Hauriou; Les principes du

droit public (Paris, 1911).


17. Op. cit., pp. 14 ff., and Geny, op. cit., II, 301.


18. Op. cit., pp. 16-41, and Geny, II, 302. For approval of Cathrein's views

by Geny, see II, 307 ff. Cf. also Gutberlet, Ethik und Naturrecht (3d ed.,

1901).


19. Op. cit., pp. 145 ff.


20. Ibid., pp. 252, 253.


21. Geny thinks supernatural theorizing is not an essential part of

Cathrein's work and he refers to Boistel and Cathrein as modern

representatives of the classical conception of natural law. Op. cit., II,

350.


22. For a similar method of analysis, see James Lorimer, The Institutes of

Law: A treatise of the Principles of Jurisprudence as Determined by Nature

(2d ed., London, 1880).


A modernized form of the version of natural law of St. Thomas is in The

Catholic Encyclopaedia, where natural law is regarded as comprised of three

constituents:


    first, a discriminating norm, which is of the essence of human nature 

itself as a reflection of the divine nature; second, a binding norm, which

is evidenced in the divine authority requiring that individuals live in

accordance with the first norm; and third, a manifesting norm, which is the

result of the efforts of reason to determine the moral qualities of actions

as limited by the first norm.


23. Op. cit., pp. 222 ff.; Geny, op. cit., pp. 314 ff.


24. Ernst Troeltsch, Naturrecht und Humanitat in der Weltpolitik (Berlin,

1923).


25. Op. cit., I, 16. He agrees with Phillipson that "as in science,

metaphysical entities are being more and more imported, so in the sphere of

law will those principles of natural law come to be more and more

emphasized, through the ineradicable promptings of the intuitive

consciousness of men and of states." Great Jurists of the World, p. 343.


26. Op. cit., pp. 43, 44.


27. Ibid., II, 10, 12.


28. Op. cit., IV, 72 ff.


29. Ibid., p. 78.


30. Cf. criticisms by Edouard Lambert on the practice of interpreting the

general and vague phrases of written constitutions in the United States in

Le gouvernement des juges et la lutte contre la législation sociale aux

États-Unis (Paris, 1921).


31. Geny, op. cit., IV, 87.


32. Ibid., pp. 81 ff.


33. Ibid., IV, 91.


34. Ibid., pp. 101, 102.


35. Geny, op. cit., IV, 137 ff.


36 Ibid., II, 312 ff.


37. Ibid., IV, 213, 214. Saleilles remarks on Geny's concepts of natural law

that he does not maintain that for a given institution there is a body of

rules which possesses at least rational existence and which can be

formulated into absolute truths; he does not maintain that on a given point

any solution can appear in its concrete expression as a formula of natural

law; he only contends that in the formulation of a judicial or legal rule

judges and legislators have the right and the duty to be guided by ideas of

justice, principles of reason, and axioms of equity, the philosophical forms

of which would be the expression of immutable and intangible truths for all

civilized peoples, "École historique et droit naturel," Revue trimestrielle

de droit civil, I (1902), 87 ff.


38. Reviewing Geny's last volume of the Science et technique en droit privé

positif, E. H. Perreau calls this the work of a true Benedictine "Le conflit

du droit naturel et de la loi positive," Revue General du droit, XLIX

(1925), 27.


39. Malberg consigns these so-called rules of natural or divine law to the

moral or political realm and concludes that "it is a capital error of the

jurists that they persist in supporting the doctrine of 'natural law,' an

error from which it would be desirable to free the science of law for a long

time." To Malberg a rule of law in the true sense can proceed only from the

state, which by its superior force can give it a sanction. Contribution à la

théorie générale de l'état, I (Paris, 1920), 237.


40. "Jus naturae et gentium; Eine Umfrage zum Gedächtnis des Hugo Grotius"

in Niemeyers Zeitschrift für Internationales Recht, XXXIV (1925), 113-189.


41. Comments of Philip Marshall Brown, ibid., pp. 116-118.


42. See Niemeyers Zeitschrift für Internationales Recht, XXXIV, opinions of

Fritz Fleiner, University of Zurich, pp. 121, 122; Friedrich Giese,

University of Frankfort, p. 141; Eduard His, University of Zurich, pp.

142-144; Sir T. Erskine Holland, Oxford University, pp. 144, 145; Christian

Meurer, University of Würzburg, p. 160; Karl Neumeyer, University of

Munchen, p. 161; Karl Strupp, University of Frankfort, pp. 173, 174;

Heinrich Triepel, University of Berlin, pp. 187, 188.


43. To this group belong Charles Dupuis, Institute of International Law,

Paris, ibid., pp. 120, 121; Walter Burckhardt, University of Berne, pp. 118,

119; Alexander Pearce Higgins, Cambridge University, p. 142; George

Kleinfeller, University of Kiel, p. 150. Recognizing that the prevailing

view among English authorities on international law is that of the

Positivist School, Professor Higgins says "appeals are, however, made to the

underlying principles of the Law of Nature under the name of Reason or

Justice when a test is sought for existing rules, or as a means of

suggesting new rules to fill the gaps in the law which modern conditions

disclose." Ibid., p. 142.


44. Rudolf Laun, University of Hamburg, ibid., 150-152; T. de Louter,

University of Utrecht, 152; Joseph Mausbach, University of Münster, 152-160;

Otto Opet, University of Kiel, 161, 162; Robert Piloty, University of

Würzburg, 163, 164; Nicholas S. Politis, University of Paris, 165; Louis Le

Fur, University of Paris, 122-140; Edgard Roubard de Card, University of

Toulouse, 168, 169; André Weisz, University of Paris, 189.


45. Niemeyers Zeitschrift für Internationales Recht, XXXIV, 166 ff.; cf.

Ernst Troeltsch, op. cit.


46. Niemeyers Zeitschrift fur Internationales Recht, XXXIV, 169-171. Duguit

finds a real basis for international law in certain international norms

exterior to the action of any individual state, which must form the basis

for valid joint action in the form of legal rules of conduct. Traité de

droit constitutionnel (2d ed.) I, 99 ff.


47. Niemeyers Zeitschrift fur Internationales Recht, pp. 122-140. See also,

"Le droit naturel ou objectif s'étend-il aux rapports intemationaux,"

reprint from Revue de droit international et de législation comparée (1925).

Le Fur states that he uses the terms "natural law" (droit) and "objective

law" interchangeably and that "the second expression has gained general

approval today in all countries; but the first one is the traditional

expression, and the idea which it expresses rests on a very just basis, if

one frees it from the errors which became incorporated in it during the

eighteenth century (where, rather than a natural law, one speaks of a law of

nature, having in mind a supposed state of primitive nature which would be a

state of isolation). Nothing therefore keeps us from reclaiming this

expression, once it is freed from the purely adventitious errors which had

found their way into it, and this is, in fact, what every one is inclined to

do today." Ibid., p. 60.


Portions of this article have been translated and are included herewith by

the special permission of Professor Le Fur. See also, by the same author,

"Le droit naturel et le droit rationnel ou scientifique: leur rôle dans la

formation du droit international," Revue de droit international (July,

August, and September, 1927); and "La théorie du droit naturel depuis le

XVIIIe siècle et la doctrine moderne" (Paris, 1928)


48. Le Fur, Revue de droit international et de législation comparée (1925),

pp 61, 62.


49. Le Fur, Revue de droit international et de législation comparée (1925),

p. 62.


50. Ibid., p. 64.


51. Le Fur, Revue de droit international et de législation comparée (1925),

p. 66.


52. Ibid., p. 67.


53. Ibid., p. 68.


54. Ibid , pp. 78, 79. An attempt has been made in France as well as in

other countries, to base international law on the individualistic doctrine

of the origin of law. It is called the theory of the fundamental rights of

states. Just as an individual is regarded as having certain inherent rights,

so states, it is asserted, have fundamental natural rights which must be

respected by all other states. There exist, it is claimed, among the states

fundamental, primitive, and absolute rights, rights which belong to every

state in its relations with other states. Among some of the rights mentioned

are independence, equality, respect, and international commerce. A. Pillet,

"Recherches sur les droits fondamentaux des états," Revue générale de droit

international public, V (1898), 66, 236; VI (1899), 503. For an American

version of such fundamental rights, consult James Brown Scott, "The American

Institute of International Law: Its Declaration of the Rights and Duties of

Nations" (1916), and comments by Elihu Root in American Journal of

International Law, X (1916), 211.


55. Cf. "Le droit naturel, le droit rationnel ou scientifique," op. cit., p.

37.


56. Essays in the Law, p. 63.


57. Ibid., pp. 63, 64. Cf. opinion of the English law officers (including

Lord Mansfield) in the case of the Silesian Loan, that the law of nations is

founded upon justice, equity, convenience, and the reason of the thing and

confirmed by long usage." Holliday's Life of William Earl of Mansfield

(London, 1797), p. 428.


58. W. S. McKechnie, "Magna Carta (1215-1915)," Malden, Magna Carta

Commemoration Essays, pp. 22, 23.


59. Lord Russell remarks on the employment of the natural law method in

modern international law, "International Law and Arbitration," American Bar

Association Reports, XIX, 253, 268.


60. James C. Carter, Province of the Written and Unwritten Law, p. 9.


61. "The Latin group and the German group (which we shall combine here for

brevity under the name of 'continental') admit the existence of law beyond

the sphere of positive law; that is to say, they accept the existence of

jural relations, although these relations may not have been validated by the

legislator. Formerly these factual relations were evolved out of human

nature (natural law); today they are predicated on conscience and public

opinion which furnish the elements necessary for their support." Alejandro

Alvarez, "New Conception and New Bases of Legal Philosophy," Wigmore

Celebration Legal Essays (Chicago, 1919), pp. 29, 30.


62. Boistel, op. cit., secs. 1, 2. "The natural-law school seeks an

absolute, ideal law, natural law ... by the side of which positive law has

only secondary importance. The modern philosophy of law recognizes that

there is only one law, the positive law, but it seeks its ideal side and its

enduring idea." Berolzheimer, System der Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie,

II, 17.


63. Cf. Zeitschrift fur Rechtsphilosophie, I, 4.



                       PART V


    SIGNIFICANCE OF THE REVIVAL OF HIGHER LAW
   CONCEPTS IN THE PUBLIC LAW OF EUROPE AND OF
                       AMERICA


                    CHAPTER XII


 OBJECTIVES IN THE MODERN REVIVAL OF NATURAL LAW
                      THINKING


THOUGH no effort has been made to review any but a few of the many

indications of the revival of natural law theories or of other types of

higher law notions, sufficient evidence has been given to show that the

return to these concepts, as criteria to measure the justice or validity of

civil enactments, is more than a casual phase of current legal thought. Many

factors are combining to bring to the fore again some of the ideas involved

in the ancient doctrines of natural law. With widely differing purposes in

view and with varying approaches to the fundamental and permanent principles

of the law, legal philosophers, jurists, and judges, in applying concrete

formulae of written charters, codes, or statutes, are wont to turn to

modernized versions of the law of nature or of its counterpart, the law of

reason.[1] It is obvious of course that there are many thinkers in all

countries who deny that there is such a thing as natural law with anything

more than moral import, and who doubt the possibility of any such thing as a

true philosophy of law. This point of view is so well known and is so

general in legal thought that it seems unnecessary to elaborate on it in a

treatise the object of which is primarily to indicate the significance of

opposite opinions.


Among some of the prevailing tendencies in legal thinking which are giving

an impetus to the revival of higher law theories are: first, the efforts to

introduce in a more direct way ethical concepts into the law; second, the

attempts to formulate ideal or philosophical standards to measure positive

laws; third, the establishment of criteria for judges and administrators

when they act as legislators; fourth, a justification for limits on the

sovereignty of states. Each of these modern applications of natural law

concepts deserves brief consideration.


1. Natural Law as a Device to introduce Ethical Concepts into the Law. It is

apparent that natural law thinking has served many purposes in the process

of the evolution of legal systems. None of these purposes has been more

constant and influential than the effort to infuse ethical concepts into the

practical application of the law by means of natural law principles. Every

stage in legal evolution bears witness to the close relation between law and

morals and not infrequently the law of nature served as a convenient

connecting link. A reference to the stages of legal history previously

outlined will indicate some of the obvious relations between these concepts.


In primitive legal systems law and religion were inseparably combined. As

law and religion came to be distinguished, law remained organically

associated with morals and ethics. It was customary for the Greeks and the

Romans to identify jurisprudence with inquiries as to the right and the just

by nature and there was no disposition to separate law and morals. The

identification of the legal with the moral prevailing at this time and the

combination of both in the natural law concepts gave a turn to legal

speculation which has influenced the growth of the law in many of its

subsequent stages.[2]


During the Middle Ages law was merely a branch of theology and was

necessarily associated with moral and ethical thinking. With the Reformation

came one of the first efforts to separate jurisprudence and theology, but

even then law was considered as intimately connected with moral ideas. And

this connection continued until the beginning of the nineteenth century.

Kant broke away from the ideas of natural law prevalent in the eighteenth

century, but he conceived of natural law in the form of eternal and

immutable principles as standards to guide the processes of law making and

law-enforcement.[3] The cycle through which man has passed in working out

the relations of law and ethics is characterized by Dean Pound as the

"ethical-philosophical natural law" of the Romans, the

"authoritative-theological natural law" of the Middle Ages, the

"rational-ethical natural law" of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries,

the "metaphysical natural law" of Kant, to the repudiation of all theories

of natural law by the Analytical School. Thus, he observes,


    the cycle is complete. We are back to the state as the
    unchallengeable authority behind legal precepts. The state
    takes the place of Jehovah handing the tablets of the law to
    Moses, or Manu dictating the sacred law, or the Sun-god
    handing the code to Hammurabi. Law is law by convention
    and enactment -- the proposition, plausibly maintained by
    sophists, which led Greek philosophers to seek some basis
    that made a stronger appeal to men to uphold the legal order
    and the security of social institutions.[4]


The historical school of jurists and the exponents of the positivist

theories of jurisprudence sought a complete separation of law and morals.

The ethical and moral ideas of earlier times which were translated into

effective legal norms were to be replaced either by customs and principles

of action which emanated from the sentiments of the people of a given time

and locality,[5] or rules of action formulated by a political sovereign

which became intrinsically just by the acceptance and promulgation of the

state.[6] Analytical jurisprudence, especially as defined in England and in

America, carried to the extreme the attempt to separate ethics and law.

Exponents of this school believed that the great gain which jurisprudence

made during the last century was the recognition of the truth that the law

of the state is not an ideal, but something which actually exists. Law, they

maintained, is not that which is in accordance with religion or nature or

morality; it is not that which ought to be, but that which is. Justice

Holmes expressed the prevailing sentiment among analytical jurists when he

favored banishing from the law every word of moral significance and

suggested that in so doing "we should lose the fossil records of a good deal

of history and the majesty got from ethical associations, but by ridding

ourselves of an unnecessary confusion we should gain very much in the

clearness of our thought."[7]


As a matter of fact the point of view of the analytical jurists did not

result in banishing the ethical and moral elements in the administration of

justice but only attempted to conceal the process with "dogmatic

fictions."[8] Ethical concepts seemingly excluded from the judicial

processes were extensively used by English and American judges in molding

the ancient rules and principles of the common law to meet new conditions

and in the application of standards in which the moral and ethical elements

played a not insignificant part.[9] Though the followers of John Austin,

such as J. G. Holland, still insist that in England law and morals must be

distinctly separated, the following statement will suffice to show the

contrast between the profession and the practice in emphasizing the judge's

function in translating into law the customary ideas of ethical conduct:


    It is the peculiar characteristic of the English system, and of
    systems derived from it, that the judges, though historically
    and technically the servants of the state, and bound to
    enforce its commands, have almost from the first also played
    the important part of educating the community in the ethics
    of social conduct. And in that part they have drawn their
    inspiration, not from abstract and possibly, unpractical
    ideals, but, by an almost imperceptible process of
    abstraction and development, from the solutions arrived at
    by the better members of the community of the many
    problems of practical life. This is, I think, the inward
    meaning of their frequent appeals to the example of the
    "reasonable man," that favorite objective standard of the
    English judge. With unwearying patience, ingenuity, and
    unsparing labor, our judges have, if I may so put it, woven
    into the national, that is, the political life of the community
    that instinct of justice, that respect for ethical considerations,
    which, if it be not presumptuous for an Englishman to say so,
    is one of the most conspicuous as well as one of the most
    honorable and abiding features of the English character.[10] 


The disposition to consider the close relationships of law and ethics even

in countries where the analytical or positivist theory has prevailed is

indicated in the opinion of a great English justice. After defining law in

the ordinary sense as rules of conduct laid down by the sovereign will of

the state and enforced by the sanction of compulsion, Lord Haldane observes:


    Law, however, imports something more than this. As I have
    already remarked its full significance cannot be understood
    apart from the history and spirit of the nation whose law it is.
    Moreover, it has a real relation to the obligations even of
    conscience, as well as to something else which I shall
    presently refer to as the general will of society. In short, if its
    full significance is to be appreciated, larger conceptions than
    those of the mere lawyer are essential; conceptions which
    come to us from the moralist and the sociologist, and
    without which we cannot see fully how the genesis of law
    has come about. That is where writers like Bentham and
    Austin are deficient. One cannot read a great book like the
    "Esprit des Lois" without seeing that Montesquieu had a
    deeper insight than Bentham or Austin, and that he had
    already grasped a truth which, in Great Britain at all events,
    was to be forgotten for a time.[11]


He then refers to rules of conduct which, so far as the citizen is

concerned, are regulated only to a small extent by law and legality on the

one hand, and by the dictates of individual conscience on the other (a field

which corresponds to the German Sittlichkeit) the system of habitual or

customary conduct, ethical rather than legal, which embraces all those

obligations of the citizen which it is "bad form" or "not the thing" to

disregard. In this field the guide to which the citizen mostly looks is the

standard recognized by the community, an illustration of "a sanction which

is sufficient to compel observance of a rule without any question of the

application of force. This kind of sanction may be of a highly compelling

quality." Attention is then directed to the gradual evolution of an

international Sittlichkeit which promises a sanction for international

obligations not yet fully recognized by formal laws and treaties.[12] Many

others who approach the law from the analytical or positivist point of view

agree with Judge Dillon that "ethical considerations can no more be excluded

from the administration of justice than any one can exclude the vital air

from his room and live."


The Philosophical Schools of jurists, on the other hand, have always

emphasized the close relations between law and morals, and hence have found

as a rule a place for natural law theories. Legal philosophy on the

Continent is often closely related to metaphysical and theological thinking

wherein law, morals, and religion are inseparably associated. Even when

legal philosophers have succeeded in divorcing law from its former

metaphysical and theological bearings they have conceived of an ethical

basis for all law.[13] Thus Stammler and Kohler, as well as Duguit, Krabbe,

and Del Vecchio, subsume an ethical basis for the rules of right or

principles of justice to which all true law must conform.


The different schools of jurists, it is claimed, were looking at distinct

elements of what is called law. The analytical jurist turned his attention

almost exclusively to the fixed body of rules applied by the official organs

of the state. The historical jurist placed uppermost the mass of traditional

ideas and customs from which actual legal rules are derived. The

philosophical jurist emphasized a third element, the social and ethical

ideas which are involved in legal rules and by means of which the law is

being constantly remolded. "The philosophical jurist," says Dean Pound,


    has called this third element "natural law" and has given us a
    theory of all law on the basis thereof. The historical jurist has
    called the second element "custom" and has given us a
    theory of all law on that basis. The analytical jurist has
    sought to treat the second and third elements as but sources
    from which legal precepts are made, but which themselves
    are no part of the law, and so has given us a theory of law
    exclusively in terms of the first element.[14]


The historical jurists, with their emphasis upon the customs and conventions

of the people and upon the process of finding the law through a search among

such customs and conventions, were superseded by the school of analytical

jurisprudence which directed its attention primarily to statutes and to the

interpretation of law by the courts. Coincident with the rise of the

Analytical School came the era of prolific law-making when most legal

thinking was turned into the channels of the verification of facts, of

experimental methods of trial and error, and of an examination for legal

purposes of a minutiae of data. Thus with the triumph of the latter school

emphasis was directed from rules, principles, and universal formulae to a

congeries of facts and conditions to which law was to be made to conform.

The search for principles was tabooed as was also, in certain quarters, the

study of comparative law. What was thought to be necessary was to discover

from the mass of data available what legal corrective was desired and then

to have the sovereign make a rule accordingly which ipso facto became the

law for the time being until changed by the same sovereign. That the

analytical jurists over-emphasized the passing and conventional and failed

to take due account of certain other vital factors in evaluating the legal

process became more apparent as this point of view was formulated into a

recognized system of jurisprudence. The extreme theories of this school have

augmented the reaction which is leading jurists again to turn their

attention to principles and to rules which are of more than passing

moment,[15] and to the necessity of establishing closer relations between

ethics and law.


2. Natural Law as an Ideal or Philosophical Standard. Beginning at least

with the Greeks and the Romans natural law was thought of as an ideal or

philosophical standard toward which temporary enactments or ordinary civil

laws were to approximate. Similar use was made of the concept during the

Middle Ages. And it is an ideal standard to which appeal may be made when

other sources failed to give justice that judges and jurists frequently

referred to natural law, natural justice, and natural rights. There are

times, as in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, when natural law as

an ideal was subordinated to certain fixed and immutable conceptions of law

and right, but these were only temporary deviations from the main purpose of

natural law ideas. For centuries law was liberalized chiefly "by a juristic

doctrine that all legal institutions and all legal rules were to be measured

by reason and that nothing could stand in law that could not maintain itself

in reason."[16] The use of natural law as a standard to guide law in its

progressive development is again receiving serious consideration. Law must

take its bearings from the ethical standards of justice. This gives rise to

certain requirements, as, for example, equality before the law, which

involves the idea of fair play. Speaking of the attempts to put in

opposition to positive law, the law of nature in the seventeenth and

eighteenth centuries, Sir Paul Vinogradoff suggests that "unless I am much

mistaken we witness another wave of this kind in our own time."[17] During

ancient and mediaeval times, he observes, two purposes of natural law were

gradually evolved, one in which it served a theoretic foundation for

axiomatic truths from which a rational system of positive law could be

derived. According to this purpose existing legal rules were accepted as

manifestations of permanent legal principles. On the other hand, the concept

was used as a critical standard to distinguish between reasonable and

unreasonable rules. It was used by Rousseau and Kant to serve as a

philosophical basis for revolutionary ideas. Modern exponents of the law of

nature, such as Charmont, Saleilles, and Stammler recur to natural law as a

critical standard. The new natural law is regarded as a pervasive method by

the help of which rules of law are to be criticized and estimated. Thus the

evolution of natural law has been influenced by the tendency toward the

scientific treatment of social life in distinction from the rationalistic

individualism of the eighteenth century. The problem today is regarded as

one of ascertaining certain standards of social value, and in this process

the new natural law takes a prominent place, not as a fixed and immutable

standard as of the eighteenth century, but as a standard which changes to

suit the conditions of various races and divergent times and conditions.


There is a better appreciation today of the fact that in certain divisions

of the law there are few rules and that judicial decisions are based chiefly

on standards and degrees.[18] The application of such phrases as those of

"fair conduct" in the case of a fiduciary, "due care" in the law of

negligence, "good faith" and "fair competition" in business transactions,

"reasonable facilities" in furnishing public utility services, "fair return"

on property invested in a business, and, "due process of law" in depriving

an individual of life, liberty, and property are well-known illustrations of

the method of determining rights on the basis of standards rather than

rules. In cases involving such concepts the judge must form his own standard

and measure the degree of agreement or variation of conduct with the

standard. "He must balance all his ingredients, his philosophy, his logic,

his analogies, his history, his customs, his sense of right, and all the

rest, and, adding a little here and taking out a little there, must

determine, as wisely as he can, which weight shall tip the scales."[19] Some

of these standards found their way into the law through the frank

recognition of natural law theories.[20] And there are abundant indications

that natural law methods of thinking are conditioning their application in

various branches of modern law.


Instead of seeking a law of absolute significance, modern jurists find in

natural law an ideal with changing content which furnishes a standard to

test what is theoretically and practically just under certain given

conditions.[21] This natural law is regarded as "an idealized ethical custom

and an ideal picture of the end of law, painted, it may be, with reference

to the institutions and ethical customs of the time and place, which may

serve as an instrument of shaping and developing legal materials and of

drawing in and fashioning materials from outside of law."[22]


We are witnessing, then, the rehabilitation of natural law theories, not as

a formal part of positive law, but as conceptions wielding influence on the

opinions of judges and legislators.[23]


Some modern commentators on French law admit that from the standpoint of

philosophy the jurists have always distinguished natural law from positive

law but they join the critics in denying the practical efficacy of natural

law theories. Referring to the contention that natural laws consist of rules

which emanate directly from God and form the source and sanction of all

civil enactments and quoting French authors who deny the existence of such a

priori rules, G. Baudry-Lacantinerie and M. Houques-Fouciade observe


    that this latter notion of natural law appears to us the only
    one admissible and it is to this which we would turn if it were
    absolutely necessary to make a place in juridical science for
    the idea of such a law. Natural law comprises then all of the
    rules consecrated or not by positive law, for the observance
    of which in a given society, it will be desirable that man be
    restrained by the means of exterior coercion. It will be, then,
    according to the changes in current opinion, susceptible of
    variation in the time and place, with the constitution itself of
    the society envisaged. But the name "rational law," or even
    theoretic or ideal law, appears to us better than the term
    "natural," which is affected often by the metaphysical
    conception associated with it. In other terms this law would
    be, as we see it, perfect law in opposition to necessarily
    imperfect law established by positive legislation. This
    approaches very nearly to the view of M. Huc, who defines
    natural law as "the law such as it ought to be according to
    the improvements recognized necessary and possible."[24]


Throughout legal history certain periods have been characterized by emphasis

upon particular phases of the growth of the law. There were times when law

was thought of primarily as an ideal of reason and of truth whether its

source was conceived to be divine or human. Law to be real, effective, and

in any sense permanent, had to accord, in a measure at least, with these

ideas or ideals. At other times law was conceived largely as a growth. Law

was thought to be the creation of the national consciousness or of the

spirit of the people. Evidences of it were to be found in the customary

habits of the people. And at such times it was regarded as the sole duty of

the state to discover and enforce these customary rules. Law has also been

considered as the will of a determinate group in any political society -- in

an ultimate sense the will of a sovereign. From this point of view it was

authority or force not truth or justice which made law. There has been an

age-long antagonism between the advocates of law as an emanation from

authority or force and law as an embodiment of truth and justice. Political

thought has varied as one or the other of these conceptions prevailed.


During the past century there has been an increasing tendency to revert to

the force theory as a basis for law. But the work of the supposed omnipotent

sovereigns has failed to meet with popular approval and has turned public

activities too frequently into the direction of discord and strife to

receive anything like universal assent. Once more the seers and the prophets

are inclined to assert that law is not force, nor is it merely growth from

customary habits, but it is right reason, as discovered from the nature of

man himself, and that law to be in accord with reason must be found by

rational processes based on the experience of man in his social

relationships.[25] Thus we are called upon to return to the ancient

landmarks -- to natural law as an ideal standard as conceived by the Greeks

and Romans. The law as idea is again to take a foremost place in the

lawmaking processes. But law as force and law as growth from customary

conduct may be used as supplementary concepts. "Logic, and history, and

custom, and utility, and the accepted standards of right conduct," it is now

affirmed, "are the forces which singly or in combination shape the progress

of the law."[26]


Vinogradoff suggests that what is needed in contrast with the analytical

jurisprudence of the Austinian type or of the older Naturrecht or historical

type is a "synthetic jurisprudence" which takes into consideration the

various factors which contribute to the making and enforcement of a rule of

law.[27] And the Austinian School was not able to discard law as idea or the

concepts of natural law. In fact, the Analytical School, though formally

repudiating natural law, has been influenced at all times by an anonymous

natural law in the form of ethical views as to what is fair and just.

Positivists do not in fact deny that moral ideas influence the law; they

merely contend that ethical rules of conduct are not law until they receive

the approval of the lawmaking or law-enforcing agents of the sovereign.

Ethical views are always "streaming into the law through all the human

agencies that are connected with it, judges and jurists as well as legislature

and public opinion. Indeed the body of the law could not maintain itself if

it did not conform in large measure to the prevailing sense of justice."[28]


When an estimate is made of the elements of a legal system the laws and the

decisions of a given period are found to be transitory. Conditions arise

which constantly require new rules and regulations. The element which

endures in the system is the professional ideals of the legal order -- a

body of philosophical, political, and ethical ideals as to the purpose of

the law.[29] To understand a legal system it is more important to discover

and evaluate these ideals than minutely to analyze the rules of positive

law. For the ideals which are set as the goal not only determine the trend

of legal development but also result in the formulation of new legal rules

and standards. The antipathy to legislation which is a fundamental principle

of the common law,[30] applied in an environment where ideals of government

limited in behalf of individual liberty, and of a philosophy of economic and

political laissez faire prevailed, gives a clue to many features of American

constitutional law. The doctrine of implied limitations on legislatures and

the extension of the meaning of due process of law may be traced to legal

attitudes compounded from such ideals and accentuated by their application

to pioneer conditions.


3. Higher Laws to guide Judges as Legislators. Modern exponents of natural

law theories reject the mechanical notion of the place and function of the

judge whereby he is expected merely to seek and apply predetermined rules

and is not permitted to mold the law in the course of his application of

these rules. They believe that whether legal traditions admit it openly or

conceal the practice judges necessarily take a prominent part in the

lawmaking process as they adapt legal rules to the unusual conditions of

concrete cases. They maintain that "the judge who would think and act

rightly in his function of rendering judgment must be able, as far as

inelastic provisions of the statute do not prevent him, to discover in the

law and make effective that which he himself, if placed in the situation of

the parties, would feel right and just."[31]


In countries where the civil law prevails the question as to the practice of

free legal decision arises in connection with the requirement that the

judges render a decision as to the rights of the parties when no code

provision or statutory rule is applicable. The French Civil Code makes it

compulsory that the judge decide the issue under such circumstances[32] and

other nations have followed the French practice. Modern codes in Continental

Europe make the duty of judges in this regard more specific, as may be seen

in the Swiss, Austrian, and Italian systems.[33]


Though the instances may be infrequent when the judge lacks guidance from

the statute or the code and is called upon in his capacity as judge to act

as a legislator, the principle is well established in European countries

that when occasion arises he should not shirk the responsibility. It is then

that he is to be guided by the customary conduct of reasonable men.[34] The

statute for the Permanent Court of International Justice also authorizes the

justices to apply "the general principles of law recognized by civilized

nations" along with international conventions, international custom,

judicial decisions, and the teachings of publicists.[35]


In Anglo-American jurisdictions the conflict between the mechanical theory

and the theory of free legal decision has been waged over the relation of

the judges to public policy and over the nature and scope of judicial

legislation. Those who support the mechanical theory hold that it is not the

function of the judge to make or to change the law.[36] This theory refuses

to recognize anything but formulated legal rules and the facts and the

circumstances of a specific case. The advocates of mechanistic ideas in the

United States have become the supporters of the eighteenth-century dictum

that the ideal to seek is "a government of laws and not of men" and they

deprecate the tendency to depart from definite legal rules in the

administration of justice. They see grave dangers in the theory of free

legal decision and oppose the modern tendencies to increase the range of

discretion of judges. They believe that the human element is an undependable

thing in administering justice and that little discretion should be given to

the judges and even then carefully defined limits should be placed on its

exercise. The judge is lauded who aims to arrive by a rigidly mathematical

process at the "inherently and necessarily just."[37]


The common law system is largely a product of judge-made law.[38] And, as we

have seen, concepts of the law of reason or law of nature have had a large

place in the development of various branches of the common law.[39] The

fiction that the judges find the law and apply it in a mechanical or

slot-machine fashion cannot have been taken seriously by the judges and must

have been recognized as having a thin veneer of truth by those not versed in

legal lore. At least the proponents of the fiction are becoming less and

their avowal of the automaton function of the judge is not so insistent. But

more significant is the frank recognition of the duty of judges in common

law jurisdictions to assist in the lawmaking processes. "The system of law

making by judicial decisions which supply the rule for transactions closed

before the decision was announced," Justice Cardozo thinks,


    would be indeed intolerable in its hardship and oppression if
    natural law, in the sense in which I have used the term, did
    not supply the main rule of judgment to the judge when
    precedent and custom fail or are displaced. Acquiescence in
    such a method has its basis in the belief that when the law
    has left the situation uncovered by any pre-existing rule,
    there is nothing to do except to have some impartial arbiter
    declare what fair and reasonable men, mindful of the habits
    of life of the community, and of the standards of justice and
    fair dealing prevalent among them, ought in such
    circumstances to do, with no rules except those of custom
    and conscience to regulate their conduct.[40]


While there are many opportunities for the influence of personality and of

individual views on economics and social policy in the realm of private law

through the development of the common law and through the interpretation of

statutes, there is a much larger range for free legal decision in the main

branches of public law. And this range has been greatly extended in American

constitutional law where wide latitude has been assumed in the

interpretation of such doctrines as implied limitations on legislatures, due

process of law, vested rights free from legislative interference, equal

protection of the laws, and the phrases "the nature of republican

government" and "the spirit of the constitution."[41] Moreover, the judges,

in interpreting the provisions of American constitutions, formerly had no

guidance from precedents or established rules and, directed by their own

reason, they reached conclusions largely controlled by the influences,

opinions, and prejudices to which the justices had been subjected.[42]


President Roosevelt in December, 1908, observed:


    The chief law makers in our country may be, and often are,
    the judges, because they are the final seat of authority. Every
    time they interpret contract, property, vested rights, due
    process of law, liberty, they necessarily enact into law parts
    of a system of social philosophy; and since such
    interpretation is fundamental, they give direction to all law
    making. The decisions of the courts on economic and social
    questions depend upon their economic and social
    philosophy.[43]


In the terms of the theory of free legal decision, the law is, as a justice

of the Supreme Court aptly called it, "a progressive science" in which it is

the duty of judges to foster and direct the process of growth. And it is the

business of judges by so-called "constructive decisions" to see that the law

is made to accord with that somewhat uncertain and elusive thing known as

"the prevailing morality or strong and preponderant opinion."[44] In this

view it becomes the function of the judges to legislate and to be guided by

public policy -- in fact, to see that the law accords with the dominant

social and political doctrines.


The result in a large number of cases cannot be reached, it is contended, by

a strict and logical application of a constitutional text, but instead the

courts must decide upon the basis of external facts of which judicial notice

is taken. Much depends on the extent to which such facts are recognized and

considered. Moreover, where the words of the Constitution, such as "due

process of law" have no technical significance and the judges must seek a

conclusion without definite guidance, "the meaning given to such words is

necessarily influenced by all that makes up in any fundamental way the

thoughts of those who are to find the meaning."[45]


In many cases arising in public law in the United States justices are called

upon to apply indefinite terms which have political and economic

significance and it is here that the personal element or free decision

chiefly enters. Evidences of personal opinions are particularly found when

courts deal with such matters as the reasonableness of building regulations,

public utility regulations, the wholesomeness of foods, public purpose for

taxation, and public use for eminent domain. In an extensive review of some

of these cases Professor Barnett observes, "there is certainly no principle

of law whatever to be found in this mass of contradictions. In fact, courts

simply deem it proper to review legislative decisions in the case of some

statutes, and improper to do so in case of others."[46]


It is evident that free legal decision plays an important rôle in the

decisions of judges applying the general terms of written constitutions. At

no point has free decision been more frequently called into service than in

the interpretation of the phrases "due process of law" and "equal protection

of the laws," whereby much of the old natural rights philosophy has been

injected into the Constitution. And remarkable consequences have resulted

from the enlargement of the meaning of these terms by decisions which had

the effect of constitutional amendments. For fundamental social policies

have been formulated by the judges and have been declared to be a part of

the fundamental law, hence impossible to change except through the difficult

process of amendment. Whenever judges attempt to measure the standards of

justice of positive laws or to fill the gaps in enacted law they turn to

doctrines of natural right or natural law or to general principles of right

for which objective validity is claimed.


Referring to the interesting theories of the law of nature, and the tendency

of the Analytical School of jurists to discredit such ideas, Justice Cardozo

says,


    recent juristic thought has given it a new currency, though in
    a form so profoundly altered that the old theory survives in
    little more than name. The law of nature is no longer
    conceived of as something static and eternal. It does not
    override human or positive law. It is the stuff out of which
    human or positive law is to be woven, when other sources
    fail.[47]


As he views the trend of the times, the exponents of the new natural law and

of the modern philosophy of law are joining in the efforts to discover the

elements of the just in and beyond the positive law.[48] Justice Cardozo

maintains he is not


    concerned to vindicate the accuracy of the nomenclature by
    which the dictates of reason and conscience which the judge
    is under a duty to obey, are given the name of law before he
    has embodied them in a judgment and set the imprimatur of
    the law upon them. I shall not be troubled if we say with
    Austin and Holland and Gray and many others that till then
    they are moral precepts, and nothing more. Such verbal
    disputations do not greatly interest me. What really matters
    is this, that the judge is under a duty, within the limits of his
    power of innovation, to maintain a relation between law and
    morals, between the precepts of jurisprudence and those of
    reason and good conscience.[49]


In the opinion of Sir Frederick Pollock natural law will have a large and

dominant part in the development of whole branches of modern law, as for

example, in the efforts of legislatures and courts to restrict unfair

methods of competition and unfair restraints of trade. Speaking of the

misconception of the law of nature which was current in the eighteenth and

nineteenth centuries, Pollock says,


    the law of nature is not competent to resolve specific
    problems offhand. Neither, for that matter, are the general
    principles of any other science. The law of nature is not the
    chaos of individual opinions but the tradition of universal
    reason confirmed by the general custom of civilized
    mankind.... Natural justice founded in reason is verified by
    the use of just men, is recognized and applied by judicial
    authorities no less than the rules of international law, which
    ultimately rest on the same ground.[50]


If it is the customary morality of right-minded men and women which the

judges are to enforce, natural law standards as conceived by them and as

developed by the scholars and commentators, will serve as an invaluable

guide.[51]


4. Higher Law Theories as a Basis for Limits on State Sovereignty. The

revival of theories of natural law or of natural rights is receiving aid

from divergent currents of political and social life. Among these currents

one which tends to place limits on the omni-competence of the state and to

discredit the traditional theories of state sovereignty leads directly

towards theories of higher laws. For centuries political rulers and certain

schools of jurists looked upon the state as the exclusive lawmaking agency

and the dictum of Hobbes that no law made by the state can be unjust[52] was

generally accepted despite the continuous undercurrents in opposition.

Theories of state omni-competence and of the absolutist dogmas of

sovereignty which came in their wake evolved from conditions which were

unfavorable to the support of limits on public authorities.[53]


The extremes in theory and practice to which the adherents of state

omni-competence went have brought a reaction in a well-defined trend of

political thinking. "The notion of sovereignty must be expunged from

political theory,"[54] says one of the foremost opponents of the traditional

dogmas of state sovereignty.


Most opponents of the doctrine of state sovereignty contend that no such an

independent and supreme power exists in any political society; that the

unity and all-inclusiveness claimed for this power is, in fact, broken by

the divided allegiance which men give to the various social groups to which

they belong; that state authority applies to only a small part of human

conduct, and that this authority is subject to certain definite limitations,

even within this restricted field.[55]


Critics of former theories of sovereignty appear to be seeking certain

fundamental principles as the basis of political obligation. Whether the

source and sanction of political control be sought in a sovereign, in some

kind of general will or social force, or simply in the rule of the majority,

there is an insistent demand for some criterion to pass on the efficacy or

validity of political acts. Such criteria were found formerly in the theory

of natural rights and in the theory of a social compact.[56]


The recent extraordinary enlargement of state functions requires that the

sovereign, if there be such, in many of its activities must be subjected to

certain rules of law. At the same time a similar growth of international

rules and practices requires further limitations on the sovereign, according

to other legal rules. From the standpoint of those interested in the growth

of international law the traditional theory of sovereignty is condemned as a

political dogma no longer in harmony with the facts of international life

and "incompatible with the existence of a society of states governed by a

recognized and generally observed system of international law."[57] If the

sovereign be made subject to a developing body of rules of law in both

private and public law, the theory of an absolute sovereign has ceased to

have its former all-inclusiveness. Older theories of sovereignty which still

retain feudal and monarchic characteristics are apparently in need of

revision. "A certain tendency to discredit the state is now abroad. The

forces which combine to spread this tendency are various. There is the old

doctrine of natural rights, which lies behind most of the contemporary

movements that advocate resistance to the authorities of the state."[58]


According to Duguit the notion of sovereignty is merely a survival of the

conception of the princely state. "By denying the personality of the state,

the sovereignty," he claims, "we disengage ourselves from a valueless and

meaningless anthropomorphism and we reject absolutely all the remaining

balance of the feudal and princely conception of the state."[59]


Following a period of emphasis upon law as an emanation from a sovereign

authority and upon rights as created by such an authority there is a

reversion again to the inherent rights of the individual and to the

necessity of the protection of these rights. This recurrence to the natural

rights of the individual renders it imperative once more to seek limits to

the competency of the political powers of the state or to find ways of

placing restrictions on the presumed sovereignty of the state. Two

well-known English political thinkers, who approach the matter from

different points of view, may be referred to as indicating in their works

the intention to revive interest in natural rights. "I have," Mr. Laski

urges, "rights which are inherent in me as a member of society; and I judge

the state, as the fundamental instrument of society, by the manner in which

it seeks to secure for me the substance of those rights.... Rights, in this

sense, are the groundwork of the state. They are the quality which gives to

the exercise of its power a moral penumbra. And they are natural rights in

the sense that they are necessary to the good life."[60] Laski believes that

a creative view of politics begins in a proper theory of rights. He outlines

a functional theory whereby the individual as a person has rights which the

state does not create but must recognize in order that the individual may

realize his best self. Among the inherent rights of the individual which it

is the duty of the state to preserve and protect, he enumerates the right to

work, the right to be paid an adequate wage, and to have reasonable hours of

work, the right to an education, and the right to participate in the

functions of government.


To give vitality to these views it is necessary to insist that there are

limits to the exercise of public authority and hence he believes any working

theory of the state must concern itself with the efforts to devise limits

upon those who exercise powers. The modern concept of an unlimited and

relatively absolute sovereign is therefore incompatible with the

preservation of these natural rights and in his judgment the concept should

be discarded.[61]


Dealing with the same problem from the standpoint of jurisprudence rather

than political theory, Sir Paul Vinogradoff raises the inquiry whether

"certain fundamental rights and claims ought not to be treated as inherent

in the nature of a freeman and a citizen."[62] Showing that to a

considerable extent the appeal to natural and imprescriptible rights was

made in the eighteenth century in the struggle for freedom of conscience

against state absolutism in religious matters, Vinogradoff affirms: "It is

of great importance to ascertain that there are claims of right which flow

naturally from the conception of human personality as a free agent and as

entitled in normal circumstances to certain legal guarantees of the

realization of welfare."[63]


Even the great advocate in France of the supremacy of the state, M. Esmein,

admitted that the individual had rights anterior and superior to those of

the state, which must be respected by the state. As an essential element of

constitutional law this principle forbids the sovereign from interfering

with individual rights and requires it to take the necessary steps to

preserve such rights.[64]


Formerly international law recognized states as sovereign and subject only

to those limitations to which they had consented. Now, it is contended,

international law must be reconstructed on a new basis.[65] Advocates of

this reconstruction discard at the outset the concept of the state with its

absolute sovereignty, as a metaphysical abstraction. The old law of nations

which was regarded as nothing more than regulations between states is to be

replaced by a new law conceived as existing above states. "The final triumph

of the new conception of international law will be assured," thinks N.

Politis, "because of the irremediable ruin which results from the other

fundamental principle of the classical doctrine, that of sovereignty."[66]

The concept of sovereignty is held to be inadmissible and the state is

regarded as not invested with absolute power but as charged with a social

mission which requires that its actions be controlled by rules of law

(droit). One of the most direct attacks on the older concepts of sovereignty

is made in the interest of the establishment of a secure basis for

international law.[67]


5. Limits on the Power to amend Constitutions in America due to Fundamental

Principles and Rights. A renewal of efforts to revive a type of higher law

philosophy is found in the attempts in American political thinking to place

certain limits on the power of the people to amend written constitutions.

Amending procedure in the United States was left largely to political

control and direction until toward the close of the nineteenth century.

Judicial control over the process of amending state constitutions was

asserted only once prior to 1880.[68] The next few decades witnessed not

only an increasing exercise of the right of judicial control over amendments

but also the gradual emergence of a distinction between amendments and

additions. Justice Story had suggested the notion of inherent limits on the

power of amendment under the federal Constitution when, referring to the

adoption of the Constitution by the people, he said: "The Union which is

perfected by means of it is indissoluble through any steps contemplated by,

or admissible under, its provisions or on the principles on which it is

based, and can only be overthrown by physical force effecting a

revolution."[69] Following this view it was not infrequently asserted that

no amendment could be made which would lead to the destruction of either the

Union or the states, or that amendments interfering with the sovereignty

either of the states or the nation would be void. Justice Cooley, the

foremost advocate of the doctrine of implied limitations on legislatures in

order to protect vested rights, believed that there are certain inherent

limitations -- principles which underlie the federal Constitution and which

prevent its radical amendment. Amendments, he insisted, "cannot be

revolutionary; they must be harmonious with the body of the instrument."[70]

But in a practical, concrete way little significance was attached to this

idea until the extension of judicial review of legislative enactments

provided a convenient method to apply limitations to the amending

process.[71] Thus it became customary to assert that amendments were invalid

which contravened the general principles of free republican government, that

interfered with the natural rights of life and liberty, or that took away

fundamental rights of either the nation or the states.


The attempt to apply the doctrine that there are limits to the amending

power under the federal Constitution have arisen primarily in the enactment

and interpretation of the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth

Amendments[72] and have acquired greater significance in the movement to

hold ineffective the Eighteenth Amendment. The attack on the Civil War

Amendments on this ground have not been so persistent and vigorous because

these amendments were regarded mainly, in their original purpose, as

declaratory of the natural rights of man.[73]


In the briefs on the cases before the Supreme Court attacking the validity

of the Eighteenth Amendment a special effort was made to revive Story's

notion of implied limits on the amending power by arguments based upon the

nature of the federal system.[74] Elihu Root argued that "any amendment

which impairs or tends directly to destroy the right and power of the

several states and of local self-government should be held void as in

conflict with the intent and spirit of implied limitations of the federal

Constitution adopted by the people of the United States."[75] It was also

claimed that certain principles of the Constitution are unamendable and as

an example due process of law was cited as a matter so vital to free

government that it may not be destroyed. The Supreme Court substantially

rejected all of the arguments presented in favor of such limitations, but

the issue has not been dropped in federal constitutional law and the

advocates of these doctrines have turned to the states where a more fruitful

field is open for the application of implied limits on legislative and

constituent powers.


A significant attempt is being made to revive interest in the philosophy and

dogmas of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries in support of the view

that indubitable private rights must be preserved, anything in laws or

constitutions to the contrary notwithstanding. Mr. Abbot, defender of this

return to natural and inalienable rights, asserts "the indisputable truth is

that there are rights which no government can lawfully invade. The man who

does not believe in them does not understand the difference between right

and wrong, does not understand human nature, and does not learn from

experience." He thinks the protection of these inalienable and reserved

rights is to be preserved under the inexpugnable law of the land, or due

process clause. There is, he insists, no power resident anywhere in the

Union which can overturn this constitutional principle. "There are," he

comments, "a number of constitutive principles of private right which have

been so wrought into the fabric of our institutions that they cannot be

abrogated." Among these indubitable rights he suggests the use of the

natural powers in the pursuit of happiness as long as they do not thereby

injure others, and the right of hearing when a man's liberties are at stake;

and he concludes that "we find in this country, at least, it is held to be

axiomatic, that there are limitations to the power of all government and if

so, there are limitations to the power of amending the Constitution of the

United States."[76]


The doctrine of higher law or of fundamental principles as a basis for

limits to be applied to the amending procedure of the federal Constitution

is seldom advocated. American legal thought more commonly follows the

doctrine that there are no inalienable rights, that legal rights exist only

through law, and that such a thing as a right in any legal sense against the

sovereign political authority is unthinkable. From this viewpoint unlimited

sovereignty resides only in the people.[77] It is well to recognize,

however, that the doctrine of limitations on the power of the people to

amend constitutions is much more commonly accepted than is ordinarily

believed, that it is a factor not to be ignored in constitutional

interpretation, and that when ostensibly repudiated as a legal doctrine it

has found its way in judicial decisions in covert processes of legal

reasoning.[78]


With the extraordinary growth of the functions of government during the last

century, and with a corresponding increase in the number of public officials

who are engaged in carrying on these functions, has come a confirmed

conviction that some limits must be set to the activities of these

functionaries. Jefferson's observation that many despots in a legislative

assembly are more to be feared than one has not ceased to gain converts as

governments have become increasingly popular in origins and sanctions.[79]

It was to be expected that laissez faire exponents of the eighteenth and

early nineteenth centuries would seek to limit governmental functions, to

divide public powers, and to favor a refined system of checks and balances.

It is more difficult to understand why the advocates of popular government

and of the extensions of its functions along all lines should at the same

time be concerned with fixing limits to the exercise of these functions.


This effort to define the field within which the public officers are

permitted to function has two significant phases -- one designed to keep

officers near to and responsive to public sentiment and to guard certain

personal rights and privileges from official encroachment, and another, a

direct result of former laissez faire theories, which is designed to prevent

the public from invading the individual and corporate rights and privileges

of property and contract. The latter forms the basis for the protection of

acquired or vested rights. The first of these phases is exemplified

especially in the growing tendency to formulate as a part of the public

fundamental law bills or charters of individual rights which are regarded in

varying degrees as inviolable. In this respect the Declaration of

Independence, the bills of rights in the state and federal constitutions of

the United States, and the French Declaration of the Rights of Man began a

movement which has influenced greatly the entire process of the development

of constitutional law.


The other phase of the movement, the disposition to use higher law ideas to

protect acquired or vested rights was a gradual development in connection

with the emergence of constitutional government. It has had a unique

application in the "United States where property owners and corporate

organizations have been accorded greater privileges than in any other

country. These privileges are protected by an independent judiciary

upholding the limitations of a written constitution and of higher laws above

the constitution.[80]


6. Concluding Comments. Duguit would have all law conform to an objective

right,[81] and other Frenchmen plead for the renaissance of natural law, now

a term conceived as involving fundamental principles changing in content and

significance with each generation.[82] Krabbe would have all law conform to

the community sense of the feeling for right.[83] The gap is not so great

after all between the broad rule of reason applied by American justices

permitting only those things which do not "shock men's sense of right" and

the concepts of higher law now prevalent on the continent of Europe. But it

is a different matter for a rule of reason, an objective right, or a feeling

for right to form the basis of legal reasoning of justices or of the

observations of legal philosophers instead of a more or less mechanical

measure to test the validity of legislation. The United States is

practically alone in placing super-censors over its legislative chambers

with often nothing more than the elusive rule of reason as a standard.[84]


Throughout the evolution of the law there has always been a disposition to

seek for law in sources external to man and his lawmaking and law-enforcing

agencies. If the law itself is not regarded as originating in such external

sources there has been an urgent desire to discover standards outside of the

law, or as a significant part of it, to evaluate its justice and fairness in

determining the legal relations among men.[85] Law is comprised not alone of

rules but of principles, conceptions, and standards. And from the standpoint

of the unity, continuity, and permanence of the law the principles,

conceptions, and standards are more important than the rules.[86] It is in

the former that the ideas involved in the phrase "natural law" are always in

evidence. When the principle is announced that one person is not to be

enriched unjustly at the expense of another, what is unjust enrichment and

by what criterion will such conduct be judged? Similarly, when legislatures

and courts lay down the principle that business competition shall not be

conducted unfairly, what is the standard by which competition is declared

unfair? If unfair competition is anything else than what Judge Hough called

the selling of goods by means that "shock judicial sensibilities,"[87] how

is the line determined between what does and does not shock judicial

sensibilities? What criteria are involved in judgments which insist that the

conduct of a fiduciary shall be fair, that public utilities shall receive a

fair return upon a reasonable valuation of their property, or that

regulations affecting such utilities must be reasonable? The ultimate

standard of what is reasonable or fair is the judicial conscience. But what

are the controlling factors which turn the scales of justice? Evidently

judges, in forming moral judgments on conduct as to whether it is fair or

reasonable, are guided by common sense and intuition based on experience.

The rule of reason which they are constantly applying has a close

resemblance to the ancient and mediaeval concepts of the law of nature,

which were accepted as guiding factors of the English common law in its

"rules of reason."


It is contended that advocates of theories of natural law usually try to

defend certain special interests and that they make their own personal views

the test of the validity of legal precepts. Writers have not infrequently

aimed to project into the realm of universal laws their own personal and

subjective sentiments and it has been difficult to draw a line between such

subjective views and the presumed objective rules to which recurrence is

usually made as having general validity. It is the subjective phases of

natural law theories which are often emphasized to the discredit of all such

theorizing.[88] Though there are many indications in natural law thinking of

frank or covert appeals to higher laws for the sake of expediency, such

instances by no means comprise all of the cases in which superior law

concepts are employed.


Natural law theories seem to be conceived and applied for diverse reasons by

the absolutists, by the individualists, by the pragmatists, and by those

whose legal thinking is inarticulate and subconscious.


From the time men put their thoughts into definite written form there were

some who sought the essential and the real qualities of man's social life in

external sources, such as God or nature. From this external source come

certain absolute ideas or standards which can be comprehended by human

thought. Those who find it convenient and comforting to anchor their

thinking in concepts of an absolute are likely to conceive as a part of such

an absolute certain of the directive principles of social control by means

of law. The search for absolute ideas in connection with law as in the field

of religion may be inspired by quite divergent motives. But the religious

and metaphysical approaches to philosophy frequently lead in the direction

of a natural law with absolute connotations.


Starting with an assumption that men lived originally in a state of nature

which was governed by the laws of nature, the individualists found a basis

for law and rights in the inherent qualities which belonged to men as

individuals and as social beings. Doctrines of freedom and equality and of

rights to live, possess property, and enjoy certain privileges unmolested

were supposed to flow from the conditions of birth and habitation in an

environment subject to the laws of nature.


In the United States, where the individualistic viewpoint has been a

dominant factor of political and social life, the doctrine of equality has

resulted in three claims: that all men ought to be equal before the law,

ought to have equal privileges of participation in political affairs, and

ought to have equal opportunities. Though these claims have come far from

practical realization, they have affected all phases of social and political

life and have been reflected in numerous statutes and judicial decisions.

The pronouncement in the Fourteenth Amendment that no person shall be denied

the equal protection of the laws is the fruition of more than a century of

equalitarian theories and of higher law ideas which accompanied them.[89]


The pragmatists' approach to natural law needs little comment. Lawmaker or

judge, finding the formal rules of the law unjust in their applications,

appealed to a higher law of reason or of nature as his guide to secure a

more rational and equitable result. Or, perchance, a group of individuals

chafing under the dominion of men guided by laws or personal whims sought in

the laws of nature a sanction for resistance to the established order and

ultimately for rebellion. Thus the anarchists turned to natural law to

sanction opposition to all forms of political authority at the same time

that individuals and corporations sought support for the protection of their

vested interests in the same law. The fact that natural law ideas can be

turned to so many different uses weakens their efficacy when urged for any

specific purpose.


The most difficult of all phases of the natural law philosophy to understand

and evaluate is its inarticulate and unconscious or subconscious use.[90] As in the development of the common law, the thinking of

lawyers and judges may be saturated with an unexpressed and unexplained

philosophy which is none other than natural law. Or American judges

revolting against the indefinite and vague terms "natural law" and "natural

justice", may find a haven in due process of law, which is little else than

a natural law given constitutional sanction -- with the same vagueness and

uncertainty inherent in the standard phrases. The assumptions, the

principles, and the philosophies with which legal controversies and the

devices for their settlement are approached are often more significant than

the formal rules available for application.[91] In such assumptions,

principles, or philosophies, one or more of the natural law theories is

likely to lurk beneath the formal expressions and to determine partially at

least the trend of legal judgments. It is the unexpressed and undefined

natural law notions which may serve as a potent weapon to liberalize the

law, as was the case with the evolution of English equity, or it may serve

as a more sinister weapon when it is championed as a means of sustaining the

legal status quo.


Along with the attitude of certain minds to search for ideals and to think

in terms of universals there is the related habit of human thought to

translate familiar and accepted ideas into the necessary and natural.[92]

And another tendency of the human mind which leads in the direction of

natural law theories is suggested in some remarks of Justice Holmes.

Speaking of "The Lantern-Bearers" of Robert Louis Stevenson, in which he

shows how in their hearts all men are idealists, Holmes says: "The same laws

are found everywhere, and everything is connected with everything else; and

if this is so, there is nothing mean, and nothing in which may not be seen

the universal law."[93]


The claim that natural law theorists are merely assuming universal or

general validity for their own subjective ideas of justice and rights by no

means accounts for the assumptions, preconceived notions, or principles

which have been associated with the natural law concept. Law in its generic

sense is conceived as "the sense of justice taking form in peoples and

races" and in the formation of men's ideas of justice there are some rules

and principles which are thought to have universal validity.[94] It matters

little whether these principles result from the instinctive, romantic, or

religious sentiments of the people, or from the dominant juristic

conceptions of a community such as the Anglo-Saxon fundamental principles of

justice, or the principles which lie at the basis of free government, or

from the free decision of justices applying the ethics and juristic ideas of

certain classes -- there is for any time and place a uniformity in the

application of these principles which gives them a singular permanence and

definiteness. It makes a great difference in the results for the development

of the law whether these principles or norms are treated as relative and

variable or absolute and unchangeable;[95] whether they are applied by

judges and legislators in a formalistic and mechanical way as determinate

norms for the measurement of conduct or are used to test existing rules of

law by standards of fairness and justice, which are constantly being

subjected to critical analysis and modification by the legal profession; and

whether they are employed as a means of legal growth or of the maintenance

of a sanctified legal order.




1. "It is not an accident that something very like a resurrection of natural

law is going on the world over" Roscoe Pound, in Harvard Law Review, XXV

(December, 1911), 162; also Sir Paul Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law, p.

246.


2. Roscoe Pound, Law and Morals (2d ed. Chapel Hill, 1926), Lecture I, "The

Historical View." Dean Pound has dealt so fully with the relations of law

and morals in this series of lectures that only a summary of certain phases

of this relation need be considered.


3. Cf. Kant, Metaphysische Anfangsgrunde der Rechtslehre (1797).


4. Pound, op. cit., pp. 12-14.


5. Pound claims that the historical jurist merely indicated a new basis for

natural law in insisting on universal ideal principles to which positive law

must conform. Op. cit., p. 21.


6. John C. Gray, The Nature and Sources of the Law (2d ed ), p. 94.


7. Collected Legal Papers (New York, 1920), p. 179.


8. Pound, op. cit., pp. 56, 57.


9. See illustrations of the close relations of law and morals in Pound, op.

cit., Lecture II, "The Analytical View."


10. Edward Jenks, "The Function of Law in Society," Society of Comparative

Legislation and International Law, 3d ser., vol. V, Pt. IV (1923), pp. 176,

177.


11. Lord Haldane, "Higher Nationality: A Study in Law and Ethics," American

Bar Association Reports, XXXVIII (1913), 402, 403.


12. Lord Haldane, op. cit., pp. 403-405, 413. Sitte generally refers to

custom -- Sittlichkeit implies custom and a habit of mind and action.


13. Pound, op. cit., p. 103. Coleman Phillipson suggests that "natural law,

in spite of its being frequently maligned and scoffed at, will continue to

hold the minds of men as long as men remain psychologists and moralists."

Great Jurists of the World, p. 306


14. Op. cit., pp. 23-25.


15. Evidences of the new point of view are at hand even in countries where

the Analytical School has been strongest, such as the movement in the United

States directed by the American Law Institute to extract principles of law

from the welter of statutes and decisions and the efforts now participated

in by all of the leading countries to secure a codification of international

law.


16. Pound, The Spirit of the Common Law, p. 81.


17. Sir Paul Vinogradoff, "Legal Standards and Ideals," Michigan Law Review,

XXXIII (November, 1924), 1 ff. For reference by the same writer to the

revival of a modified conception of the law of nature as one of the

significant currents of thought in jurisprudence, see Historical

Jurisprudence, I, 144, 145.


18. Benjamin N. Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process (New Haven,

1922), pp. 161, 162.


19. Cardozo, op. cit., p. 162.


20. See Pound, Law and Morals, p. 60.


21. Stammler, Wirthschaft und Recht (2d. ed.), p. 181, and Lehre von dem

Richtigen Recht (Berlin, 1902), pp. 116-121; Saleilles, "L'École historique

et droit naturel," Revue trimestrielle de droit civil, I, 80, 98; R.

Demogue, Notions fondamentales du droit privé, p. 22.


Vinogradoff characterized this phase of natural law thinking as follows:

"The law of nature is an appeal from Caesar to a better informed Caesar. It

is an appeal by society at large, or by the best spirits of a given society,

not against single decisions or rules, but against entire systems of

positive law. Legislators are called in to amend law by separate statutes;

judges may do a great deal in amending the law by decisions in individual

cases, but the wisdom of legislators and equity of judges are by themselves

powerless against systems, because they start from the recognition of the

authority of positive law in general. And yet law, being a human

institution, ages not only in its single rules and doctrines, but in its

national and historical setting, and the call for purification and reform

may become more and more pressing with every generation. Public opinion,

then, turns from reality to ideals. Speculation arises as to the essentials

of law as conceived in the light of justice. Of course these conceptions of

justice are themselves historical, but they are drawn not from the

complicated compromises of positive law but from the simpler and more

scientific teaching of philosophical doctrine. Thus the contents of the law

of nature vary with the ages, but their aim is constant; it is justice; and

though this species of law operates not in positive enactments, but in the

minds of men, it is needless to urge that he who obtains command over minds

will in the end master their institutions." Common Sense in Law, pp. 244,

245. See also, by the same author, "Reason and Conscience in Sixteenth

Century Jurisprudence," Law Quarterly Review, XXIV (October, 1908), 379.


22. Pound, Law and Morals, p. 113.


23. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law, pp. 235 ff., and Central Law Journal,

LXXX (May, 1915), 346.


24. Traité théorique et pratique de droit civil, I (3d ed., 1907), 5.


25. Cf. Joseph H. Drake in editorial preface to Del Vecchio, Formal Bases of

Law, P. 28.


26. Cardozo, op cit., p. 112.


27. Custom and Right (Cambridge, 1925), pp. 12, 13.


28. M. R. Cohen, "Jus Naturale Redivivum," Philosophical Review, XXV, 761,

762.


29. Pound, "The Theory of Judicial Decision," Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI (April,

1923), 661.


30. Idem., "Common Law and Legislation," Harv. Law Rev., XXI (April, 1908),

403.


31. Gmelin, The Science of Legal Method (Boston, 1917), p. 89; for a

thorough discussion of the function of the judge as a lawmaker, see other

selections in this volume. Cf. also my article on "General Observations on

the Effects of Personal, Political, and Economic Influences in the Decisions

of Judges," Illinois Law Review, XVII (June, 1922), 96. In the following

pages a few extracts are used from this article.


32. Art. 4 of the Civil Code provides that "le juge qui refuse de juger sous

prétexte du silence, de l'obscurité ou de l'insuffisance de la loi, pourra

être poursuivi comme coupable de déni de justice."


33. The pertinent provisions of these codes are:


    The statute governs all matters within the letter or the spirit
    of any of its mandates. In default of an applicable statute, the
    judge is to pronounce judgment according to the customary
    law, and in default of a custom, according to the rules which
    he would establish if he were to assume the part of a
    legislator. He is to draw his inspiration, however, from the
    solutions consecrated by the doctrine of the learned and the
    jurisprudence of the courts. Swiss Civil Code, art. 1.


    Should the case, however, remain doubtful, it shall be
    decided in accordance with the law of nature and with due
    regard to the circumstances of the case diligently collected
    and thoroughly considered. Austrian Civil Code
    Introduction, secs. 6-8.


    When a case, however, remains doubtful, one ought to
    decide according to the general principles of law, taking into
    account all of the circumstances of the controversy. Italian
    Civil Code, 1866, sec. 3.


In discussing the language of the Italian code the question arose whether to

use the phrase "following the principles of natural law" or "following

general principles of law."


Other phrases suggested were "principles of reason," "principles of equity,"

"principles of natural equity," "principles of natural reason." The general

principles of law were referred to as those rules which reason deduces from

the nature of things and from their reciprocal relations. Giorgio Del

Vecchio, Sui principi generali del diritto (Modena, 1921), pp. 9, 10.


34. See Cardozo, op. cit., p. 106.


When positive laws are silent or vague Stephen suggests that judges may

decide "according to the natural reason of the thing"; Geny would have them

render judgment according to the "nature of positive things"; and Pollock

would have them follow the "ideal standard of scientific fitness and

harmony."


The will of the state, expressed in decision and judgment, says Gmelin, is

to bring about a just determination by means of the subjective sense of

justice inherent in the judge, guided by an effective weighing of the

interests of the parties in the light of the opinions prevailing among the

community regarding transactions like those in question. And Geny recommends

that, on the one hand, we are to interrogate reason and conscience, to

discover in our inmost nature, the very basis of justice; on the other, we

are to address ourselves to social phenomena, to ascertain the laws of their

harmony and the principles of order which they exact. Sociological Method,

trans. Modern Legal Philosophy Series, IX, 131. Geny, Méthode

d'interprétation et sources en droit privé positif, II, 92.


35. Cf. art. 38 and Procès-verbaux of the Proceedings of the Advisory

Committee of Jurists, pp. 281 ff. These principles were not formulated or

defined but were thought to be founded on "the fundamental law of justice

and injustice deeply engraved on the heart of every human being and which is

given its highest and most authoritative expression in the legal conscience

of civilized nations." M. le Baron Descamps, Procès-verbaux, pp. 310, 311.


36. According to Elihu Root the appeal to courts in the matter of social

reform rests upon a misconception of the true function of a court. It is

not within the judge's function or within his power to enlarge or improve or

change law. The Independent, LXXII (April 4, 1912), 704; James Coolidge

Carter, Law: Its Origin, Growth and Function (New York, 1907), pp. 172, 173.

For opposite view, see John F. Dillon, The Law and Jurisprudence of England

and America, p. 267.


37. E. V. Abbot, Justice and the Modern Law, pp 10 ff.


38. A. V. Dicey, Lecture on "Judicial Legislation," in Lectures on the

Relation between Law and Public Opinion in England during the Nineteenth

Century (London, 1926), pp. 359, 360.


39. Supra, pp. 39 ff.


40. Op. cit., pp. 142, 143.


41. Justice Cardozo thinks that in the field of constitutional law in the

United States the method of free decision is dominant today. Op. cit., p.

17. Agreeing with this view Judge Bruce says, "we are governed by our judges

and not by our legislatures.... It is our judges who formulate our public

policies and our basic law." The American Judge (New York, 1924), pp. 6-8.


42. W. D. Coles, "Politics and the Supreme Court of the United States,"

American Law Review, XXVII (March-April, 1893), 189, 190.


43. Emphasizing the same thought at a dinner to Justice Harlan after

twenty-five years' service on the Supreme Bench, President Roosevelt said:

"For the judges of the Supreme Court of the land must be not only great

jurists, but they must be great constructive statesmen, and the truth of

what I say is illustrated by every study of American statesmanship, for in

not one serious study of American political life will it be possible to

omit the immense part played by the Supreme Court in the creation, not

merely the modification, of the great policies through and by means of which

the country has moved on to her present position." Amer. Law Rev., XXXVII

(January-February, 1903), 93.


44. Noble State Bank v. Haskell, 219 U. S. 104, 111 (1911).


45. W. F. Dodd, "The Problem of State Constitutional Construction," Columbia

Law Review, XX (June, 1920), 636.


46. James D. Barnett, "External Evidence of the Constitutionality of

Statutes," Amer. Law Rev., LVIII (January-February, 1924), 88.


47. Op. cit., pp. 131, 132.


48. Cardozo, op. cit., p. 132, and Berolzheimer, System der Rechts- und

Wirtschaftsphilosophie, II, 27.


49. Cardozo, op. cit., p. 133.


50. Review of Professor Brown's International Society: Its Nature and

Interests, Law Quar. Rev., XXXIX (1923). "The best and most rational portion

of English law is in the main judge-made law. Our judges have always shown,

and still show, a really marvelous capacity for developing the principles of

the unwritten law, and applying them to the solution of questions raised by

novel circumstances." Pollock, Law Quar. Rev., IX (April, 1893), 106.


"The besetting danger of modern law," to Pollock, "is the tendency of

complex facts and minute legislation to leave no room for natural growth,

and to choke out the life of principles under a weight of dead matter which

posterity may think no better than a rubbish heap." The Expansion of the

Common Law, p. 8.


51. Cardozo, op. cit., p. 106. "Another significant current of thought

connected with the evolutionist movement in jurisprudence may be seen in the

revival of a modified conception of the law of nature -- not in the

rationalist sense, of course, but in that of a striving toward ideals. If,

as Ihering put it, law has not only to register actual rules and to explain

their origin, but also aim at the solution of social problems, it is not

wrong or presumptuous to reflect on the general principles which in the

present state of civilization we ought to accept as the guiding lights for

legislators and reformers, and as the critical tests for approving or

disapproving existing rules of positive law." Vinogradoff, Historical

Jurisprudence, I, 144, 145.


52. Leviathan, chap. 30. For a similar view see John Austin, Lectures on

Jurisprudence or The Philosophy of Positive Law (5th ed., London, 1885), pp.

268 ff.


53. A short summary may be found in F. W. Coker, "Pluralistic Theories and

the Attack upon State Sovereignty," in A History of Political Theories:

Recent Times, edited by Charles E. Merriam and H. E. Barnes (New York,

1924), pp. 81 ff.


54. H. Krabbe, The Modern Idea of the State, trans. by George H. Sabine and

Walter J. Shepard (New York, 1922), p. 35. See also A. D. Lindsay, "The

State in Recent Political Theory," Political Quarterly, I (February, 1914),

128-145.


55. Coker, op. cit., p. 89, and Louis Le Fur, "La souveraineté et le droit,"

Revue du droit public, XXV (1908), 389.


Among the critics of the prevailing doctrines of sovereignty, see Léon

Duguit, Law in the Modern State (New York, 1919); H. Krabbe, The Modern Idea

of the State (New York, 1922); Harold J. Laski, Problem of Sovereignty (New

Haven, 1917); Authority in the Modern State (New Haven, 1919); The

Foundations of Sovereignty and Other Essays (New York, 1921); and Ernest

Barker, "The Superstition of the State," London Times Literary Supplement

(July, 1918), p. 329.


56. "When we turn to history for evidence of the cultural tradition of the

state and of its relation to law, we find the overwhelming weight of

authority opposed to the absolutistic view of sovereignty and of the State

and denying the alleged independence of both from the limitations embodied

in the conception of law." E. M. Borchard, Yale Law Journal, XXXVI, 1039.


57. See Harv. Law Rev., XXXVI (February, 1923), 495; James W. Garner,

"Limitations on Sovereignty in International Relations," American Political

Science Review, XIX (February, 1925), 1; and E. M. Borchard, "Political

Theory and International Law," in A History of Political Theories: Recent

Times (New York, 1924), p. 120.


58. W. Y. Elliot, "Sovereign State or Sovereign Group," Amer. Pol. Sci.

Rev., XIX (August, 1925), 482.


Geny, an advocate of the doctrine of natural rights, regards sovereignty as

a postulate which is contrary to the facts and conditions of social life.

Science et technique en droit privé positif, I, 75.


Surveying the recent progress of political thought in continental Europe,

Vinogradoff suggests that "in modern Europe itself there is a marked

recurrence of the view that the state is subject to the authority of a

higher law. This recurrence may be traced to the wide-spread discontent with

the policies of modern states in championing the interests of economic

imperialism. The theory culminates in the assertion that it is society

which creates law and not the state. Society creates law by developing and

applying certain propositions conceived as reasonable and just. In this

respect it is not reason as given by Providence and not reason given once

for all by human nature, but reason conceived by public opinion and public

morality at a particular time." "The Juridical Nature of the State," Mich.

Law Rev., XXXIII (December, 1924), 138-142.


59 Duguit, Traité de droit constitutionnel, vol. I, chap. 5.


60. A Grammar of Politics (New Haven, 1925), pp. 39, 40.


61. See especially op. cit., chaps. 2 and 3.


62. "The Foundations of a Theory of Rights," Yale Law Jour., XXXIV

(November, 1924), 64.


63. Ibid., p. 67. "As a general conclusion," Vinogradoff asserts, "it may be

said that the will of the state is not the one factor in building up Right

and Law in human society. There is a second factor of equal importance --

the consciousness of men as to their rights. In practice Law appears as a

shifting compromise between these two factors." Ibid., p. 69. At another

time, he defends the main proposition of Duguit's political philosophy in

these words: "The attempt to define the nature of the state in juridical

terms is not a quibble of the lawyers. It is an obvious consequence of the

view that state and government in a civilized country, in spite of their

might have to conform to a rule of law, and that the more closely their

functions are subjected to the application of ordinary legal rules and

methods, the better will be the guarantees against oppression, corruption

and arbitrary measures." Historical Jurisprudence, I, 92.


64. Esmein, Droit constitutionnel (Barthélemy's ed., 1915), pp. 29, 30; also

Duguit, "The Law and the State," Harv. Law Rev., XXXI, 38.


An exponent of the theory that the concept of sovereignty should be

abandoned is Charles Benoist. For a summary of his views see Duguit, "The

Law and the State," op. cit., pp. 171 ff. Benoist became the advocate of a

measure to establish in France a supreme court whose duty it should be to

uphold the constitution and to prevent violations thereof by the legislative

and executive powers. Journal officiel, documents parlementaires, Chambre

1903, session ordinaire, pp. 95, 99.


65. N. Politis, "Les limitations de la souveraineté," Revue de Paris, XXXIII

(March, 1926), 7. Politis is an advocate of the views espoused by Duguit. He

also regards the state as bound by rules of law.


66. Ibid., p. 9.


67. N. Politis, "Le problème des limitations de la souveraineté et la

théorie de l'abus des droits dans les rapports intemationaux," Académie de

droit international, VI (1925), 1-121; also Goicochea, El problema de las

limitaciones de la soberanía en el derecho público contemporáneo (Madrid,

1923).


68. Collier v. Frierson, 24 Ala. 100 (1854), holding that the procedure

defined in the constitution not having been strictly followed, an amendment

approved by the people was invalid. Cf. W. F. Dodd, "Amending the Federal

Constitution," Yale Law Jour., XXX (February, 1921), 321.


69. Story on the Constitution (5th ed by Cooley), I, 223.


70. T. M. Cooley, "Power to Amend the Federal Constitution," Michigan Law

Journal (April, 1893). For Cooley's comments on natural rights see ibid.

(June, 1894).


71. State ex. rel. Halliburton v. Roach, 230 Mo. 408, 130 S. W. 689 (1910),

initiative petition to submit to the people an amendment to the state

constitution was held not to be an amendment but a statutory enactment. The

court passed upon the legal sufficiency of a petition to amend the

constitution. See dissent of Justice Woodson.


72. See Judge M. F. Morris, "The Fifteenth Amendment to the Federal

Constitution," North American Review, CLXXXIX (January, 1909), 82. In the

opinion of Judge Morris a distinction must be made between an addition and

an amendment to the Constitution. An addition, he suggests, requires the

unanimous consent of the states. Ibid., p. 85.


73. Justin Dupratt White, "Is There an Eighteenth Amendment?" Cornell Law

Quarterly, V (January, 1920), 113.


Mr. White contends that, on the general theories assumed as a basis for the

American system of government, intra-state prohibition cannot be the subject

of a valid constitutional amendment, that the consent of the people of all

of the states is necessary for such a change, or that such consent must be

given through conventions called for this purpose in the states. Certain

amendments such as those seeking to reorganize state governments or to

interfere with their vital powers are regarded as improper. All of the

amendments to the federal Constitution prior to the Eighteenth are thought

to be "assertive of those fundamental rights which are the foundation of a

republican form of government." The dictum of Chief Justice Chase in Texas

v. White, 7 Wall. 700, 725 (1868), that "the Constitution in all of its

provisions looks to an indestructible union of indestructible states" is

taken to mean that the federal character of the Union cannot be changed

except by revolution.


74. Cf. Briefs in the case of Rhode Island v. Palmer, pp. 29, 66, and in the

Kentucky Distilleries and Warehouse Co. v. Gregory, 41, and Dodd, op. cit.,

pp. 330 ff.


75. Brief in case of Feigenspan v. Bodine, p. 64. For argument favoring

limitations on the federal amending power see George Ticknor Curtis,

Constitutional History of the United States, II, 160. See George D. Skinner,

"Intrinsic Limitations on the Power of Constitutional Amendment," Mich. Law

Rev., XVIII (January, 1920), 213. Mr. Skinner insists that the Ninth and

Tenth Amendments are unamendable -- that "the essential form and character

of the government being determined by the location and distribution of

powers cannot be changed." Also W. L. Marbury, "The Limitations upon the

Amending Power," Harv. Law Rev., XXXIII (December, 1919), 223. Mr. Marbury

claims that the power to amend does not include the power to destroy the

Constitution nor does it include the power to enact ordinary legislation.

William L. Frierson replied to Mr. Marbury, Harv. Law Rev., XXXIII (March,

1920), 659.


76. E. V. Abbot, "Inalienable Rights and the Eighteenth Amendment," Col. Law

Rev., XX (February, 1920), 183 ff. See also Henry Wynans Jessup, The Bill of

Rights and its Destruction by Alleged Due Process of Law (Chicago, 1927).


77. For the generally accepted theory of American lawyers, see D. O.

McGovney, "Is the Eighteenth Amendment Void because of its Contents?" Col.

Law Rev., XX (May, 1920), 449.


78. See People v. Western Union Co., 70 Col. 90 (1921), and People v. Marx,

70 Col. 100 (1921), for an interesting application of the limits on the

power of the people to amend state constitutions A defence of our natural

and inherent rights for whose security and preservation our government was

instituted, is made by Max Schoetz, "Natural and Inherent Rights protected

by the Fourteenth and Fifteenth Amendments of the Constitution of the United

States," Marquette Law Review, VII (1922-23), 154.


79. A bill of rights, Jefferson observed, "is what the people are entitled

to against every government on earth, general or particular." Letter to

Madison. Dec. 20, 1781.


80. "The whole American political and social system is based on industrial

property right, far more completely than has ever been the case in any

European country." A. T. Hadley, Undercurrents in American Politics (New

Haven, 1915), p. 33. See especially the chapter in this volume on "The

Constitutional Position of the Property Owner."


81. Traité de droit constitutionnel, 1, 16. "It is above all in the

atmosphere of American life," says Mr. Laski, "that the broad accuracy of M.

Duguit's interpretation finds its most striking evidence. The whole

background of American constitutionalism is a belief in the supremacy of

reason." "A Note on M. Duguit," Harv. Law Rev. XXXI (November, 1917), 192.


82. Charmont, La Renaissance du droit naturel and Modern French Legal

Philosophy in Modern Legal Philosophy Series, pp. 106 ff.


83. The Modern Idea of the State, chap. 3.


84. "The test of reasonableness is, of course, one that it is seldom easy

to apply in a court of law. For it always raises issues which in their

nature are ultimately questions of opinion, and it tempts the judge to

believe that he is simply finding the law when in fact he is really testing

and rejecting other men's views by the light of his own. In arriving at the

meaning of this conception, it is therefore urgent for the judge to be

certain that he has surveyed the whole ground." Harold J. Laski, "Judicial

Review of Social Policy in England: A Study of Roberts v. Hopwood et al."

Harv. Law Rev., XXXIX (May, 1926), 832, 842. See (1925) A. C. 578.

"Reasonableness then means not a view arrived at by men who, having taken

steps to inform themselves of the facts relevant to a decision, arrive at a

considered view, but what the courts think they should have come to hold;

and they (local councils) will have to pay out of their personal fortune for

acting upon a faith different from that of the House of Lords." Ibid., p.

845.


85. "'Objective law,' 'social solidarity,' man's 'sense of right,' like

'natural law' which has dominated men's thinking and molded legislative and

judge-made law, are value-standards which embody an implicit dogmatism

transcending experience and expressing both an ideal and the quest for and

supposed need of perfection and the absolute." Borchard, Yale Law Jour.,

XXXVI, 1091.


86. Pound, "The Administrative Application of Legal Standards," Amer. Bar

Assn. Reports, XLIV, 445.


87. Steiff v. Bing, 215 Fed. 204, 206 (1914).


88. Pound, Law and Morals (2d ed.,), pp. 90, 91; Pollock, Essays in the Law,

p. 47.


89. T. V. Smith, "Notes on the American Doctrine of Equality," International

Journal of Ethics, XXXV, 164, 377; XXXVI, 31.


90. Cf. Cardozo, op. cit., p. 167.


91. "Implicit in every decision where the question is, so to speak, at

large," says Justice Cardozo, "is a philosophy of the origin and aim of

law, -- the philosophy which, however veiled, is in truth the final arbiter

... neither lawyer nor judge, pressing forward along one line or retreating

along another, is conscious at all times that it is philosophy which is

impelling him to the front or driving him to the rear." It is in a

situation of this kind that "the personality of the judge, his taste, his

training or his bent of mind, may prove the controlling factor." Harv. Law

Rev., XXXVII (1923), 282; see also The Nature of the Judicial Process, pp.

71, 90.


92. "The jurists who believe in natural law seem to me to be in that naïve

state of mind that accepts what has been familiar and accepted by them and

their neighbors as something that must be accepted by all men everywhere."

Holmes, Collected Legal Papers (New York, 1920), p. 312. "Men in general are

inclined to regard the habitual and the simple as identical with the

necessary, and the natural." N. M. Korkunov, General Theory of Law, trans.

by W. G. Hastings, p. 135.


93. Collected Legal Papers, p. 159. Justice Holmes finds that the jurists'

search for criteria of universal validity usually under the guise of

natural law is the result of a demand for the superlative which is common to

all men. Ibid., p. 310.


94. "Does not the interpretation of the will of the legislature," inquires

Geny, "imply an incessant comparison of the formulae or principles which

express an ideal of justice and of reason, -- formulae which are outside of

and above the law. These superior principles of an immanent right [droit]

play a decisive role in the interpretation of positive laws." Méthode

d'interprétation et sources en droit privé positif (2d ed., Paris, 1919), I,

43 ff.


95. "The sanctification of ready-made antecedent universal principles as

methods of thinking is the chief obstacle to the kind of thinking which is

the indispensable prerequisite of steady, secure and intelligent social

reforms in general and social advance by means of law in particular." John

Dewey, "Logical Method and Law," Corn. Law Quar., X (December, 1924), 27.



BIBLIOGRAPHY


THE bibliography comprises a selected list of books and articles which are

regarded of interest in the evolution of ideas relating to natural law.[1]

As the consideration of natural law in many legal treatises is inseparable

from the treatment of the philosophy of law, certain works are included

which deal primarily with legal philosophy and incidentally consider natural

law. Similarly natural law and the law of nations since the time of Grotius

frequently have been treated together, and titles are included in which

consideration of natural law is incidental to an analysis of international

law. The discussion or exposition of natural law is to be found in so many

treatises and under such diverse headings that it is quite impossible to

give a complete and comprehensive list of titles relating to the subject. As

a rule works which deal primarily with natural laws in the physical sense or

with ethics and morality as separated from legal ideas are excluded. Many of

the works on natural law appeared in numerous reprints and were translated

into foreign languages. Obviously these reprints and translations could not

be included in a selected bibliography.


I am indebted to Mr. John T. Vance, Law Librarian of the Library of Congress

for the privilege of checking a list of about six hundred titles relating to

natural law in its varied ramifications and to the Librarians of the Harvard

Law Library for assistance in using the incomparable resources of that

library. For a guide to foreign titles I received aid from the Catalogue de

la Bibliothèque du Palais de Paix,The Hague, 1916 and 1922.


Abbot, Everett V. Justice and the modern law. Boston and New York, 1913.


-- "Inalienable rights and the eighteenth amendment," Columbia Law Review,

XX (February, 1920), 183.


Abicht, Johann Heinrich. Kurze darstellung des natur- und völkerrechts zum

gebrauch bei vorlesungen. Bayreuth, 1795.


-- Neues system eines aus der menschheit entwickelten naturrechts. Erlangen,

1792.


Achenwall, Gottfried. Prolegomena ius naturae. Göttingen, 1758-74.


Acollas, Émile. Introduction à l'étude du droit. 1885.


-- L'idée du droit. 2d ed. 1889.


Acquisto, B. d'. Corso di diritto naturale o filosofia del diritto. 2a. ed.

Palermo, 1856.


Affolter, A. Naturgesetze und rechtgesetze. München, 1904.


-- "Cathrein: Recht, naturrecht und positives recht" (rezension),

Juristisches Literaturblatt, XIV (1902), 11.


Ahrens, Henri. Cours de droit naturel, ou de philosophie du droit complété

dans les principales matières, par des aperçus historiques et politiques.

Paris, 1838. 8e éd. 2 vols. Leipzig, 1892.


-- Naturrecht oder philosophie des rechts und des staates, auf dem grunde

des ethischen zusammenhanges von recht und kultur. óte, durchaus neu

bearbeitete, durch die staatslehre und die principien des völker rechts

vermehrte, aufl. 2 vols. Wien, 1870-71.


Alengry, Franck, ed. La déclaration des droits de l'homme et du citoyen.

Paris, 1901.


Alonso y Equilaz, J. El derecho natural: exposición de los principios

universales del derecho con aplicación especial a los seres humanos. Madrid,

1870.


Aquilanti, F. Filosofia del diritto. Roma, 1916.


(Aquinas, St. Thomas). Institutiones juris naturalis seu philosophiae

moralis universae secundum principia. Thomae Aquinatis ad usum scholarem

adornavit Theodorus Meyer. Editio altera emendata. Friburgi Brisgoviae,

1906.


Aristotle. Politics, vol. I, chap. 5; (Jowett's trans.), I, 7-8.


Asquini, A. "La natura dei fatti come fonte di diritto," Archivio Guiridico,

vol. LXXXVI (1921), no. 2.


Audisio, Gulielmus. Iuris naturae et gentium privati et publici fundamenta.

Roma, 1852. 4a. ed. Lipsiae, 1868.


Avellar Brotero, J. M. Principios de direito natural. Rio de Janeiro, 1829.


Bachiller y Morales, A. Elementos de la filosofía del derecho o curso de

derecho natural. Habana, 1857.


Barbeyrac (J.). Éléments du droit naturel, par Burlamaqui; et devoirs de

l'homme et du citoyen tels qu'ils lui sont prescrits par loi naturelle;

traduits du Latin de Pufendorf par Barbeyrac, avec les notes du traducteur

et le jugement de Leibnitz. Nouvelle éd. Paris, 1820.


-- Traité du jeu, où l'on examine les principales questions de droit

naturel et de morale, qui ont du rapport à cette matière. 2 vols. Amsterdam,

1709.


Baroli, Pietro. Diritto naturale privato e pubblico. Cremona, 1837.


Bauer, Anton. Lehrbuch des naturrechts. 3te aufl. Göttingen, 1825.


Beaussire, E. La liberté dans l'ordre intellectuel et moral. Études de

droit naturel. Paris, 1866.


Becker, Carl. The Declaration of Independence: A study in the history of

political ideas. New York, 1922.


Beneke, F. E. Grundlinien des naturrechts, der politik und der philosophie.

Berlin, 1838.


Bentham, Jeremy. Principles of morals and legislation. 1780.


Bergbohm, Karl. Jurisprudenz und rechtsphilosophie, vol. I. Leipzig, 1892.


Berolzheimer, Fritz. System der rechts- und wirtschaftsphilosophie. 5 vols.

München, 1904-07. Vol. II of the work translated by R. S. Jastrow as The

world's legal philosophies, Modern Legal Philosophy Series, Boston, 1912.


Beudant, Charles. Le droit individuel et l'état; introduction à l'étude du

droit. 2e éd. Paris, 1891.


Bierling, Ernst Rudolf. Juristische prinzipienlehre. 5 vols. Leipzig,

1894-1917.


Binder, Julius. Rechtsbegriff und rechtsidee: bemerkungen zur

rechtsphilosophie R. Stammlers. Leipzig, 1915.


Bitzer, Friedrich. Das system des natürlichen rechts. Stuttgart, 1845.


Blake, Ralph Mason. "On natural rights," International Journal of Ethics,

XXVI (October, 1925), 86.


Boistel, Alphonse. Cours élémentaire de droit naturel ou de philosophie du

droit, suivant les principes de Rosmini. Paris, 1870.


-- Cours de philosophie du droit professé à la faculté de droit de Paris. 2

vols. Paris, 1899.


Bonatelli, Francesco. Del diritto naturale fondato sull' etica. 1860.


Bonnecase, Julien. La notion de droit en France au dix-neuvième siècle.

Contribution à l'étude de la philosophie du droit contemporain. Paris, 1919.


Bonnin, Charles Jean Baptiste. Traité du droit, contenant les principes du

droit naturel et du droit des nations, pour servir d'introduction à l'étude

des lois et à la connaissance des traités. Paris, 1808.


Bonnuci, Alessandro. La derogabilita del diritto naturale nella scolastica.

1906.


Boucaud, Charles. Qu'est ce que le droit naturel? Paris, 1906.


-- L'idée de droit et son évolution historique. Paris, 1906.


-- Les droits de l'état et les garanties civiques du droit naturel. 1908.


Bourgeois, Léon Victor Auguste. Déclaration des droits de l'homme et du

citoyen 1789, expliquée et accompagnée de lectures. Paris, 1902.


Breuer, Isaac. Der rechtsbegriff auf grundlage der Stammlerschen

sozial-philosophie. Berlin, 1912.


Brini, G. Jus naturale. Bologna, 1889.


Brown, William Laurence. An essay on the natural equality of men; on the

rights that result from it and on the duties which it imposes. 2d ed.

London, 1794.


Brugi, B. "Il periodo del diritto naturale in Germania," Rivista Italiana

per le Scienze Guiridiche (1901), p. 404.


Brunetti, G. "Il diritto naturale nella legislazione civile," Rivista del

Diritto Commerciale, XX (1922), nos. 8, 9.


Brutt, Lorenz. Die kunst der rechtsanwendung. Berlin, 1907.


Bry, G. "De l'idée d'un droit naturel et de son rôle dans la législation

positive," Bulletin du Comité des Travaux Historiques, 1901.


Bryce, James. "The law of nature," in Studies in History and Jurisprudence,

II (Oxford, 1901), 556.


Buddens, J. F. Selecta juris naturae et gentium. Halae Saxonum, 1704.


Burlamaqui, Jean Jacques. Juris naturalis elementa. Geneva, 1754.


Burlamaqui, Jean Jacques. Éléments du droit naturel. Lausanne, 1783.


-- Principes du droit naturel. Geneva, 1747. The principles of natural and

politic law. Trans. by Mr. Nugent. London, 1748. 5th ed. 2 vols. Cambridge,

Mass., 1807.


Burle, E. Essai historique sur le developpement de la notion de droit

naturel dans l'antiquité grecque. Trévoux, 1908.


Calafat León, Juan. Las leyes naturales de la vida aplicadas a la

constitución política de los estados y a la sociedad de las naciones.

Madrid, 1918.


Cappellari, Giovanni. Sulla relazione dell' etica col diritto naturale.

Venezia, 1835.


Cardozo, Benjamin N. The nature of the judicial process. New Haven, 1922.


-- The growth of the law. New Haven, 1924.


Carle, G. La filosofia del diritto nello stato moderno. Torino, 1903.


Carlyle, A. J. and R. W. A history of mediaeval political theory in the

West. 4 vols. New York, 1903-22.


Carreras y Arano, J. Filosofía de la ley según Santo Tomás de Aquino.

Madrid, 1919.


Cassirer, Erich. Natur- und völkerrecht im lichte der geschichte und der

systematischen philosophie. Berlin, 1919.


Cathrein, Viktor. Recht, naturrecht und positives recht. Eine kritische

untersuchung der grundbegriffe der rechtsordnung. 2te aufl. Freiburg im

Breisgau, 1909.


-- "Naturrechtliche strömungen in der rechtsphilosophie der gegenwart,"


Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie, XVI (1922-23), 54.


Caumont, Aldrich Isidore Ferdinand. Étude sur la vie et les travaux de

Grotius, ou le droit naturel et le droit international. Paris, 1862.


Cauvière, Jules Louis Fortune. Un nouveau traité de droit naturel. 1893.


Charmont, J. La renaissance du droit naturel. Montpellier, 1910. Pages

200-216 of this volume translated in Modern French Legal Philosophy, Modern

Legal Philosophy Series, VII (Boston, 1916), 133-145.


Chazelle, Rene. Des garanties données ou à donner au droit naturel de

liberté dans la detention préventive. Thesis. Strasbourg, 1922.


Clark, Andrew Inglis. "Natural rights," Annals of American Academy of

Political and Social Science, XVI (1900), 212-226.


Clay, J. Schets eener kritische geschiedenis van het begrip natuurwet in de

nieuwere wijsbegeerte met eene inleiding omtrent dat begrip bij

voor-christelyke denkers. Leiden, 1915.


Cohen, M. R. Jus naturale redivivum. Reprinted from Philosophical Review,

XXV (1916), 761.


Cordovani, M. "Il diritto naturale nella moderna cultura italiana," Rivista

Internazionale di Filosofia del Diritto, IV (April-June, 1924), 101.


-- Elementa juris naturalis internationalis. Aretii, 1924.


Corwin, Edward S. "The 'higher law' background of American constitutional

law," Harvard Law Review, XLII (December, 1928, and January, 1929), 149,

365.


Cosentini, E. La nuova concezione del diritto naturale. Napoli, 1905.


Cosentini, E. Filosofia del diritto. Torino, 1914. Especially chap. 11 and

bibliography, pp. 218-224.


Cotelle, Louis Barnabe. Abrégé du cours élémentaire du droit de la nature et

des gens par demandes et par réponses. Paris, 1820.


Courcelle, Seneuil J. G. "La doctrine du droit naturel," Le Journal des

Economistes (1891), p. 7.


Cranenburgh, Leonardus Petrus Alphonsus Maria Van. Naturrecht en positief

recht. Dissertation, Amsterdam, 1902.


Cromaziano, Agatopiste. Della istoria critica del moderne diritto di natura

e di genti. Discorsi raccoiti dalla restaurazione di ogni filosofia.

Perugia, 1789.


Cruet, Jean. Étude juridique de l'arbitraire gouvernemental et

administratif. Paris, 1906.


Cumberland, Richard. De legibus naturae. London, 1672.


Dahn, Felix. Die vernunft im recht. Grundlagen der rechtsphilosophie.

Berlin, 1879.


Darjes, Joachim Georg. Institutiones jurisprudentiae universalis in quibus

omnia juris naturae socialis et gentium capita in usum auditorii sui

methodo scientifica explanantur. 3a ed. Jenae, 1748.


-- Observationes juris naturalis, socialis ad ordinem systematis sui

selectae. 2 vols. Jenae, 1753.


Daunou, Pierre Claude François. Essai sur les garanties individuelles. 1818.


De Glinka. Esquisse d'une théorie de droit naturel. Paris, 1836.


Demogue, Rene. Les notions fondamentales de droit privé. Paris, 1911.


Deslandres, M. "Étude sur le fondement de la loi," Revue du Droit Public,

XXVIII (1908), 5.


Deville, Abbé. Le droit canon et le droit naturel; études critiques. Lyon,

1880.


Diels, Hermann. "Ein antikes system des naturrechtes," Internationale

Monatschrift für Wissenschaft, Kunst und Technik, XI (1916), 82. Donati, D.

Il problema delle lacune dell' ordinamento guiridico. Milano, 1910.


Dorlencourt, L. "Le droit naturel," Revue Pratique de Droit Français, IX

(Paris, 1860).


Doumergue, Émile. "Les origines historiques de la déclaration des droits de

l'homme et du citoyen," Revue du Droit Public, XXI (1904), 673.


Dresch, L. von. Naturrecht. Tübingen, 1822.


Dreske, O. Zwingli und das naturrecht. Halle, 1911.


Droste-Hülshoff, Clemens August von. Lehrbuch des naturrechtes oder der

rechtsphilosophie. 2te aufl. Bonn, 1823.


Dubois, Auguste. L'évolution de la notion de droit naturel antérieurement

aux physiocrates. Paris, 1908.


Dugast, L. Les lois sociales devant le droit naturel. Paris, 1899.


Duguit, Léon. Le droit social, le droit individuel et la transformation de

l'état; conférences faites à l'école des hautes études sociales. 2e éd.

Paris, 1911.


Duguit, Léon. L'état, le droit objectif et la loi positive. 2 vols. Paris,

1901.


-- Traité de droit constitutionnel. 2e éd. 5 vols. Paris, 1921-26.


Dyroff, Adolf. "Naturrecht und psychologie," Archiv für Rechtswissen schaft,

XV, 309.


Eckstein, W. Das antike naturrecht in sozialphilosophischer beleuchtung.

Wien, Leipzig, 1926. Bibliography, pp. 119-135.


Egger, F. Das natürliche öffentliche recht nach den lehrsätzen des freiherm

C. A. von Martini vom staatsrechte, mit bestandiger rücksicht auf das

natürliche privatrecht (von) Franz Edlen von Zeiller und auf das positive

europäische völkerrecht. Wien, Triest, 1809-10.


Eggers, Christian Ulrich Detlev. Institutiones iuris civitatis publici et

gentium universalis. Hafniae, 1796.


Ehrlich, E. Freie rechtsfindung und freie rechtswissenschaft. Leipzig, 1903.


Eulenberg, Franz. "Naturgesetze und soziale gesetze; logische

untersuchungen," Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, XXXI, 711;

XXXII, 689, 780 (Tübingen, 1910-11).


Faguet, Émile. Le libéralisme. Paris, 1903.


Felice, Fortuné Barthélemy de. Leçons de droit de la nature et des gens. 4

vols. Yverdon, 1769.


Fernández Concha, R. Filosofía del derecho o derecho natural dispuesto para

servir de introducción a las ciencias legales. 2a ed. 2 vols. Barcelona,

1887-88.


Ferrer Neto Paiva, Vicente. Elementos de direito natural, ou de philosophia

de direito. 2a ed. Coimbra, 1850.


Feuerbach, P. J. Kritik des natürlichen rechts als propädeutik zu einer

wissenschaft der natürlichen rechte. Altona, 1796.


Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. Grundlage des naturrechts, nach prinzipien der

wissenschaftslehre. Jena und Leipzig, 1796-97. Trans. by A. E. Kroeger as

The science of rights, Philadelphia, 1869.


Filomusi-Guelfi, Francesco. Del concetto del diritto naturale e del diritto

positive nella storia della filosofia de diritto. Napoli, 1874.


Finnettus, J. F. De principiis juris naturae et gentium adversus Hobbesium,

Pufendorfium, Thomasium, Wolfium et alios. 2a ed. 2 vols. Venetiis, 1777.


Fischer, Fr. Ueber den gegenwärtigen stand des naturrechts, nebst winken zu

seiner weiterbildung. Basel, 1837.


Fleischer, J. L. Institutiones juris naturae et gentium, in quibus regulae

justi, decori atque honesti potissimum secundum principia Thomasiana

distincte explanantur et applicantur. 2a ed. Halae, Magdeb., 1730.


Fortescue, Sir John. De natura legis naturae.


Foster, C. J. Natural law: A lecture introductory to the course of

Jurisprudence in University College, London. London, 1851.


Foaillée, Alfred. L'idée moderne du droit. Paris, 1878. 7e éd. Paris, 1913.


Frank, Reinhard. Naturrecht, geschichtliches recht und soziales recht.

Leipzig, 1891.


Friters, Alfred. Revolutionsgewalt und notstandsrecht. Rechtsstaatliches und

naturrechtliches. Berlin, 1919.


Fritot, Albert. Cours de droit naturel, public, politique et

constitutionnel. 4 vols. Paris, 1827.


Fuchs, Ernst. Recht und wahrheit in unserer heutigen justiz. Berlin, 1908.


Geny, François. Science et technique en droit privé positif. 4 vols. Paris,

1914-24.


Gerard de Rayneval, Joseph Mathias. Institutions du droit de la nature et

des gens. 2e éd. Paris, 1803.


Gerigh, Hubert. Der irrtum beim ehevertrage nach dem naturrecht. Breslau,

1913.


Gierke, Otto Von. Johannes Althusius und die entwicklung der

naturrechtlichen staatstheorien; zugleich ein beitrag zur geschichte der

rechtssystematik. 3te aufl. Breslau, 1913.


-- Naturrecht und deutsches recht. Frankfurt, 1883.


-- Political theories of the Middle Ages. Trans. by F. W. Maitland.

Cambridge, 1922.


Giese, Friedrich. Die grundrechte. Tübingen, 1905.


Giner, F. Estudios juridicos y políticos. Madrid, 1875.


Giner, F., und Caldron, A. Zur vorschule des rechts: Kurzgefasste

grund-sätze des naturrechts in vorlesungen, frei übersetzt von Karl Röder,

herausgegeben von Paul Hohlfeld und Aug. Wünsche. Leipzig, 1907.


Grabmann, Martin. "Das naturrecht der scholastik von Gratian bis Thomas von

Aquin," Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaffsphilosophie, XVI (1922-23), 12-53.


Grondin, Max. Les doctrines politiques de Locke et l'origine de la

déclaration de droits. Thesis. Bordeaux, 1920.


Gros, Karl Heinrich Von. Lehrbuch der philosophischen rechtswissenschaft

oder des naturrechts. 4te aufl. Stuttgart und Tübingen, 1822.


Grotius, Hugo. De jure belli ac pacis. Paris, 1625. Grotius' work appeared

in many editions.


Guelfi, F. Filomusi. Del concetto del diritto naturale e del diritto

positive nella storia della filosofia del diritto. 2a ed. Roma, 1909.


Guillemon, Pierre. De la rebellion et de la résistance aux actes illegaux.

Thesis. Bordeaux, 1921.


Gundling, N. H. Jus naturae ac gentium connexa ratione novaque methodo

elaboratum. Ed. nova. Genevae, 1751.


Gunnerus, Johann Ernst. Vollständige erläuterungen und anmerkungen über das

natur- und völkerrecht des Herrn Hofrath Darjes. Frankfurt und Leipzig,

1748.


Gutberlet, Konstantin. Ethik und naturrecht. 1883. 3te aufl. 1901.


Gysin, Arnold. "Die lehre vom naturrecht bei Leonard Nelson und das

naturrecht der aufklärung," Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphil osophie,

XVII (Berlin, 1924).


Haines, Charles Grove. "The law of nature in state and federal judicial

decisions," Yale Law Journal, XXV (June, 1916), 617.


Hägermann, Gustav. Die erklärungen der menschen- und bürgerrechte in den

ersten americänischen staatsverfassungen. Berlin, 1910.


Haghette, E. Déclaration des droits de l'homme. 1900.


Haldane, Lord. Higher nationality: a study in law and ethics. American Bar

Association Reports, XXXVIII, 1913.


Haring, Johann Baptist. "Zur neueren naturrechtslehre," Theolog. Prakt.

Quartalschrift, LXXV (1922), 209, 384.


Hauriou, M. "Le droit naturel et l'Allemagne," Le Correspondant (Sept. 23,

1918), pp. 913-939.


Haus, J. J. Elementa doctrinae juris philosophicae sive juris naturalis.

Gandavi, 1824.


Haymann, F. Kants kritizismus und die naturrechtlichen strömungen der

gegenwart; festrede der zweihundertjähriger wiederkehr des geburts tages von

Immanuel Kant gehalten am 8. marz 1924 in der juristischen gesellschaft in

Köln. Berlin, 1924.


-- "Naturrecht und positives recht," Zeitschrift für Rechtsphilosophie in

Lehre und Praxis, I (Leipzig, 1914), 233.


Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Grundlinien der philosophie des rechts oder

naturrecht und staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Trans. by S. W. Dyde as

Hegel's philosophy of right, London, 1896.


Heineccius, Johann Gottlieb. Elementa juris naturae et gentium, commoda

auditoribus methodo adornata. Halae, 1738.


-- A methodical system of universal law; or, The laws of nature and nations

deduced from certain principles, and applied to proper cases. Trans. by

George Turnbull. To which is added, a discourse upon the nature and origin

of moral and civil laws. 2 vols. London, 1763.


Hemming, Nic. de. De lege naturae. Viteb., 1564.


Hennebicq, L. Philosophie du droit et droit naturel. Bruxelles, 1897.


Herbart, J. F. Analytische beleuchtung des naturrechts und der moral, zum

gebrauch beym vortrage der praktischen philosophie. Göttingen, 1836.


Hertling, Georg Graf v. Naturrecht und sozialpolitik. 1897.


Heydenreich, Karl Heinrich. System des naturrechts nach kritischen

principien. 2te aufl. 2 vols. Leipzig, 1801.


Hinrichs, H.F.W. Geschichte des natur- und völkerrechts. Leipzig, 1848-52.


Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. 1651.


-- Elements of law, natural and politic. Edited with notes by Ferdinand

Ronnies. London, 1889.


Hocking, William Ernest. Present status of the philosophy of law and of

rights. New Haven, 1926.


Holder. Allgemeine grundsätze des natürlichen staatsrechts. Berne, 1863.


Hoffbauer, Johann Christoph. Naturrecht aus dem begriffe des rechts

entwickelt. Mersburg, 1825.


Holaind, René Isidore. Natural law and legal practice. New York, 1899.


Holberg, L. de. Einleitung in des natur- und völkerrechts, aus dem

danischen. Hafn., 1748.


Höpfner, Ludwig Julius Friederich. Naturrecht des einzelnen menschen, der

gesellschäften und der völker óte aufl. Frankfurt und Leipzig, 1792.


Hübner, Martin. Essai sur l'histoire du droit naturel. 2 vols London

1757-58.


Huebner, Margarete. Untersuchungen über das naturrecht in der

altchristlichen literatur, besonders des abendlandes vom ausgange des 2.

jahrhunderts bis Augustin. Dissertation, Bonn, 1918.


Hufeland, Gottlieb. Lehrsätze des naturrechts und der damit verbundenen

wissenschaften zur vorlesungen. Jena, 1790. 2te aufl. Frankfurt und Leipzig,

1795.


Hugo, Georg. Lehrbuch des naturrechts als einer philosophie des positiven

rechts, besonders des privatrechts. Berol, 1798.


Huit, C. La philosophie de la nature chez les anciens. Paris, 1901.


Hurlbut, Elisha P. Essay on human rights and their political guaranties. New

York, 1850.


Huygens, E. Le droit naturel et les lois. Gand, 1904.


Ihering, Rudolf von. Der kampf urn's recht. 18te aufl. Wien, 1913.


-- Der zweckim recht. Leipzig, 1877-83. 2 vols. 4te aufl. Leipzig, 1923.

Trans. by Isaac Husik as Law as a means to an end, Modern Legal Philosophy

Series, vol. V (Boston, 1913). Institutes du droit naturel privé et public

et du droit des gens, par M. B. 2e éd. 2 vols. Paris, 1876.


Jakob, L. H. Philosophische rechtslehre oder naturrecht. Halle, 1795.


Jellinek, Georg. The declaration of the rights of man and of citizens: a

contribution to modern constitutional history. Trans. by Max Farrand, New

York, 1901.


-- Die erklärung der menschen- und bürgerrechte. Ein beitrag zur modernen

verfassungsgeschichte. 3te aufl. München, 1919.


-- Das recht des modernen staates. Berlin, 1900.


-- Die sozialethische bedeutung von recht, unrecht und strafe. 2te aufl.

Berlin, 1908.


Jessup, Henry Wynans. The bill of rights and its destruction by alleged due

process of law. Chicago, 1927.


Jodi, F. "Ueber das wesen des naturrechts und seine bedeutung in der

gegenwart," Juristische Viertrljahrschrift, XXV (1893).


Jouffroy, H. Catéchisme de droit naturel à l'usage des étudiants en droit.

Leipzig et Paris, 1841.


Jouffroy, Theodore S. Cours de droit naturel. 2 vols. Paris, 1834-35. 5e éd.

Paris, 1876.


Jung, Erich. Das problem des natürlichen rechts. Leipzig, 1912.

Bibliography, pp. 330-334.


Kant, Immanuel. Die metaphysik der sitten; metaphysische anfangsgründe der

rechtslehre. 2d ed. 1798. Trans. by W. Hastie as The philosophy of law: an

exposition of the fundamental principles of jurisprudence as the science of

right. Edinburgh, 1887.


Kantorowicz, Hermann U. Zur lehre vom richtigen recht. Berlin und Leipzig,

1909. Katholische rechtsphilosophie: Das naturrecht im geschichte und

gegenwart, XVI (1922-23). Articles by various authors.


Kelsen, Hans. Hauptprobleme der staatsrechtslehre, entwickelt aus der lehre

vom rechtssatze. 2te aufl. Tübingen, 1923.


-- Der soziologische und der juristische staatsbegriff: kritische

untersuchung des verhältnisses von staat und recht. Tübingen, 1922.


"Naturrecht und positives recht," Revue Internationale de la Théorie du

Droit, II (1927-1928), 71.


Klein, E. F. Grundsätze der natürlichen rechtswissenschaft nebst einer

geschichte derselben. Halle, 1797.


Kloverkorn, Fritz. Zur entstehung der erklärung der menschen- und

bürgerrechte. Berlin, 1910.


Koehler, Heinrich. Juris socialis et gentium ad ius naturale revocati

specimina VII. Jenae, 1737.


-- Juris naturalis, ejusque cumprimis cogentis methodo systematica propositi

exercitationes VII. Frankfurt, 1738.


Kohler, Josef. Lehrbuch der rechtsphilosophie. Berlin und Leipzig, 1909. 2te

aufl. Berlin, 1917. Trans. by A. Albrecht as Kohler's philosophy of law,

Modern Legal Philosophy Series, Boston, 1914.


-- "Das naturrecht in der prozesswissenschaft," Archiv für Rechts- und

Wirtschaftsphilosophie, I, 503.


-- "Fichtes naturrecht," Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie,III,

172.


-- "Die spanischen naturrechtslehrer des 16 und 17 jahrhunderts," Archiv für

Rechts und Wirtschaftsphilosophie, X, 235.


-- Moderne rechtsprobleme. 2te aufl. Leipzig und Berlin, 1913.


-- Das recht. Frankfurt, 1909.


-- Recht und persönlichkeit in die kultur der gegenwart. 1914. Kohler, W.

Geist und freiheit: allgemeine kritik des gesetzesbegriffes in natur- und

geistewissenschaft. Tübingen, 1914. Korkunov, N. M. Cours de théorie

générale du droit. Trad. par Schernoff, Paris, 1903; also trans. by Hastings

as General theory of law, Modern Legal Philosophy Series, Boston, 1909.


Krabbe, H. Die lehre der rechtessouveränität. Gröningen, 1906.


-- Die moderne staatsidee. 1919.


-- The modern idea of the state. Trans. by G. H. Sabine and W. J. Shepard.

New York, 1922. Krause, Karl C. F. Grundlage des naturrechts, oder

philosophischer grundriss des ideales des rechtes. Leipzig, 1803.


-- Abriss des systemes der philosophie des rechtes, oder des naturrechtes.

Göttingen, 1828.


-- Erklärende bemerkungen und erläuterungen zu J. G. Fichtes grundlage des

naturrechts. Aus dem handschriftlichen nachlasse des verfasser herausgegeben

von Georg Mollat. Leipzig, 1893.


-- Das system der rechtsphilosophie. Herausgegeben von K. D. A. Röder.

Leipzig, 1874.


Krauss. Gedanken über staatsethos und internationalen verkehr. 1925.

Kuhlenbeck, Ludwig. Natürliche grundlagen des rechts und der politik.

Einsenach und Leipzig, 1904.


Kuhn, Fridolin. Die probleme des naturrechts bei Thomas von Aquin. München,

1909.


Lama, M. A. de la. Derecho natural: lecciones de filosofía del derecho y de

principios de legislación. 2a ed. Lima.


Lampredi, J. M. Juris publici universalis sive juris naturae et gentium

theoremata. Diritto pubblico universale, ossia diritto di natura e delle

genti. 3a ed. 3 vols. Florentiae, 1792-93. 4 vols. Pavia, 1818.


Lascaris, J. B. Juris naturae et gentium principia, et officia ad

Christianae doctrinae regulam exacta et explicata. 2 vols. Romae, 1778-79.


Lasson, A. System der rechtsphilosophie. Berlin und Leipzig, 1882.


Le Fur, Louis. "Le fondement du droit," Les Lettres (November and December,

1925, and January, 1926).


-- "Le droit naturel ou objectif s'étend-il aux rapports internationaux?"

Revue de Droit International et de Législation Comparée (1925), p. 59.


-- "Le droit naturel et le droit rationnel ou scientifique, leur rôle dans

la formation du droit international," Revue de Droit International et de

Législation Comparée (July, August, and September, 1927).


-- La théorie du droit naturel depuis le XVIIIe siècle et la doctrine

moderne. Paris, 1928.


Leibnitz, G. G. de. Codex iuris gentium diplomaticus. Guelph, 1747.


-- Nova methodus discendae docendaeque iurisprudentiae. Lipsiae, 1748.


Letoumeau, Charles. L'évolution juridique dans les races humaines. Paris,

1891.


Levi, Alessandro. La société et l'ordre juridique. Paris, 1911.


-- Il diritto naturale nelle filosofia di Roberto Ardigo. Padova, 1904.


Levi, Leone. Law of nature and nations as affected by divine law. London,

1855.


Levy, E. Introduction au droit naturel. Paris, 1922.


Levy-Bruhl, L. La morale et la science des moeurs. Paris, 1903.


Linck, Anton Arnold von. Ueber das naturrecht unserer zeit als grundlage der

strafrechtstheorien. München, 1829.


Lioy, Diodato. Della filosofia del diritto. Napoli, 1875-80. Trans. by W.

Hastie as The philosophy of right, with special reference to the principles

and development of law, London, 1875-80.


Lorimer, James. The institutes of law. A treatise of the principles of

jurisprudence as determined by nature. 2d ed. London and Edinburgh, 1880.


Luzac, E. Du droit naturel, civil et politique en forme d'entretiens. 2

vols. Amsterdam, 1802.


Maass, J. G. E. Grundriss des naturrechts. Leipzig, 1808.


Mackintosh, Sir James. A discourse on the study of the law of nature and

nations. London, 1799.


McMaster, John Bach. The acquisition of political, social and industrial

rights of man in America. Cleveland, 1903.


Madihn, Ludwig Gottfried. Grundsätze des naturrechts. Zum gebrauch seiner

vorlesungen. 2 vols. Frankfurt, 1794.


Maffioli. Éléments du droit naturel. 2 vols. Paris, 1800.


Malbèrg, Carré de. Contribution à la théorie générale de l'état. 2 vols.

Paris, 1920-22.


Manigk, A. Die idee des naturrechts. Berlin und Leipzig, 1926.


-- Wie stehen wir heute zum naturrecht? Berlin und Grunewald, 1926.


Marcaggi, Vincent. Les origines de la déclaration des droits de l'homme de

1789. 2e éd. Paris, 1912.


Marin. Historia del derecho natural y de gentes. 2 vols. Madrid, 1780.


Mausbach, Josef. Naturrecht und völkerrecht. Freiburg, 1918.


Meinecke, Friedrich. Die idee der staatsräson in der neuren geschichte.

München und Berlin, 1925.


Meister, C. F. G. Bibliotheca juris naturae et gentium. 3 vols. Göttingen,

1794-1857.


Melillo. Diritto naturale e di genti. Napoli, 1856.


Mellin, G. S. A. Grundlegung zur metaphysik der rechte oder der positiven

gesetzgebung: ein versuch über die ersten gründe des naturrechts. Zullichan,

1706.


Mendive, J. Elementos de derecho natural. Valladolid, 1884.


Mendizábal y Martín, L. Tratado de derecho natural. 2 pts. Madrid, 1920-21.


Menzel, A. Naturrecht und soziologie. Wien, 1912.


-- "Kaiser Joseph II und das naturrecht," Zeitschrift für Öffentliches

Recht, I, 511.


Meyer, Georg. Der staat und die erworbenen rechte. Leipzig, 1895.


Meyer, T. Institutiones iuris naturalis. 2 vols. 1886-1900.


Micelli, Vincenzo. La norma guiridica. Palermo, 1006.


Michel, Henry. L'idée de l'état: essai critique sur l'histoire des théories

sociales et politiques en France depuis la révolution. 2" éd. Paris, 1896.


Michelet, K. L. Naturrecht oder rechtsphilosophie als die praktische

philosophie, enthaltend rechts-, sitten-, und gesellschaftslehre. 2 vols.

Berlin, 1886.


Miller, William Galbraith. Lectures on the philosophy of law. Designed

mainly as an introduction to the study of international law. London, 1884.


-- Law of nature and nations in Scotland. Edinburgh, 1896.


Miraglia, Luigi. Il concetto storico dei diritti innati. Naples, 1881.


-- Filosofia del diritto. 3a ed. Naples, 1903. Trans. by John Lisle as

Comparative legal philosophy, applied to legal institutions, Modern Legal

Philosophy Series, Vol. III, Boston, 1914.


Modern French legal philosophy. Extracts from A. Fouillée, J. Charmont, L.

Duguit and R. Demogue. Trans. by Mrs. F. W. Scott and J. P. Chamberlain,

Modern Legal Philosophy Series, Boston, 1916.


Möhl, Arnold. Ueber das naturrecht. Mannheim, 1821.


Moliner, V. "Vico: fragment d'un traité inédit de droit naturel," Revue de

Législation et de Jurisprudence, VI (Paris, 1837).


Montemayor, Giulio de. Storia del diritto naturale. Milan, Palermo, and

Naples, 1911.


Morel de Vindé, Charles Gilbert Terray. La déclaration des droits de l'homme

et du citoyen, mise à la portée de tout le monde, et comparée avec les vrais

principes de toute société. 2e éd. Paris, 1790.


Morelly. Code de la nature; ou, Le véritable esprit des loix, 1755; pub.

avec notice et table analytique par Edouard Dolléans. Paris, 1910.


Munguía, Clemente de Jesús. Del derecho natural en sus principios comunes y

en sus diversas ramificaciones, o sea, Curso elemental de derecho natural y

de gentes, público, político, constitucional, y principios de legislación. 4

vols. México, 1849.


Murena, M. La giustizia naturale. Napoli, 1760.


Muriel, Domingo (Cyriaco Morelli). Rudimenta juris naturae et gentium.

Venice, 1791. -- Elementos de derecho natural y de gentes. Trad. de Ludano

Abeille, Buenos Aires, 1911.


Niemeyer, T. "Jus naturae et gentium. Eine umfrage zum gedächtnis des Hugo

Grotius," Zeitschrift für Internationales Recht, XXXIV (1925). Norcia, F.

Juris naturae et gentium institutiones. 2 vols. Romae, 1830.


Oldendorp, I. Iuris naturalis gentium et civilis. Antverpiae, 1539.


Passerin d'Entrèves, A. Il concetto del diritto naturale cristiano e la sua

storia secondo E. Troeltsch; nota presentata dai sod Solari e Jannaccone.

Torino, 1926.


Pérez Gomar, Gregorio. Conferencias sobre el derecho natural como

introducción al curso de derecho de gentes. Montevideo, 1864.


Pestel, Fridericus Guilelmus. Fundamenta jurisprudentiae naturalis,

delineata in usum auditorum. 2a ed. 2 pts. Lugduni Batavorum, 1774.


Picard, E. Essai sur la certitude dans le droit naturel. Bruxelles, 1864.


Pilati, C. Ragionamenti intorno alla legge naturale e civile. Venezia,

1766.


Platon, Jean Georges. Pour le droit naturel, à propos du livre de M.

Hauriou: Les principes du droit public. Paris, 1911.


Plucknett, Theodore F. T. "Bonham's case and judicial review," Harvard Law

Review, XL (November, 1926), 30.


Politz, K. H. L. Natur- und völkerrecht. Leipzig, 1827.


Pollock, Sir Frederick. "The history of the law of nature," Journal of the

Society of Comparative Legislation, II (1900), 418-433. Reprinted in

Columbia Law Review, I (January, 1901), 11, and in Essays in the Law

(London, 1922).


Portets, Xavier de. Cours de droit naturel, de gens et public. Paris, 1830.


Posada, A. Transformación del estado. Traducción con estudio preliminar

sobre la nueva orientación del derecho político. Madrid, 1910.


Post, A. H. Das naturgesetz des rechts: einleitung in eine philosophie des

rechts auf grundlage der modernen empirischen wissenschaft. Bremen, 1867.


Pound, Roscoe. An introduction to the philosophy of law. New Haven, 1922.


Pound, Roscoe. Law and morals. 2d ed. Chapel Hill, 1926.


-- "The theory of judicial decision," Harvard Law Review, XXXVI (April, May,

and June, 1923) 641, 802, 940.


-- "Philosophical theory and international law," Bibliotheca Visseriana, I,

71.


-- "Comparative law in the formation of American law," Acta Academiae

Universalis Jurisprudentiae Comparativa, I (1928), 183. Principes naturels

du droit et de la politique (par J. F. Dreux du Radier). 2 vols. Paris,

1765.


Pufendorf, Samuel. De jure naturae et gentium, libri octo. Amsterdam, 1704.

Translated and reprinted in many editions.


-- De officio hominis et civis juxta legem naturalem libri duo. London,

1673.


-- Les devoirs de l'homme et du citoyen, tels qu'ils lui sont prescrits par

la loi naturelle. Traduit du latin de Pufendorf, par J. Barbeyrac, Paris,

1830.


Quesnay, François. Le droit naturel. Paris, 1765.


Quesnay, R. F. J. "Il diritto naturale," Bibliotèca dell' Economísta, Ser.

1, vol. I.


Rachel, Samuel. De jure naturae et gentium dissertationes. Ed. by Ludwig von

Bar, Washington, D. C., The Carnegie Institution of Washington, 1916. 2

vols. Reproduction of edition of 1676.


Radbruch, Gustav. Grundzüge der rechtsphilosophie, 1914.


-- "Rechtswissenschaft als rechtsschöpfung, ein beitrag zum juristischen

methodenstreit," Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, XXII

(1906), 335.


Raymond, George Lansing. Ethics and natural law. New York and London, 1020.


Rayneval, J. M. G. de. Instituciones de derecho natural y de gentes. Notas

de M. Antonio López. 2 vols. Madrid, 1821.


Redslob, Robert. Die staatstheorien der französischen nationalversammlung

von 1789; ihre grundlagen in der staatslehre der aufklärungszeit und in den

englischen und amerikänischen verfassungsgedanken. Leipzig, 1912.


Rees, Wilhelm. Die erklärung der menschen- und bürgerrechte von 1789;

beitrage zu ihrer entstehungsgeschichte. Leipzig, 1912.


Reeves, Jesse Siddall. "The influence of the law of nature upon

international law in the United States," American Journal of International

Law, III (New York, 1909), 547-561.


Reinhard, L. Historia Jurisprudentiae naturalis. Lipsiae, 1725. Renard, G.

"Le droit, la justice et la volonté," Recueil Sirey (Paris, 1924), pp.

87-123.


-- Le droit, la logique et le bon sens. Paris, 1925.


-- Le droit, l'ordre et la raison. Paris, 1927.


Ripert, G. "Droit naturel et positivisme juridique," Annales de la Faculté

de Droit d'Aix (Marseilles, 1918).


Ritchie, David George. Natural rights, a criticism of some political and

ethical conceptions ... London and New York, 1895. 2d ed. 1916.


Rivalta, V. Diritto naturale e positivo. Bologna, 1898.


Roder, Karl David August. Grundzüge des naturrechts oder der

rechtsphilosophie. 2 vols. 2te aufl. Leipzig und Heidelberg, 1860-63.


Rodríguez, C. Elementos de derecho natural. 5a ed. Valencia, 1908.


Roguin, Ernest. La règle de droit. Paris, 1889.


Rosmini, E. Della natura del diritto et della sua relazione col dovere.

Naples, 1843.


-- Filosofia del diritto. 1841. 2a ed. 1865.


Rossig, C. G. Die grundsätze des natur- und völkerrechts, des allgemeinen

staats- und allgemeinne bürgerlichen rechts. Lipsiae, 1794.


Rothe, Tancrède. Traité de droit naturel théorique et appliqué. 6 vols.

Paris, 1885-1912.


Rotteck, Karl Wenzeslaus Rodecker von. Lehrbuch des vernunftrechts und der

staatswissenschaften. 4 vols. Stuttgart, 1829-35.


Rousseau, Jean Jacques. Discours sur l'origine et les fondements de

l'inégalité parmi les hommes. Ed. by Henri François and René E. G. Vaillaut,

New York and London, 1922.


Royer-Collard. Discours sur l'étude du droit de la nature et de gens. Paris,

1830.


Rumpf, M. Gesetz und richter, versuch einer methodik der rechtsanwen-dung.

Berlin, 1906.


Rutherforth, Thomas. Institutes of natural law. 2 vols. Cambridge, 1754-56.


Salmond, John W. "The law of nature," Law Quarterly Review, XI (London,

1895), 121.


Saleilles, Raymond. "École historique et droit naturel," Revue Trimestrielle

de Droit Civil, 1902, I, pp. 80-112.


-- "Le code civil et la méthode historique," Livre du Centenaire, I (1904),

95-129.


Salvadori, G. Das naturrecht und der entwickelungsgedanke. Leipzig, 1905.


Salvioli, G. Filosofia del diritto. Introduzione: Il diritto natural.

Napoli.


Santilli, A. La scuola del diritto naturale nella filosofia giuridica

contemporanea. Napoli, 1905.


Santistéban, J. S. Derecho natural o filosofía del derecho. 3a ed. Corbeil.


Savigny, L. von. "Das naturrechts problem und die methode seiner lösung,"

Jahrbuch für Gesetzgebung, Verwaltung und Volkswirtschaft im Deutschen

Reiche, XXX (1901), 407.


Savigny, F. K. von. Vom beruf unsrer zeit für gesetzgebung und

rechtswissenschaft. 1814.


Schaumann, C. G. Wissenschaftliches. naturrecht. Halle, 1792.


Scherger, George Lawrence. The evolution of modern liberty. New York, 1904.


Schilling, Friedrich Adolph. Lehrbuch des naturrechts oder der

philosophischen rechtswissenschaft mit vergleichender berücksichtigung

posi-tiver rechtsbestimmungen. 2 pts. Leipzig, 1859-62.


Schilling, Otto. Naturrecht und staat nach der lehre der alten kirche.

Paderborn, 1914.


Schlegel, J. F. W. Naturrettens eller den almindelige retslaeres

grundsaetringe. 2en ud. 2 vols. Köbenhavn, 1805.


Schmalz, Theodor. Die wissenschaft des natürlichen rechts. Leipzig, 1831.


Schmidt, Carl. Naturrecht und positives recht. Leipzig, 1873.


Schoetz, Max. "Natural and inherent rights protected by the Fourteenth and

Fifteenth Amendments of the Constitution of the United States," Marquette

Law Review, VII (1922-23), 154.


Schroeder, Edward August. Das recht der freiheit: kritisch, systematisch und

kodifiziert. Leipzig, 1901.


Schroeder, L. C. Elementa juris naturalis, socialis et gentium. Groen, 1735.


Schwarz, Ignaz. Institutiones juris publici universalis, naturae, et

gentium, ad normam moralistarum nostri temporis, maxime protestantium,

Hugonis Grottii, Puffendorfii, Thomasii, Vitriarii, Heineccii, aliorumque ex

recentissimis adornatae, et ad crisin revocatis eorum principiis, primum

fusiore, tum succinctiore methodo pro studio academico, praesertim

catholico, accomodatae. 2 vols. Venetiis, 1760.


Schwarz, J. Institutiones juris universalis naturae et gentium. 2 pts.

Augustae, 1743.


Siotto-Pintor, Manfredi. "Diritto naturale, diritto libero e diritto

legislative nel pensiero d'un giurista-filosofo Americano," Rivista

Internazionale di Filosofia del Diritto, III, 109. -- "La funzione del

diritto naturale dottrina del diritto pubblico intemo," Rivista

Internazionale di Filosojia del Diritto, IV, 1.


Selden, John. De jure naturali et gentium juxta disciplinam ebraeorum, libri

septem. Londini, 1640.


Senn, Felix. De la justice et du droit, explication de la définition

traditionnelle de la justice suivie d'une étude sur la distinction du jus

naturale et du jus gentium. Paris, 1927.


Sharp, Granville. Tract on the law of nature and principles of action in

man. 2d ed. London, 1809.


Simon, Ayala J. Concepto del derecho natural. Cómo se vive y se realiza el

derecho. San Salvador, 1908.


Singer, Heinrich. "Das naturrecht im codex canonici," Archiv für Rechts- und

Wirtschaftphilosophie, XVI (1922-23), 206-215.


Smith, Thomas V. Notes on the American doctrine of equality. International

Journal of Ethics, XXV, 164, 377, and XXXI, 31.


Smith, George H. Elements of right and of the law. 2d ed. 1887.


Solari, G. La scuola del diritto naturale nelle dottrine etico-guiridiche

de secoli XVII e XVIII. Torino, 1904.


Spencer, Herbert. Justice: being part IV of the Principles of ethics. New

York, 1891.


Stahl, F. J. Die philosophie des rechts. 1829. 5th ed. 1878.


Stammler, Rudolf. Lehrbuch der rechtsphilosophie. Berlin, 1922.


-- Die lehre von dem richtigen rechte. Berlin, 1902. Trans. by Isaac Husik

as The theory of justice, Modern Legal Philosophy Series, vol. VIII. Boston,

1925.


-- Rechts- und staatstheorien der neuzeit. Leipzig, 1917.


-- Systematische theorie der rechtswissenschaft. Halle, 1911.


-- Wirtschaft und recht nach der materialistischen geschichtsauffassung:

eine sozialphilosophische untersuchung. 3te aufl. Leipzig, 1806.


Stephani, H. Grundlinien der rechtswissenschaft oder des sogennanten

naturrechts. Erlangen, 1797.


Suliotis, C. I. Le droit naturel ou philosophie du droit. Paris, 1888.


Tapparelli d'Azeglio, Luigi. Essai théorique de droit naturel, basé sur les

faits. Trad. de l'italien d'après la dernière éd. avec approbation de

l'auteur. 4 vols. Paris et Toumai, 1857.


-- Saggio teoretico di diritto naturale appoggiato sul fatto. Livomo, 1845.


-- Corso elementare di naturale diritto ad uso delle scuole. 2a ed. Napoli,

1850.


Tarde, Gabriel. "Les transformations du droit," Étude sociologique, chap. 6.

8e ed. Paris, 1922.


Textor, Johann Wolfgang. Synopsis juris gentium, ed. by Ludwig von Bar. 2

vols. Washington, D. C. 1916.


Thevenet, Jean. "Un théoricien du droit naturel," Revue Général du Droit

Législation et Jurisprudence (April and June, 1925).


Thibaudeau, A. Les lois naturelles et la société des nations. Rennes, 1919.


Thomasius, C. Fundamenta iuris naturae et gentium. Halle, 1688.


-- Institutiones iurisprudentiae divinae. Lipsiae, 1688.


-- Grundlehren des natur- und völkerrechts. 1709.


Tissot, J. Droit naturel. Paris, 1875.


Tittel, Gottlieb August. Erläuterungen der theoretischen und praktischen

philosophie nach Herrn Feders ordnung; natur- und völkerrecht. Frankfurt,

1794.


Tönnies, Ferdinand. "Hobbes naturrecht," Archiv für Rechts- und Wirt

schaftsphilosophie, IV, 395; V, 129, 283.


Tourtoulon, Pierre. Les principes philosophiques de l'histoire du droit.

1919. Trans. by Martha M. Read as Philosophy in the development of law,

Modern Legal Philosophy Series, Vol. XIII. Boston, 1922.


Trendelenburg, Friedrich Adolf. Naturrecht auf dem grunde der ethik.

Leipzig, 1860. 2te aufl. 1868.


Troeltsch, Ernst. "Das stoisch-christliche naturrecht und das moderne

profane naturrecht," Historische Zeitschrift, CVl (München, 1911), 237-267.


Tucker, Henry St. George. Lectures on natural law. Charlottesville, 1844.


Tyrell, James. Brief disquisition on the law of nature according to the

principles and method laid down in Dr. Cumberland's Latin treatise on that

subject, as also his confutations of Mr. Hobbes's principles put into

another method. London, 1692.


De los Ríos Urruti. La filosofía del derecho en Don Francisco Giner. 1916.


Vadillo, Marqués de. Lecciones de derecho natural. Madrid, 1898.


Valensin, A. Traité de droit naturel. Vol. I. Paris, 1922.


Vareilles-Sommières. Les principes fondamentaux du droit. Paris, 1880.


Varvello, F. Institutiones philosophiae. Pars III, Ethica et jus naturae.

2a ed. 2 vols. Torino, 1923.


Vattel, Emmerich de. Le droit des gens, ou, principes de la loi naturelle,

appliqués à la conduite et aux affaires des nations et des souverains. 3

vols. Londres, 1758. Translated and reprinted in many editions.


-- Le droit des gens ou principes de la loi naturelle, appliqués à la

conduite et aux affaires des nations et des souverains (ed. of 1758).

Reproduced in The classics of international law, edited by James Brown Scott

and published by the Carnegie Institution of Washington (1916), 3 vols.


Vaunois, Albert. De la notion du droit naturel chez les Romains. De la

propriété artistique en droit français. Thesis. Univ. of Paris, 1884.


Vecchio, Georgio del. I presupposti filosofici della nozione del diritto.

Bologna, 1905.


-- II concetto del diritto. Bologna, 1906. 2a ed. 1912.


-- II concetto della natura e il principio del diritto. Torino, 1908. 2a

ed. Bologna, 1922. These treatises are translated by J. Lisle in The formal

bases of law, Comparative Legal Philosophy Series, Boston, 1914.


-- "Sui principi generali del diritto," Archivio Guiridico, Quarta Serie,

vol. I, Fasc. I.


-- "Positive right," Law Magazine and Review, XXXVIII (May, 1913), 297.


Verdross, M. Die einheit des rechtlichen weltbildes auf grundlage der völker

rechtsverfassung.


Vico, Giovan Battista. Dell' unico principio e fine del diritto universale.

Napoli, 1839.


Vinogradoff, Sir Paul. Common sense in law. London, 1914.


-- "Legal standards and ideals," Michigan Law Review, XXXIII (November,

1924), 1.


-- "Reason and conscience in sixteenth century jurisprudence," Law Quarterly

Review, XXIV (October, 1908), 379. Virozsil, A. von. Jus naturae privatum

methodo critica deductum. 3 vols. Pesthini, 1833.


Vitriarius, P. R. Institutiones juris naturae et gentium ... ad methodum H.

Grotii conscriptae; editae denuo et auctae J. J. Vitriario; accedit J. F.

Buddei Historia juris naturalis ut et synopsis juris naturalis. Lugduni et

Batavorum, 1704.


Vittoria, Francisco di. De juris insulis et de jure belli, 1696. Trans. by

J. P. Bate in Classics in international law, Washington.


Voigt, Moritz. Die lehre vom jus naturale, aequum et bonum, und jus gentium

der Römer. 4 vols. Leipzig, 1856-76.


Voltelini, Hans von. "Die naturrechtlichen lehren und die reformen des 18

Jahrhunderts," Historische Zeitschrift, CV (München, 1910), 65-104.


Walter, F. Naturrecht und politik im lichte der gegenwart. 2d ed. Bonn,

1871.


Warnkonig, L. A. Rechtsphilosophie als naturlehre des rechts. Freiburg,

1839.


Wilde, Norman. The ethical basis of the state. Princeton, 1924.


Wolff, Christian. Grundsätze des natur- und völkerrechts, worm alle

verbindlichkeiten und alle rechte aus der natur des menschen in einem

beständigen zusammenhange hergeleitet werden. Halle im magdeburgischen,

1754.


-- Institutiones juris naturae et gentium, in quibus ex ipsa hominis natura

continue nexu omnes obligationes et jura omnia deducuntur. Halae

Magdeburgicae, 1754.


-- Jus gentium methodo scientifica pertractatum, in quo jus gentium naturale

ab eo, quod voluntarii, pactitii et consuetudinarii est, accurate

distinguitur. Halae Magdeburgicae, 1749.


Wright, B. F. "American interpretations of natural law," American Political

Science Review, XX (August, 1926), 543.


-- "Natural law in American political theory," Southwestern Political and

Social Science Quarterly, IV (December, 1923), 202.


Zeiller, F. von. Jus naturae privatum. Viennae, 1819.




1. For a bibliography of works on natural law to the middle of the

nineteenth century, consult Hermann Theoderick Schletter, Handbuch der

juristischen literatur (Grimma, 1843), pp. 315 ff.



TABLE OF CASES


Adair v. United States, 208 U. S. 161, 144, 163.


Adkins v. Children's Hospital, 261 U. S. 525, 144, 162, 181, 185-189, 203.


Airway Electric Appliance Corporation v. Day, 266 U. S. 71, 232.


Allen v. Jay, 60 Me. 124, 131.


Allgeyer v. Louisiana, 165 U. S. 578, 163, 168.


American Ry. Express Co. v. F. S. Royster Guano Co., 273 U. S. 274, 176.


Ames v. Union Pac. Ry. Co., 64 Fed. 165, 156.


Arndt v. Griggs, 134 U. S. 316, 179.


Atkin v. Kansas, 191 U. S. 207, 179.


Ballard v. Hunter, 204 U. S. 241, 175.


Bank of Columbia v. Okley, 4 Wheat. 235, 117, 167.


Bank of State v. Cooper, 2 Yerg. (Tenn.) 599, 85, 112, 113, 167, 174.


Bankhead v. Brown, 25 Ia. 540, 125.


Banton v. Belt Line Ry., 268 U. S. 413, 233.


Barbier v. Connolly, 113 U. S. 27, 148, 161, 168, 169, 178.


Barbour v. Louisville Board of Trade, 82 Ky. 645, 167.


Barclay and Co. v. Edwards, 267 U. S. 442, 233.


Barron v. Baltimore, 7 Pet. 243, 193.


Bartemeyer v. Iowa, 18 Wall. 129, 148, 200, 214.


Bass, Ratcliff and Gretton Ltd. v. State Tax Commission, 266 U. S. 271, 232.


Bayard v. Singleton, 1 Martin 42, 111.


Bedford v. Shilling, 4 Serg. & R. (Pa.) 400, 95.


Beebe v. State, 6 Ind. 501, 101.


Benson v. Mayor, 10 Barb. 223, 174.


Bertholf v. O'Reilly, 74 N. Y. 516, 162, 178.


Block v. Hirsch, 256 U. S. 135, 171.


Bonham's Case, 8 Co. Rep. 107a, 8 Co. 113b and Brownl., 255, 33, 35.


Bosley v. McLaughlin, 236 U. S. 385, 187.


Bowman v. Middleton, 1 Bay (S. Ca.) 252, 111.


Braceville Coal Co. v. People, 147 Ill. 66, 162, 163.


Bradford Corporation v. Ferrand (1902), 2 Ch. 655, 42.


Bradwell v. State, 16 Wall. 130, 148.


Buchanan v. Rucker, 1 Camp. 63, 41.


Budd v. New York, 143 U. S. 517, 155.


Bunting v. Oregon, 243 U. S. 426, 187.


Bums Baking Company v. Bryan, 264 U. S. 504, 190, 191.


Butchers' Union Co. v. Crescent City Co., 111 U. S. 746, 161, 168.


Calder v. Bull, 3 Dallas, 386, 86-88, 110, 138, 173.


Carroll v. United States, 267 U. S. 132, 233.


Chester v. Bateson (1920), 1 K. B. 829, 41.


Chicago, Burlington & Quincy R. R. Co. v. McGuire, 219 U. S. 549, 179.


Chicago, Burlington & Quincy R. R. Co. v. Chicago, 166 U. S. 226, 134, 147,

148, 164, 169.


Chicago, Milwaukee & St. Paul Railway Co. v. Minnesota, 134 U. S. 418, 155,

168, 204.


Chicago, Rock Island & Pacific Ry. Co. v. Arkansas, 219 U. S. 453, 169.


City of Bridgeport v. Housatonic Railroad Co., 15 Conn. 475, 120.


City of London v. Wood, 12 Modern 669, 34.


Coates v. Mayor of the City of New York, 7 Cow. 585, 131.


Cochran v. Van Surlay, 20 Wend. 364, 130.


Collier v. Frierson, 24 Ala. 100, 337.


Commissioners of Leavenworth Co. v. Miller, 7 Kan. 479, 124.


Commonwealth v. Perry, 155 Mass. 117, 174, 175.


Concord R. R. v. Greely, 17 N. H. 47, 114.


Connolly v. Union Sewer Pipe Co., 184 U. S. 540, 170.


Cook v. Ottawa Univ., 14 Kan. 418, 128.


Coppage v. Kansas, 236 U. S. 1, 163.


Corfield v. Coryell, 4 Wash. C. C. 371, Fed. Cas. No. 3230, 173.


Couch v. Jeffries, 4 Burrows 2460, 89.


County of San Mateo v. Southern Pacific Ry. Co., 13 Fed. 722, 184.


Crawley v. Isaacs, 16 L. T. R. 529, 42.


Cummings v. Missouri, 4 Wall. 277, 164, 174.


Curtis Admr. v. Whipple, 24 Wis. 350, 127.


Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 4 Wheat. 518, 91, 92, 112, 116, 174.


Dash v. Van Kleek, 7 Johns (N. Y.) 477, 92, 110.


Davidson v. New Orleans, 96 U. S. 97, 147, 153, 164, 168.


Day v. Savadge, Hobart 85, 34.


Denny v. Mattoon, 84 Mass. 361, 99.


Detroit v. Detroit and Howell P. R. Co., 43 Mich. 140, 133.


Dobbins v. Los Angeles, 195 U. S. 223, 179.


Dominion Hotel v. Arizona, 249 U. S. 265, 207.


Dow v. Beidleman, 125 U. S. 680, 155.


Dred Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393, 178.


Dubuque County v. Dubuque and Pacific Ry. Co., 4 Greene (Ia.) 1, 124, 125,

127.


Dunn v. City Council of Charleston, Harper's Law Repts. 189, 132, 167.


Eakin v. Raub, 12 Serg. & R. 330, 81, 126.


Elliott's Executor v. Lyell, 3 Call. 234, 90.


Embury v. Conner, 3 N. Y. 511, 132.


Erie Railroad Co. v. Williams, 233 U. S. 685, 187.


Erwin's Appeal, 16 Pa. St. 256, 115.


Ex parte Smith, 223 Pac. 971, 188.


Ex parte Wall., 107 U. S. 265, 168, 200.


Fairmont Creamery Co. v. Minnesota, 274 U. S. 1, 193.


Fallbrook Irrigation District v. Bradley, 164 U. S. 112, 164.


Fisher v. McGirr, 1 Gray (Mass.) 101.


Fletcher v. Peck, 6 Cranch 87, 90.


Fort Smith Light and Traction Co. v. Bourland, 267 U. S. 330, 232.


Franklin v. South Carolina, 218 U. S. 161, 176.


Freeland v. Hastings, 10 Allen (Mass.) 570, 127.


Freeman v. Jeffries, L. R. 4 Ex. 189, 42.


French v. Barber Asphalt Pav. Co., 181 U. S. 324, 153.


Frisbie v. United States, 157 U. S. 160, 162.


Gardner v. Village of Newburgh, 2 Johns Ch. 162, 92, 131.


Gast Realty Co. v. Schneider Granite Co., 240 U. S. 55, 172.


Gelpeke v. City of Dubuque, 1 Wall. 175, 124, 127.


Gitlow v. New York, 268 U. S. 652, 175, 193, 234.


Godcharles v. Wigeman, 113 Pa. St. 431, 162.


Goddard v. Jacksonville, 15 Ill. 589, 101.


Goddin v. Crump, etc., 8 Leigh (Va.) 120, 120.


Goshen v. Stonington, 4 Conn. 209, 87, 94, 110, 120.


Granger Cases, 94 U. S. 155, 148, 149, 227.


Guilford v. Supervisors, 18 Barb. 615, 130.


Gulf, Colorado and Santa Fé Railway v. Ellis, 165 U. S. 150, 170.


Ham v. McClaws, 1 Bay (S, Ca.) 93, 89.


Hanson v. Vernon, 27 Ia. 28, 125, 126, 130.


Herlihy v. Donohue, 52 Mont. 601, 181.


Hoke v. Henderson, 4 Dev. 1, or 15 N. Ca. 1, 95, 112, 115.


Holden v. Hardy, 169 U. S. 366, 144, 174, 186.


Holden v. James, 11 Mass. 396, 111, 169.


Holmes v. Holmes, 4 Barb. 295, 101.


Hood v. Lynn, 1 Allen (Mass.) 103, 120.


Hurtado v. California, 110 U. S. 516, 144, 148, 168, 175.


In re Dorsey, 7 Porter (Ala.) 293, 113.


In re House Bill, 21 Colo. Rep. 27, 162.


In re Jacobs, 98 N. Y. 98, 178.


In re Kemmler, 136 U. S. 436, 170, 194.


In re Leach, 134 Ind. 665, 164.


In re Opinion of Justices, 58 Me. 590, 121, 128, 131.


Interstate Commerce Comm. v. Louisville & Nashville R. R. Co., 227 U. S. 88,

172.


Ives v. South Buffalo Ry. Co., 201 N. Y. 271, 211.


Jacobsen v. Massachusetts, 197 U. S. 11, 179.


Jeffers v. Fair, 33 Ga. 347, 116.


Johnson v. Clark (1908), 1 Ch. 303, 42.


Johnson v. County of Stark, 24 Ill. 75, 123.


Jones' Heirs v. Perry, 10 Yerg. (Tenn.) 59, 95, 112.


Kansas City Southern Ry. Co., et al. v. Road Improvement Dist., 266 U. S.

379, 232.


Kentucky Distilleries and Warehouse Co. v. Gregory, 253 U. S. 350, 339.


Kirtland v. Hotchkiss, 100 U. S. 491, 153.


Lake Shore & Michigan Southern Ry. Co. v. Smith, 173 U. S. 684, 179.


Lawson v. Milwaukee and Northern Railway Co., 30 Wis. 597, 124, 127.


Lawton v. Steele, 152 U. S. 133, 168.


Lebanon School District v. Lebanon Female Seminary, 12 Atl. 857, 133.


Leeper v. Texas, 139 U. S. 462, 169.


Legal Tender Cases, 12 Wall. 457, 227.


Levy Leasing Co. v. Siegel, 258 U. S. 242, 171.


License Tax Cases, 5 Wall. 462, 174.


Lincoln v. Smith, 27 Vt. 328, 101.


Linder v. United States, 268 U. S. 5, 233.


Lindsley v. Natural Carbonic Gas Co., 220 U. S. 62, 191.


Loan Association v. Topeka, 20 Wall. 655, 130, 153, 174.


Local Government Board v. Arlidge (1913), 1 K. B. 463; (1914), 1 K. B. 160;

(1915), A. C. 120, 41.


Lochner v. New York, 198 U. S. 45, 168, 171, 178, 185, 185, 187, 191, 203.


Lowell v. Boston, 111 Mass. 454, 131.


McClure v. Owen, 26 Ia. 243, 125.


McCray v. United States, 195 U. S. 27, 221.


Madisonville Traction Co. v. St. Barnard Mining Co., 196 U. S. 239, 174.


Maple Flooring Manufacturers' Association v. United States, 268 U. S. 563,

233.


Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 81, 90.


Master v. Miller, 4 T. R. 320, 42.


Mather v. City of Ottawa, 114, Ill. 659, 131.


Matter of Albany Street, 11 Wend. 149, 132.


Maxwell v. Dow, 176 U. S. 581, 175.


Mayo v. Wilson, 1 N. H. 53, 106.


Mead v. Acton, 139 Mass. 341, 127, 131.


Merrill v. Sherbume, 1 N. H. 199, 101.


Michigan Public Utilities Commission v. Duke, 266 U. S. 570, 232.


Millett v. People, 117 Ill. 294, 162.


Minneapolis St. Louis R. R. Co. v. Beckwith, 129 U. S. 26, 157, 183.


Minnesota v. Barber, 136 U. S. 313, 179.


Minor v. Happersett, 21 Wall. 162, 194.


Mirehouse v. Rennell, 1 Cl. & F. 527, 42.


Missouri Pacific Railway Co. v. Humes, 115 U. S. 512, 147, 214.


Missouri Pacific Railway Co. v. Nebraska, 164 U. S. 403, 133, 147.


Missouri Pacific Railroad Co. v. Road Dist., 266 U. S. 187, 232.


Monongahela Bridge Co. v. United States, 216 U. S. 177, 176, 211.


Monongahela Navigation Co. v. United States, 148 U. S. 312, 135, 156, 160,

176.


Moore v. Dempsey, 261 U. S. 86, 218.


Morford v. Unger, 8 Ia. 82, 125.


Moses v. Macferlen, 2 Burr. 1005, 42.


Mugler v. Kansas, 123 U. S. 623, 179, 214.


Muller v. Oregon, 208 U. S. 412, 187.


Munn v. Illinois, 94 U. S. 113, 148, 202, 227.


Murdock v. Memphis, 20 Wall. 590, 146.


Murray's Lessee v. Hoboken Land and Improvement Co., 18 How. 272, 105, 143.


National Waterworks Co. v. Kansas City, 62 Fed. 853, 156.


Needier v. Bishop of Winchester, Hob. 220.


Noble State Bank v. Haskell, 219 U. S. 104, 328.


Norman v. Heist, 5 W. & S. 171, 167.


North Laramie Land Co. v. Hoffman, 268 U. S. 276, 233.


Northern Securities Co. v. United States, 193 U. S. 197, 195.


Norwood v. Baker, 172 U. S. 269, 153, 201.


Nunnemacher v. State, 129 Wis. 190, 174, 211.


Ochsenbein v. Papelier, L. R. 8 Ch. 695, 42.


Officer v. Young, 5 Yerg. (Tenn.) 320, 112.


Ogden v. Saunders, 12 Wheat. 213, 90.


Ohio Utilities Co. v. Public Utilities Commission, 267 U. S. 359, 233.


Opinion of Justices, 211 Mass. 624, 131.


Patterson v. Colorado, 205 U. S. 454, 175, 193.


Patterson v. The Eudora, 190 U. S. 169, 186.


Pavesich v. Life Ins. Co., 122 Ga. 190, 211.


Pembina Mining Co. v. Pennsylvania, 125 U. S. 181, 157.


Pennoyer v. Neff, 95 U. S. 714, 147, 160.


Pennsylvania Coal Co. v. Mahon, 260 U. S. 393, 171.


People v. Batchellor, 53 N. Y. 128, 128.


People v. Brooklyn, 4 N. Y. 419, 123.


People v. Charles Schweinler Press, 214 N. Y. 395, 162.


People v. Coler, 166 N. Y. 1, 211.


People v. Gallagher, 3 Gibbs. (Mich.) 244, 101.


People v. Gillson, 109 N. Y. 389, 178, 203.


People v. Hurlbut, 24 Mich. 44, 174.


People v. La Fetra, 230 N. Y. 429, 171.


People v. Marx, 99 N. Y. 377, 175, 178.


People v. Max, 70 Colo. 100, 341.


People v. O'Brien, 111 N. Y. 1, 133.


People v. Salem, 20 Mich. 452, 126, 128, 130.


People v. Smith, 21 N. Y. 595, 123.


People v. State Treasurer, 23 Mich. 499, 129.


People v. Western Union Co., 70 Colo. 90, 341.


People v. Williams, 189 N. Y. 131, 162.


Pierce v. Society of the Sisters, 268 U. S. 510, 233.


Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U. S. 537, 179.


Pollock v. Farmers' Loan & Trust Co., 157 U. S. 429, 149, 150.


Powell v. Pennsylvania, 127 U. S. 678, 148.


Prudential Insurance Co. v. Cheek, 259 U. S. 530, 193.


Pumpelly v. Green Bay Co., 13 Wall. 166, 85, 134.


Railroad Co. v. County of Otoe, 16 Wall. 667, 124.


Reagan v. Farmers' Loan and Trust Co., 154 U. S. 362, 155, 178.


Regents of the University of Maryland v. Williams, 9 G. & J. 365, 87, 95,

174.


Rex v. Local Government Board (1914), 1 K. B. 160, 41.


Rhode Island v. Palmer, 253 U. S. 350, 339.


Rice v. Parkman, 16 Mass. 326, 95, 99.


Riley v. Massachusetts, 232 U. S. 671, 187.


Ritchie v. People, 155 Ill. 98, 162.


Ritchie v. Wayman, 244 Ill. 509, 162.


Rogers v. Peck, 199 U. S. 425, 175.


Ruggles v. Illinois, 108 U. S. 526, 155.


St. Louis v. The Ferry Co., 11 Wall. 423, 174.


San Mateo County v. Southern Pacific Ry. Co., 13 Fed. 722, 184.


Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific Railroad Co., 118 U. S. 394, 157.


Santa Clara Railroad Tax Case, 9 Sawyer, 165, 157.


Schibsby v. Westenholz, L. R. 6 Q. B. 155, 41.


Schmitt v. F. W. Cook Brewing Co., 187 Ind. 623, 101.


Scott v. McNeal, 154 U. S. 34, 160, 167.


Scott v. Scott (1913), C. 417, 41.


Sears v. Cottrell, 5 Mich. 250, 167.


Sharpless v. Mayor of Philadelphia, 21 Pa. St. 147, 124, 126, 127, 206.


Shields v. Ohio, 95 U. S. 319, 158.


Silberschein v. United States, 266 U. S. 221, 232.


Sill v. Coming, 15 N. Y. 297, 114.


Simon v. Southern Ry. Co., 236 U. S. 115, 172.


Sinking Fund Cases, 99 U. S. 700, 200.


Sioux City Bridge v. Dakota County, 260 U. S. 441, 172.


Slaughter-House Cases, 16 Wall. 36, 145, 146, 149, 160, 175, 200, 204, 214.


Smyth v. Ames, 169 U. S. 466, 155, 156.


Sohier v. Massachusetts General Hospital, 3 Cush. 483, 99.


Southern Railway Co. v. Greene, 216 U. S. 400, 157, 170.


Speer v. School Directors, etc. of Blairsville, 50 Pa. St. 150, 127.


Spring Valley Water Works v. Schottler, 110 U. S. 347, 154.


Standard Oil Co. v. United States, 221 U. S. 1, 195.


State v. — , 1 Hay. (N. Ca.) 28, 106, 167.


State v. Barker, 116 Ia. 96, 174.


State v. Doherty, 60 Me. 504, 113.


State v. Evans, 3 Ill. 208, 133.


State v. Goodwill, 33 W. Va. 179, 162.


State v. Keeran, 5 R. I. 497, 101.


State v. Loomis, 115 Mo. 307, 162.


State v. Moores, 55 Neb. 480, 84.


State v. Nemaha County, 7 Kan. 542, 124, 139.


State v. Norton, 5 Ohio N. P. R. 183, 162.


State v. Noyes, 10 Foster (N. H.) 279, 101.


State v. Paul, 5 R. I. 185, 101.


State v. Simons, 2 Spears 761, 114.


State v. Tappan, 29 Wis. 664, 127.


State, etc. v. Wapello Co., 13 Ia. 388, 125.


State ex rel. Halliburton v. Roach, 230 Mo. 408, 338.


Stebbins and Hurley v. Riley, 268 U. S. 137, 233.


Stein v. Mayor, Aldermen, etc. of Mobile, 24 Ala. 591, 124.


Stewart v. Supervisors of Polk Co., 30 Ia. 9, 126, 130.


Stone v. Farmers' Loan and Trust Co., 116 U. S. 307, 154, 178


Stone v. Wisconsin, 94 U. S. 181, 149.


Stuart v. Palmer, 74 N. Y. 183, 168. Symsbury Case, Kirby (Conn.) 444, 89.


Talbot v. Dent, 9 B. Mon. (Ky.) 526, 120.


Taylor v. Beckham, 178 U. S. 548, 201.


Taylor v. Porter, 4 Hill 140, 100, 114, 115.


Taylor v. Thompson, 42 Ill. 9, 127.


Terrett v. Taylor, 9 Cranch 43, 94, 173.


Thomas v. City of Port Huron, 27 Mich. 320, 129.


Thomas v. Leland, 24 Wend. 65, 130.


Texas v. White, 7 Wall. 700, 338.


Town of Guilford v. Supervisors of Chenango Co., 13 N. Y. 143, 124.


Township of Pine Grove v. Talcott, 19 Wall. 666, 124, 129.


Tregor's Case, Y. B. Pasch, 8 Edw. Ill.; Fitzherbert, Annuities 41, 34.


Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U. S. 312, 170, 176.


Trustees of the University of North Carolina v. Foy, 2 Hay (N. Ca.) 310, 89,

106, 110.


Turpin v. Lemon, 187 U. S. 51, 179.


Turpin v. Locket, 6 Call. 113, 90.


Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U. S. 78, 170, 176, 194.


Tyson and Bro. United Theatre Ticket Offices v. Banton, 273 U. S. 418, 191,

192.


Tyson v. School Directors of Halifax Township, 51 Pa. St. 9, 127.


United States v. American Tobacco Co., 221 U. S. 106, 195.


United States v. Cohen Grocery Co., 255 U. S. 81, 144.


United States v. Cruikshank, 92 U. S. 542, 146, 148, 175, 194.


United States v. Harris, 106 U. S. 629, 144.


United States v. Trans-Missouri Freight Association, 166 U. S. 290, 195.


United States v. Trenton Potteries Co., 273 U. S. 392, 195.


Untermeyer v. Anderson, 276 U. S. 440, 144.


Van Home's Lessee v. Dorrance, 2 Dall. 304, 89.


Van Zandt v. Waddell, 2 Yerg. (Tenn.) 260, 112.


Varick v. Smith, 5 Paige 137, 132.


Wales v. Stetson, 2 Mass. 143, 91.


Walker v. Sauvinet, 92 U. S. 90, 149.


Wally's Heirs v. Kennedy, 2 Yerg. (Tenn.) 554, 112.


Ward v. Bamard, 1 Aikens (Vt.) 120, 112.


Waters-Pierce Oil Co. v. Texas, 212 U. S. 86, 176.


Watson v. Maryland, 218 U. S. 173, 175.


Weismer v. Village of Douglas, 64 N. Y. 92, 130.


Welch v. Wadsworth, 30 Conn. 149, 87, 120.


Wells v. City of Weston, 22 Mo. 385, 125.


West v. Louisiana, 194 U. S. 258, 176.


Wheeler's Appeal from Probate, 45 Conn. 306, 87.


White v. White, 5 Barb. 474, 100, 115, 167.


Whiting v. Sheboygan and Fond du Lac Railroad Co., 25 Wis. 167, 126.


Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357, 191, 194.


Wilkinson v. Leland, 2 Pet. 627, 94, 173.


Wisconsin, Minnesota & Pacific R. R. Co. v. Jacobsen, 179 U. S. 287, 179.


Wolff Co. v. Industrial Court, 262 U. S. 522, 192.


Work v. Rives, 267 U. S. 175, 232.


Wynehamer v. State of New York, 13 N. Y. 378, 100, 115, 178.


Yee Hem v. United States, 268 U. S. 178, 233.


Yeiser v. Dysart, 267 U. S. 540, 233.


Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356, 144, 169, 178.


Zylstra v. Corporation of Charleston, 1 Bay 382, 111.



INDEX


Abbot, E. V., on natural rights, 339-340


Adams, John, on natural rights, 54


Adams, Samuel, on natural rights, 54


Ahrens, Heinrich, on natural law, 239-240


Althusius, on distinction between king and tyrant, 16


Anglo-Americans, legal points of view of, 44-47


Appendix, on natural law phrases used by Supreme Court, 232-234


Aquinas, Thomas, on natural law, 13, 14, 278


Arbitrary acts, held void by courts, 166-172


Aristotle, on distinction between fundamental and ordinary laws, 6, 7;

dualism of, 6, 7, 23


Austin, John, opposition to natural rights, 71


Bacon, Sir Francis, on law of nature, 35


Baudry-Lacantinerie, G., on natural law, 320


Becker, Carl, on anti-natural rights' doctrine, 66


Bentham, on natural law doctrines, 68


Beudant, on natural rights, 243


Bill of rights, in British North America Act, 83


Bingham, John A., draft of due process of law clause by, 144


Blackstone, Sir William, on natural law in Commentaries, 38, 39, 56, 57


Blatchford, Justice, on judicial review of rate regulation, 155


Bodin, Jean, theory of sovereignty of, 20, 21, 60


Boistel, on natural law, 242, 243


Bossuet, advocate of force theory, 61


Bracton, use of Roman concepts of natural law, 32, 33


Bradley, Justice, on judicial review of rate regulation, 156, 157, 204


Brandeis, Justice, on rule of reason, 190, 191; on fundamental rights, 194


Brewer, Justice, on protection of property rights, 134, 135; on natural

justice, 176; conservative doctrines in Supreme Court decisions and, 201,

202; on duty of courts to protect property, 223


Brown, Justice, on Duguit's theories, 272


Brown, Ray A., on cases under due process clause, 184, 185


Butler, Justice, on rule of reason, 190


Canon law, natural law in, 13


Cardozo, Benjamin N., on natural law theories, 70; on use of natural law,

326; on modern law of nature, 329, 330


Carlyle, R. W. and A. J., on concept of jus naturale, 11, 13


Cathrein, Victor, on natural law, 286-288


Charmont, Joseph, on natural law, 258-260


Chase, Justice Salmon P., on immutable fundamental rights, 174


Chase, Justice Samuel, higher law ideas, 86, 87, 110, 138


Cicero, on law of nature, 9, 10


Clifford, Justice, on legislative supremacy, 153, 154


Coke, Sir Edward, on doctrine of superior principles of right and justice,

33, 56, 57; opinion in Bonham's Case, 33-35; on Magna Carta as fundamental

law, 37, 38; on due process of law, 107


Cole, Justice, on judicial review, 126


Collins, Charles W., cases under Fourteenth Amendment, 183


Comte, Auguste, on natural rights, 69


Conservatism, in Supreme Court decisions, 137-139


Constant, Benjamin, on limitations upon sovereignty, 238, 239


Constitutions, limits on power to amend, 336-342


Cooley, Thomas M., on meaning of due process of law, 116, 117; on implied

limitations on legislatures, 116n, 138; Constitutional Limitations cited,

116, 117, 118, 119; Law of Taxation cited, 117, 129; on superior law

principles, 118, 119; on public purpose as principle in taxation, 127-130;

on public purpose as requirement for exercise of eminent domain, 133; on

bills of rights, 171; on limits on amending power, 337


Corwin, Edward S., on judicial review in New York, 205, 206


Dalloz, summary of natural rights in, 240, 241


Declaration of Independence, natural rights' doctrine in, 54; Constitution

and, 201


Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, 63-65


Demogue, R., on natural law, 260


Dewey, John, on immutable rules, 222, 223


Dicey, A. V., on judicial legislation, 224, 225; on supremacy of law, 226


Dickinson, Thomas, on recognition of rights by charters, 54, 55


Digest and Institutes, natural law in, 10, 11


Dillon, John F., on implied limits on legislatures, 125-127, 138; on

necessity of checks upon majority, 151


Due process of law, different meanings of, 104-107; in English law, 104,

105; in Massachusetts constitution, 105; in Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments,

106; applied by state justices, 108-116; concepts involved in, 113, 114;

economic conditions and, 119-122; reactionary tendencies and, 122-139;

Fourteenth Amendment and, 143-165; as applied to regulation of public

utilities, 154-159; general rule of reason and, 166-195; fundamental rights

and, 172-177; police regulations and, 177-182; extension of meaning of, 182,

185 Duguit, Léon, on theories of natural law, 260-273


Ehrlich, Eugen, on natural law, 248


Eminent domain, public purpose limitation for, 131-134; limitations on

exercise of, in foreign countries, 135, 136


Esmein, M., on natural rights, 335


Federalists, the, aims of, 96, 97; on limiting legislative activities, 97-99


Field, Justice, on interpretation of Fourteenth Amendment, 146, 148; on

fundamental rights, 160, 161; on inalienable rights, 174; conservative

doctrines in Supreme Court decisions and, 199, 200.


Fourteenth Amendment, due process of law and, 143-165; restricted

interpretation of, 145-149; change in interpretation of, due to economic and

political pressure, 149-154; summary of decisions under, for 1924, 234


French parlements, guardians of fundamental laws, 62, 63


Fundamental law, English doctrines of, 29-39


Fundamental rights, acts contravening, are void, 172-177


Gaius, on natural law, 10


Gavet, Gaston, on natural rights, 271


Geny, Francois, on Stammler's theories, 250; on natural law, 288-293


Gibson, Justice, on reasoning of Marshall, 81, 82


Gierke, Otto, on higher law theories, 244-246


Gray. Justice, on judicial review of rate regulation, 155


Grotius, Hugo, doctrines of natural law of, 18, 19; on state of nature, 51,

52; doctrines of, cited, 92


Guillemon, Pierre, on higher laws, 270- 271


Guizot, F. P., on higher law, 59


Haldane, Lord, on relation of moral ideas to law, 313, 314


Harlan, Justice, on requirement for compensation in eminent domain

proceedings, 133, 134; conservative doctrines in Supreme Court decisions

and, 200, 201


Hauriou, M., on superior law doctrines, 273, 274


Hegel, G. W. F., on natural rights, 69; theories of law of, 237, 238


Henry, Patrick, on natural rights, 54


Higher law theories, in mediaeval thought, 14, 15; in England, 29-48; as

basis for review of legislative acts by courts, 80-85; in recent Supreme

Court decisions, 185-193; limits on state sovereignty and, 331-336


Higher laws, as guide to legislators, 323-331


Hobbes, Thomas, distinction between ius naturale and lex naturalis, 21


Holdsworth, William E., on Magna Carta, 30; on equity and law of reason, 32;

on political functions exercised by courts, 33; on Coke's dicta in Bonham's

Case, 35; on supremacy of parliament, 35, 37, 38


Holland, J. G., on supremacy of parliament, 34n, 37, 38


Holmes, Justice, on conservative attitude of lawyers, 152; on due process of

law, 171; dissent in Minimum Wage Case, 187; on legislative supremacy, 192


Hosmer, Chief Justice, on protecting vested rights, 94, 95; on implied

limits on legislatures, 110


Hough, Justice, on litigation under due process of law, 153, 184


Houques-Fouciade, M., on natural law, 320


Ihering, Rudolf von, on higher law philosophy, 246, 247


Inalienable rights, American theories of, 52-56


International law, natural law theories in, 294-302


Isadore of Seville, on natural law, 12, 13


Jefferson, Thomas, use of natural rights' doctrine, 54, 57; natural rights'

theories of, discredited, 65


Jenks, Edward, on Magna Carta, 30


John of Salisbury, on distinction between king and tyrant, 16


Johnson, Justice, on higher law, 90, 91; on due process of law, 116, 117


Judicial review of legislation, rate regulation and, 154-160; conservative

doctrines and, 198-210; in New York, 205, 206; in Massachusetts, 205, 206


Kant, Immanuel, theories of law of, 237, 238


Kent, Chancellor, on implied limitations on legislatures, 92-94; on public

purpose requirement for eminent domain, 131


Kohler, Joseph, on natural law, 247


Krabbe, H., higher law doctrines of, 274-277


Krause, F., on natural law, 239


Laissez faire theories, checks on governmental powers and, 118;

individualism and, 121, 122; liberty of contract and, 162; arbitrary wage

payment interfered with economic, 186; doctrine of liberty of contract and,

189; Justice Peckham's defense of, 203


Lambert, Edouard, on judicial review in United States, 207, 208


Laski, Harold J., on natural rights, 334, 335


Laurent, on law of nature, 240, 241


Le Fur, Louis, on natural law, 297-300


Legislative supremacy, in state governments, 108, 109


Legislatures, purpose of implied limits on, 95-97


Liberty of contract, as phase of due process of law, 160-164


Lincoln, Abraham, on natural rights, 102


Locke, John, on law of nature, 22, 23; on arbitrary acts of government, 166


McIlwain, C. H., on fundamental laws in England, 29, 31


McKechnie, William S., on Magna Carta, 30, 37


Magna Carta, referred to as fundamental and immutable, 29, 30; law

interpreted according to maxims of, 85; "law of land" phrase in, 104, 105;


Fourteenth Amendment called American, 143


Maitland, F. W., on law of nature in development of equity, 32n


Marshall, John, on judicial review, 81, 82; conservative legal theories of,

196, 197


Mason, Justice, on natural rights, 114, 115


Michel, Henri, on natural rights, 243


Middle Ages, natural law in, 12-17


Miller, Justice, on implied limitations on legislatures, 130, 138, 153; on

interpretation of Fourteenth Amendment, 147; on immutable fundamental

rights, 174


Moody, Justice, on inalienable rights, 176


Mott, Rodney L., on due process of law, 107n, 108n


Natural law, Graeco-Roman concepts of, 4-12, 24-27; German current views on,

246-251; metaphysical and theological types of, 278-293; ethical concepts

and, 310-316; Dean Pound on types of, 311, 315; philosophical standards and,

316-323


Natural law concepts, denial of the application of, 75-77


Natural law ideas, types of, in ancient and mediaeval times, 24-27; in

English law, 43, 44; American, 57-59, 216-219


Natural law theories, ancient and mediaeval, 3-27; in English judicial

decisions, 39-43; in relation to natural rights, 49-52; American, 52-59;

French, 59-65; in American law, 77-80; return to, 99-103; due process of law

and, 104-139; economic and legal bases for, 117-122; judicial review of

legislative acts and, 196-234; purpose of, in American constitutional law,

210-216; American political and legal conservatism and, 210-232; continuance

of, in Europe, 237-244; German doctrine of a Rechtsstaat and, 244-251,

European, 302-306; objectives in, 309-336; main types of, 345-349


Natural rights, decline of theories of, 65-72; ideas on, in colonial times,

78-80


Nesbitt, James L., on due process of law, 180-181


Otis, James, on natural rights, 54


Paine, Thomas, on natural rights, 54, 57


Paterson, Justice, on natural rights, 89


Peckham, Justice, on rule of reason, 178; conservative doctrines of, in

Supreme Court decisions, 202, 203


Permanent Court of International Justice, general principles of law and,

324, 325


Physiocrats, theories of natural rights of, 60, 61


Pike, L. O., on Magna Carta, 30


Plucknett, Theodore, F. T., on English fundamental ideas, 31


Police regulations, reasonableness of, 177-182


Pollock, Sir Frederick, on supremacy of parliament, 34n, 37, 38; on natural

law doctrines in English law, 39-41; on law of nature, 301, 330


Pound, Roscoe, on metaphysical jurists, 279; on types of natural law, 311,

315


Powell, Thomas Reed, on interpretation


Pufendorf, Samuel, on law of nature, 22; on state of nature, 51, 52;

doctrines of, cited, 92


Quesnay, on higher law, 60


Radbruch, Gustav, on natural law, 296


Ranke, on natural rights, 69


Reasonableness, standards of, for valid customs, 15; Justice Stone on

doctrines of, in Anti-Trust Cases, 194, 195; as standard in judicial review

of legislation. 166-195; use of in recent Supreme Court decisions, 232-234


Rechtsstaat, German doctrine of, 244-246


Reformation, theories of natural law and, 17-24


Renan, on natural rights, 69


Riddell, Justice, on eminent domain proceedings in Canada, 136


Roman praetors, ideas of natural justice of, 7, 8


Roosevelt, Theodore, on judicial law-making, 327


Root, Elihu, on limitations on amending power, 339


Rule of reason, due process of law and, 166-195; in recent Supreme Court

decisions, 232-234


Saleilles, Raymond, on natural law, 252-258; on Duguit's theories, 272


Salmond, John W., on differences between English and Continental points of

view, 46, 47; on natural law, 76


Sanford, Justice, on interpretation of Fourteenth Amendment, 193


Savigny, on natural rights, 69, 70


Schiffer, Eugen, on natural law, 296, 297


Seneca, on doctrine of equality, 19, 55


Social compact theory, 86, 87


Social-Utilitarians, repudiation of natural rights' theory by, 68


Sophists, legal theories of, 5, 6


Sophocles, idea of higher laws of, 5


Sovereignty, in Greek thought, 7; higher law theories and limits on, 331-

336


Stammler, Rudolf, on natural law, 248-250


Stoics, concepts of natural law of, 7-10


Stone, Justice, on doctrine of reasonableness in Anti-Trust Cases, 194-195


Story, Justice, on implied limitations on legislatures, 94, 95, 173;

conservative legal theories and, 196, 197; on limits on amending power, 337


Strong, Justice, on interpretation of Fourteenth Amendment, 148


Super-constitution, created by courts, 227


Sutherland, Justice, on meaning of due process of law, 185, 186, 192


Taft, Chief Justice, on meaning of due process of law, 170; dissent in

Minimum Wage Case, 186


Thayer, James Bradley, on judicial review, 227-229


Troeltsch, Ernst, on natural law, 288


Ulpian, on types of natural law, 10, 11


Van Buren, Martin, on Federalist policies, 96


Vattel, on law of nature, 50-52


Vecchio, Georgio del, on natural law, 279-286


Vested rights, limits on legislatures to protect, 88-95; Marshall on

preserving, 90, 91; Kent on preserving, 92-94; Story on preserving, 94, 95;

Hosmer on preserving, 94, 95; New York courts, on preserving, 99-101


Vinogradoff, Sir Paul, on interpretation of Magna Carta, 30; on modern

revival of natural law, 317-319; on natural rights, 335


Waite, Chief Justice, on judicial review of rate regulation, 155 of due

process of law, 215, 216


Washington, Justice, on fundamental rights, 173


Webster, Daniel, on due process of law, 112, 116; conservative legal

theories and, 106, 197


William of Ockham, classification of natural law by, 17


Wilson, James, on law of nature, 55


Wohlgemuth, M., on higher laws, 269, 270


Wolff, Frederick von, on natural law, 50; on state of nature, 51, 52


Wright, B. F., on American theory of natural rights, 67, 68


Zane, John M., on natural law school, 77 Zeno, on natural law, 8, 9





Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "The Revival of Natural Law Concepts" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools