History of Medieval Political Theory in the West  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

Jump to: navigation, search

"There is no change in political theory so startling in its completeness as the change from the theory of Aristotle to the later philosophical view represented by Cicero and Seneca ... We think that this cannot be better exemplified than with regard to the theory of the equality of human nature. There is only one possible definition for all mankind, reason is common to all ; men differ indeed in learning, but are equal in the capacity for learning. There is no race which under the guidance of nature cannot attain to virtue. The same virtues are pleasing, the same vices are detestable to all nations; all men can be made better by learning the true conception of life. It is only the perversions which depraved habit and foolish conceptions have brought, which cause men to differ so much from each other. Nature has given to all men reason, that is, true reason, and therefore the true law, which is right reason commanding and forbidding. We shall see later how these sweeping generalisations recur in Seneca, and it can scarcely be doubted that we have here presented to us of the lawyers like Ulpian and Florentinus in which all men are presented to us as being by nature free, by nature equal. We are indeed at the beginnings of a theory of human nature and society of which the "Liberty, Equality, and Fraternity" of the French Revolution is only the present-day expression. To complete the parallelism of the conception, we may observe that the "Fraternity" of the Revolution is only a later form of Cicero's phrase, "By nature we are disposed to love men; this is the foundation of law."" --History of Medieval Political Theory in the West (1903–36) by Robert Warrand Carlyle and Alexander James Carlyle

[...]

We have ventured to suggest that the dividing-line between the ancient and the modern political theory must be sought, if anywhere, in the period between Aristotle and Cicero. We think that this cannot be better exemplified than with regard to the theory of the equality of human nature."--History of Medieval Political Theory in the West (1903–36) by Robert Warrand Carlyle and Alexander James Carlyle



"When we come to Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus at the close of the second century, we find that remarkable turn of theory whose expression we have already noticed in considering the meaning of "natural law." It will be as well to put together these phrases in this new connexion. In the first place we may perhaps put the famous phrase of Ulpian: "Quod ad jus naturale attinet, omnes homines aequales sunt." * It is just possible that this phrase is a little more technical than might at first sight appear, for Ulpian is evidently discussing the legal position of the slave, and the equality of which he speaks may conceivably have had primarily a technical signification, as equal in position before the law. Still, the phrase is very noteworthy in its bold and direct character. The impression it makes is not weakened but rather confirmed when we turn to his equally famous phrase, " cum jure naturali omnes liberi nascerentur." * Slavery had no place under the jus naturale, but came in under the jus gentium. By the law of nature men were free and equal."--History of Medieval Political Theory in the West (1903–36) by Robert Warrand Carlyle and Alexander James Carlyle

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

History of Medieval Political Theory in the West (1903–36) was a six-volume book by brothers Robert Carlyle and Alexander James Carlyle.

Full text of volume 1[1]

A HISTORY


OP


MEDUIVAL POLITICAL THEORY










A HISTORY


OF


MEDIEVAL 'POLITICAL THEOKY IN THE WEST


BY


R W. CARLYLE, CLE.


AND


A. J. CARLYLE, M.A.

CHAPLAIN AXD LIOTUREB (FORMIRLT FBLLOW) or VNITBR8ITY COLLBOS, OXFORD


VOL. I.

THE SECOND CENTURY TO THE NINTH

Bt a. J. CAELYLE, M.A


NEW YORK G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS

EDINBURGH AND LONDON

WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS

1903






l\




Prmted by William Blackwood & Sons, Edvnkwghy ScotUmd.



^


sy,^4^








VOL. I. A HISTORY OF POLITICAL THEORY


FBOH


THE ROMAN LAWYERS OF THE SECOND CENTURY TO THE POLITICAL WRITERS OF THE NINTH*


BY

A. J. CARLYLE.










PREFACE.


In bringing out the first volume of a History of Mediaeval Political Theory, it may be well to indicate briefly the character of the work which we hope to carry out. In this volume we deal with the elements out of which the more developed theory of the Middle Ages arose; we hope to carry on the work to the political theorists of the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries — that is, to the time when, as it is thought, the specific characteristics of modern political theory began to take shape.

The subject with which we are endeavouring to deal is strictly a history of theory, not of institutions. We believe, indeed, that in the Middle Ages, as at other times, the two things are closely related to each other, — that theory never moves very far away from the actual conditions of public life; but yet the two things are distinct, if not separate. The principles which lie behind the development of political institutions are sometimes the subject of careful reflection, sometimes are hardly apprehended; but in either case they are to be distinguished from any particular concrete forms in which they may be embodied. We have, indeed, been compelled frequently to examine the institutions of the Middle Ages, but we have done this only in order to draw out more clearly the character of the theories which were actually






VI PREFACE.

current among those who reflected on the nature of political life.

We are very conscious of the fact that in the attempt to deal with a subject which extends over so many centuries it is probable that we have made many mistakes, and have been guilty of many omissions. We can scarcely hope that we have succeeded in discovering or understanding every important reference to political theory, and we shall be very grateful to any one who may enable us to supplement or correct our judgment upon any aspect of the subject.






PREFACE TO VOLUME I.


While I am alone responsible for the judgments which are expressed in this volume, it would have been impossible for me to prepare it without the work which my brother has already completed on the political literature of the eleventh, twelfth, and thirteenth centuries. I must express my in- debtedness first of all to my friend the Eev. J. M. Schulhof, M.A., of Clare College, Cambridge, and Exeter College, Oxford, who has read through the whole of the proofs, and to whose learning and careful correction I owe the removal of many serious mistakes. But I must also express my most sincere gratitude to Mr A. J. Greenidge, Lecturer in Ancient History at Brasenose and Hertford Colleges, Oxford, who has read the proofs of Parts I. and II. of this volume; to the Eev. F. E. > Brightman, Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford, who has read most of Part III. ; to Mr H. W. C. Davis, Fellow and Tutor of Balliol College, Oxford, who has read Part IV. ; and to the Kev. J. N. Figgis, formerly Chaplain and Lecturer of St Catharine's College, Cambridge, who has read a large part of the work. These gentlemen are not responsible in any degree for the judgments expressed in this volume, but I am under great obligations to them for many important corrections and suggestions.

A. J. CAELYLE.










CONTENTS OF THE FIRST VOLUME.


PART I.

INTRODUCTION. CHAPTER I.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OP CICERO.

Continuity of ancient and modem political theory, 1— Cicero and Seneca as representing the political theory of the later Republic and early Empire, 3 — Cicero's theory of justice and natural law, 4 — his dogmatic assertion of equality of human nature, 6 — origin of the State, 13— definition of the State, and meaning of political liberty, 14 — summary of the more im- portant aspects of Cicero's political theory, 17.

CHAPTER II.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF SENECA.

General similarity to that of Cicero, 19 — the equality of human nature, and its relation to slavery, 20 — contrast between the conventional and the primitive conditions of society, the state of nature, 23 — the relation of the wise man to the State, 25 — the theory of liberty and the best government, 29 — the divine source of political authority, 30.


PAET II.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE ROMAN LAWYERS. CHAPTER III.

THE THEORY OF THE LAW OF NATURE.

The Digest and Institutes of Justinian and their influence on mediaeval political theory, 33 — Gains' theory of the jus gentium, 36 — distinction between the jus ncUurale and the jus gentium in Ulpian and others, 39 — relation of this distinction to the theory of a state of nature, 42.


LjOOQ IC 


X: -^ CONTENTS.

CHAPTER IV.

BLAVERT AND PROPERTY,

Theory of the natural equality and liberty of human nature, 45 — the limitation of rights of masters over slaves, 48-— the origin of property, 51 — ^private property a natural and. primitive institution, 62 — doubtful position of Hermogenianus, 53.

CHAPTER V.

THE THEORY OF THE CIVIL LAW.

Gains and Marcianus hold that civil law is the application of the general principles of justice to the circumstances of a particular community, 55— Ulpian's definitions of jtis and juris prudentia represent the same concep- tion, 57 — ^ambiguous phrases of Ulpian and Paulus, 58 — the theory of the jurists the same as that of Cicero and the Stoics, 61.


CHAPTER VI.

THE SOURCE OF POLITICAL AUTHORITY.

The theory of the jurists and the social contract, 63 — ^Ulpian's phrase deriving the authority of the Emperor from the Roman populus represents the view of the jurists from the second century to the sixth, 64 — Julianus, 64 — Gains, 65 — Pomponius, 66— Marcianus and Papinian, 68 — Theodosius and Valentinian, 69 — Justinian, 69 — divine source of authority of govern- ment, 69.

CHAPTER VII.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF JUSTINIAN's INSTITUTES.

The Institutes enable us to judge of the permanent tendencies of the Roman jurisprudence, 71—^^ theory of the jus naturaU and the jus gentium, 71 — theory of the primitive state, 75— slavery, property, civil law, source of political authority, 76 — summary of the most important elements in the political theory of the jurists, 77.






CONTENTS. XI


PAET III.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS.

CHAPTER VIIL

THE POLITICAL THEORY OP THE NEW TESTAMENT.

Need of care in estimating the influence of Christianity on political theory, 81 i^

— theory of the natural law, 82— the equality of human nature, 83 — theory of slavery, 85 — the divine character and the end of government, 1/^89 — relation of the Christian Church to the. Emniirpi, 91 — anarchical elements in primitive Christianity, ^3 — relation of the Christian theory of the State to the philosophical, 97— theory of private property, 98.

CHAPTER IX.

NATURAL LAW.

Political theory of the Fathers in the main homogeneous, 102 — ^natural law in the Fathers has the same character as in Cicero, 102 — ^they connect this with St Paul's phrases in the Epistle to the Romans, 105 — St Isidore adopts the distinction between the jus naturale and the ju8 gentium: through him this passes into the theory of the Middle Ages, 106.

CHAPTER X.

NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY.

The Fathers in the main carry on the conceptions of the New Testament and the contemporary philosophers. 111 — summary of this in a passage of Ambrosiaster, 112 — men are by nature free and equal, 114 — this equality and freedom in one sense permanent ; the soul is always free, 115 — ^slavery is not unlawful ; it is caused by sin, and is a system of remedial discipline, 116 — the Church recognises and sanctions the existence of slavery, 120 — masters are responsible for the spiritual wellbeing of their slaves, 123 — influence of the Church continues to mitigate the hardships of slavery, 123.


CHAPTER XI.

NATURAL EQUALITY AND GOVERNMENT.

Man is by nature sociable, 125 — coercive government of man by man is not natural or primitive, 126 — this is the consequence of sin, and a divine remedy for sin, 128.


^






1/


1/


y


XII CONTENTS.

CHAPTER XII.

THE THEORY OP PROPERTY.

Uncertainty as to theory of early Fathers, 132 — later Fathers treat private property as lawful, but not primitive or natural, 135— limitation of rights of property ; almsgiving an act of justice, not of charity, 137 — relation of this conception to the theory of property in St Thomas Aquinas, 139 — St Augustine's treatment of private property, an institution of positive human law, 139 — St Isidore of Seville's treatment of private property, interpretation uncertain, 142 — summary of patristic theory of slavery, government, and property in relation to distinction between the natural and the conventional state, 144.

CHAPTER XIII.

THE SACRED AUTHORITY OP THE RULER.

The civil ruler the representative of God, 147 — Ambrosiaster's phrase, "the Vicar of God," 149 — he is God's representative whether he is just or unjust,. 150 — St Gregory the Great and the theory of the " Divine Right," 152 — question whether this theory influenced St Gregory's conduct towards the Emperor, 153 — circumstances under which the theory grew up ; anarchism in early Christian societies, 157 — ^patronage of the Church by Constantino and his successors, 158 — influence of Old Testament con- ception of the "Lord's anointed," 158.

CHAPTER XIV.

AUTHORITY AND JUSTICE.

. The normal view of the Fathers, the end of the State is justice, 161 — emphatic assertion of this by St Ambrose, 162 — St Augustine's theory of the State, 164 — eliminates the elements of law and justice from Cicero's definition of the State, 165 — St Augustine's view does not represent the normal theory of the Fathers, nor has it much influence on the Middle Ages, 168 — Cassiodorus lays much stress on justice, 170 — St Isidore's definition of the State agrees with Cicero's, 171 — his clear distinction between the king and the tyrant, 172 — the theory of justice counteracts that of the " Divine Right," 174.

CHAPTER XV.

THE THEORY OP THE RELATION OP CHURCH AND STATE.

Relation of this subject to political theory, 175 — conversion of Constantino made the subject important, 176 — normally churchmen refuse to recognise any authority of secular ruler in Church matters (Rufinus, Hosius, Lucifer of Cagliari), 176 — ambiguous phrases of Optatus and Ambrosiaster, 178 — persecution did actually tend to make the secular ruler an arbiter in






CONTENTS. XIU

Church disputes, 179 — St Ambrose's treatment of subject, civil ruler subject to Church discipline, 180 — civil ruler has no jurisdiction in spiritual matters, 182 — rights of Church property, 182 — definition of relations of Church and State in fifth century, 184 — Emperor has no ^/^ authority in spiritual matters, and is subject to Church authority in such things, 186 — definitions of Pope Celasius I., 190 — the authorities of Church and State are divine, co-ordinate, and each independent of the other in its own sphere, subject in the sphere of the other, 191.


PART IV.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE NINTH CENTURY. CHAPTER XVI.

NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY.

Comparison of the character of political theory of ninth century with that of the Fathers, 195 — equality of human nature, 199 — theory of slavery the same as that of the Fathers, 201 — emphatic sanction of slavery by Church in the ninth century, 204 — influence of the Church continues to make for mitigation of conditions of slavery, 208 — Smaragdus Abbas desires abolition of slavery, 208.

CHAPTER XVII.

THE DIVINE AUTHORITY OP THE KING.

Government a consequence of sin, but a divine institution, 210 — origin of ^^ society and the State, 211 — Hincmar of Rheims, &c., on divine nature of civil power, 212 — significance of phrases, "King by divine grace," &c., and of consecration of kings and emperors, 214 — the king is the ** Vicar of God," 215 — rebellion against the king is rebellion against God, 216.

CHAPTER XVIII.

THE THEORY OF THE KING AND JUSTICE.

The writers of the ninth century use the language of St Gregory the Great, but their actual theory of the State is different, 219 — influence of St Isidore's definition of the king and the tyrant, 221 — influence of the treatise, *De Duodecim Abusivis Sjeculi,* 222 — political treatises of the century largely made up of admonitions to the king to follow after justice, 224— strong phrases of Hincmar of Rheims and Sedulius Scotus, 227.


1^






V


v/


XIV CONTENTS.

CHAPTER XIX.

THE KING AND THE LAW.

Justice embodied in the law, 229 — Hincmar of Rheims looks upon the king as bound by the law, 230 — the law in the ninth century is the law of the nation, not merely of the king: difiference between this conception and that of Roman jurists, 234 — formulas of legislation in the ninth century, 236— '^Quoniam lex consensu populi et constitutione regis fit," 238.

CHAPTER XX.

THE THEORY OF THE SOURCE AND CONDITIONS OF AUTHORITY IN THE STATE.

Theory of succession and election in the ninth century, 240 — ^an apparently doubtful case, the "Divisio Regnorum" of Charles the Great, 241 — normal arrangement of ninth century, election with mutual promises of king and people, 242 — this almost amounts to a compact in some cases, 244 — renewals of these statements of mutual obligation in times of trouble, 246 — notion that the king may be compelled to keep his promises,

aiinnn of ^^pfty^r nr king, 250.

CHAPTER XXI.

THE RELATION OF THE AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE.

The theory of the ninth century founded on the definitions of Pope Gelasius L, 253 — important comments on these, 255 — complexity of actual relations of the two authorities in the ninth century, 257 — good illustration of con- sequent complexity of theory in Sedulius and Cathulf us, 258 — ^illustrations of authority of civil ruler over ecclesiasucs : the king the ** Vicar of God " in the government of His Church (this implies responsibility of king for good order in the Church), 261 — this extends apparently in some sense to papacy, 263 — authority of the king in summoning 83aiods and issuing canons, 265 — authority of the king in appointment of ecclesiastics, 267 — relation of the Emperor to papal elections, 271 — illustrations of authority of ecclesiastics over civil ruler ; the Bishops, the ** Vicars of God," have authority over men of every rank, 273 — the king subject to the canon law: nature of its authority, 275 — emperor and king subject to excom- munication, 278 — authority of ecclesiastics in protection of the oppressed, 280 — authority of Popes and bishops in appointment and deposition of kings and emperors, importance of unction, 282 — the theory of the ninth century remains that the two powers were independent, 287 — the " I Qonati on 'L ^ Qonatantine^ misunderstood in later middle ages ; its real purpose probably was to secure reversion of Byzantine VterritotSs in Italy to the^ Pope, 287 — general summary of the political theory of the ninth century, 290.


Index 293






TEXTS OF AUTHORS REFERRED TO IN VOLUME I.


Ado of Yienne, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 123.

St Agobard of Lyons, Monumenta Germaniae Historica, Epistolae, v.

Alcuin, Opera, Migne Patrologia Latiua, vols. 100, 101.

Epistolae, Monumenta Germaniae Historica, Epistolae, iv.

Alexander of Hales. O)loni8e Agrippinse, 1622.

St Ambrose, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 14-17.

Ambrosiaster, Commentaries on St Paul's Epistles, in St Ambrose, Migne

Patrologia Latina, vol. 17. Qusestiones Veteris et Novi Testamenti, in St Augustine, Migne

Patrologia Latina, vol. 35. Apostolical Canons, Canones Apostolorum et Conciliorum. Ed. H. T.

Bruns. St Augustine, Opera, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 32-47.

De Civitate Dei. Ed. B. Dombart (Teubner).

Pseudo- Augustine, in St Augustine, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 39.

St Barnabas, Patrum Apostolicorum Opera. Ed. O. Gebhardt, A. Har- nack, and T. Zahn.

Cassiodorus, Opera, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 69, 70.

Varia, Monumenta Germaniae Historica, Auctorum Antiquissi-

morum, xii. Cathulfus, Monumenta Germanise Historica, Epistolae, iv. acero. Ed. C. F. W. Mueller (Teubner). Clement of Alexandria, Migne Patrologia Graeca, vols. 8, 9. St Clement of Borne, Patrum Apostolicorum Opera. Ed. O. Gebhardt,

A. Hamack, and T. Zahn. Codex Ecclesiae Africanae, Canones Apostolorum et Conciliorum. Ed.

H. T. Bruns. Codex of Justinian, Corpus Juris Civilis. Ed. P. Erueger. Council of Aries, Mansi, Councils, vol. xiv.






XVI TEXTS OF AUTHORS REFERRED TO IN VOL. I.

Council of Frankfort, Mansi, Councils, vol. xiil, and Monumenta Ger- manise Historica Legum, sect, ii vol. 1.

Council of Qangrse, Canones Apostolorum et Conciliorum. Ed. H. T. Bruns.

Councils of Toledo, Canones Apostolorum et Conciliorum. Ed. H. T. Bruns.

St Cyprian. Ed. G. Hartel.

De Duodecim Abusivis Sseculi, in St Cyprian. Ed. G. Hartel, voL 3. Digest of Justinian, Corpus Juris Civilis. Ed. Th. Mommsen. Diogenes Laertius. Ed. G. C. Cobet.

Felix II., Epistolae Eomanorum Pontificum . . . A. S. Hilaro usque ad

Pelagium II. Ed. Thiel. Florus Diaconus, Migne Patrologia Latina, voL 119.

Gaius, Institutes. Ed. P. Ejrueger et G. Studemund, 1900.

Gelasius I., Epistolae Eomanorum Pontificum . . . A. S. Hilaro usque ad

Pelagium II. Ed. Thiel. Gratian, Decretum, Corpus Juris Canonici. Ed. A. Friedberg. St Gl'egory the Great, Opera Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 75-79. Epistolse, Monumenta Germanise Historica, Epistolse, i. and ii.

Hadrian I., Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 96.

Monumenta Germanise Historica, Epistolse, iii. Codex Carolinus.

St Hilary of Poitiers, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 9, 10. Hincmar of Eheims, Opera, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 125, 126.

De Ordine Palatii, Monumenta Germanise Historica, Legum, sect

ii. vol. 2. Hosius of Cordova, in St Athanasius,Opera, Migne Patrologia Grseca, vol.ii. Hrabanus Maurus, Opera, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 107-112. Epistolse, Monumenta Germanise Historica, Epistolse, v.

Institutes of Justinian, Corpus Juris Civilis. Ed. P. Krueger. St Irenseus, Migne Patrologia Grseca, vol. 7. St Isidore of Seville, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 81-84. Pseudo-Isidore, Decretales Pseudo-Isidorianse. Ed. P. Hinschius.

St Jerome, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 22-30. Jonas of Orleans, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 106. Justin Martyr, Migne Patrologia Grseca, vol. 6.

Lactantius, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 6, 7.

St Leo I., Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 54-56.

Leo III., Monumenta Germanise Historica, Epistolse, v.

Leo IV., Monumenta Germanise Historica, Epistolse, v.

Liber Pontificalis. Ed. L. Duchesne.

Lucifer of Cagliari, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 13.






TEXTS OF AUTHORS REFERRED TO IN VOL. I. XVU

Marculfus, Formulae, Monumenta Germanise Historica, Legom, sect. v. Minucius Felix, Octavius, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 3. Monumenta Germanise Historica, Auctores Antiqoissimi, qoarta — — Diplomata, qoarto.

Epistolse, quarto.

— Leges, quarto. Scriptores, folio.

New Testament, Bevised Version.

Novels of Justinian, Corpus Juris Civilis. Ed. R. Schoell and G. Kroll.

St Optatus of Milevis, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 11. Origen, Migne Patrologia Graeca, vols. 11-17.

Plato. Ed. M. Wohlrab (Teubner). Pliny. Ed. H. Keil (Teubner). Plutarch. Ed. G. N. Bernardakis (Teubner). Polybius. Ed. T. Buttner-Wobst (Teubner).

Bufinus of Aquileia, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 21.

Salvian, Monumenta Germanise Historica, Auctorum Antiquissimorum, i. 1. Sedulius Scotus, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 103. Seneca, Opera. Ed. F. Haase (Teubner).

Epistolse. Ed. O. Hense (Teubner).

Smaragdus Abbas, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 102. Stobseus. Ed. A. Meineke (Teubner).

Teaching of the Twelve Apostles, or^Didache. Ed. A. Harnack, 1886. Tertullian, Migne Patrologia Latina, vols. 1-3. Theophilus of Antioch, Migne Patrologia Graeca, vol. 6. St Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica. Romae, Ex Typographia Senatus, 1886.

St Zeno of Verona, Migne Patrologia Latina, vol. 11.






ERRATA.

, 29, notes 2 and 3, transpose numeration.

86, 1. 1, for second century read second and third centuries.

86, 1. 31, for second century read second and third centuries.

48, n. 1, coL 2, 1. 8, after recte insert fit.

52, 1. 11, for law of nature read law of nations.

65, n. 3, col. 1, 1. 2, for autens read autem.

65, n. 3, col. 2, L 6, for quae read quia.

71, 1. 16, for second century read second and third centuries.

140, n. 1, col. 1, 1. 11, for leguatis read legatis.

150, n. 1, col. 2, L 20, for indicium read judicium, and so also va I, 22. 156, n. 1, col. 1, 1. 81, for Corcyritan read Corcyritani.

170, 1. 25, for that the ruler is God's minister to secure justice

read that it is the ruler whose commands are just who is to be obeyed.

171, n. 1, col. 1, 1. 18, for indicium read judicium. 182, n. 1, for p. 181 read p. 180.

207, n. 1, col. 2, 1. 6, for dediguentur read dedignentur. 228, n. 2, for bidi ut ursi read rabidi ut ursL

268, n. 2, col. 1, 1. 7, for talen read talem.






PART I. INTRODUCTION.


CHAPTER I.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF CICERO.

Between the active and profound political thought of Plato and Aristotle and the energetic political speculation of modem times there lies a great interval of time and an almost equally great interval of character. It has often been thought that between these periods there was no such thing as a living and active political theory. It has been thought that with the disappearance of the free Greek communities political specula- tion became wholly abstract and lifeless ; that the freedom of men's political thought was first crushed by the weight of the great empires, and then lost in the confusion of the barbaric invasions in which the ancient civilisation perished, and that in the sixteenth century political theory arose suddenly and without any immediate antecedents, being grounded in part upon original reflection, abstract or related to actual political conditions, and in part on the recovery of ancient philosophy. Such judgments, we are aware, have long ceased to be held by those who have any acquaintance with the characteristics of mediaeval thought, and have been corrected by the work of several writers, especially in England by Mr B. L. Poole in his 'Illustrations of Mediaeval Thought'; but they still con- tinue to affect the judgment of many, and even those who are

VOL. I. A






2 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

aware that in the Middle Ages political thought was both active and closely related to the actual conditions of society have yet no very clear conception of the relations of the mediaeval theory to the ancient, or of the dependence of modern theory upon the mediaeval.

We think that the conception of the disappearance of a living political theory in the Middle Ages is fundamentally wrong, and that the more closely the political conceptions of the Middle Ages are examined, the more clear will it become that there is no such gulf between ancient and modern political thought as has been imagined. There are, no doubt, profound differences between the ancient mode of thought and the modern, — the civilisation of the ancient world is very dififerent from that of the modern; but, just as it is now recognised that modern civilisation has grown out of the ancient, even so we think it will be found that modern political theory has arisen by a slow process of development out of the political theory of the ancient world, — that, at least from the lawyers of the second century to the theorists of the French Eevolu- tion, the history of political thought is continuous, changing in form, modified in content, but still the same in its funda- mental conceptions.

We are indeed conscious of the fact that between Aristotle and the Eoman Lawyers there are profound dififerences, and we would suggest that if there did exist anywhere a real break in the continuity of political thought, it would be found to lie here. We feel, indeed, that the inquiry on which we are setting out should have begun with the successors of Aristotle and Plato, and that there is thus an important omission in our discussion. But the subject of the later forms of Greek Phil- osophy is one which can only be adequately handled by those who are intimately acquainted with the greater philosophic literature of Greece, and we can scarcely pretend to this know- ledge. We hope that some philosophic scholar will before long undertake this task ; and we anticipate that under such a care- ful investigation much which is at present obscure in the transitions of thought will be explained, and that, while the fact of a great change in political theory during these cen-






CHAP. I.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OP CICERO. 3

turies will remain clear, the process of thought by which these changes came about will be found capable of explanation.

The political theory of the Middle Ages is founded upon the theory represented by the Boman Lawyers from the second to the sixth century, and by the Christian Fathers from the second to the seventh century, while it is modified by the constitu- tional traditions and customs of the Teutonic races. We there- fore have to begin our work with an examination of the political theory of the Koman Lawyers. We shall next consider the political theory of the Fathers, endeavouring to estimate the influence of distinctively Christian conceptions upon this. But before dealing with these subjects we must make some inquiry as to the antecedents of these political conceptions. A com- plete examination of these would involve that careful study of the chsuracter of the post- Aristotelian philosophy of which we have spoken. In the absence of this we must content ourselves with an examination of one or two Latin writers in whom we can, as it appears to us, trace the development of a good many of the characteristic conceptions of the Lawyers and the Fathers. Cicero has left to us in the fragments of the ' De Republica ' and in his treatise ' De Legibus ' a very interesting and significant account of the political theory fashionable in the first century before our era; while Seneca's writings serve to illustrate some general tendencies of political thought one hundred years later. With the assistance of these writers we can in some measure reconstruct the general outlines of the political conceptions which influenced the Lawyers and the Fathers. We can at least learn from them the commonplaces of political philosophy in their days, the notions current among the educated men of the period.

Cicero is a political writer of great interest, not because he possesses any great originality of mind, or any great power of political analysis, but rather because, in the eclectic fashion of an amateur philosopher, he sums up the commonplaces of the political theory of his time. We feel in reading him that, while he has no special contribution of his own to make to philosophy, he is really as interesting to us as if he had been able to do






4 INTRODUCTION. [pART I.

this. For, when we read him, we feel that we learn not so much what Cicero thought as what was generally current in his time ; we learn how the honourable and right-minded and reasonably intelligent politician of his time tended to think, what were the conceptions which the public of that time would have applauded as being just and edifying with regard to the nature of society and the principles underlying social relations. We find these ideas expressed not in any very profound fashion, but with grace, with considerable clearness at least on the surface, and with an abundant and often impressive rhetorical eloquence.

Among the fragments of Cicero's *Eepublic' which St Augustine has preserved for us in the * De Civitate Dei ' none is more important than a passage which comes, he says, from the end of the second book of the 'Eepublic.'^ He tells us that in Cicero's Dialogue Philus requests that the subject of justice should be carefully discussed, especially because it was a common saying of the time that injustice was neces- sarily involved in the administration of the commonwealth. Scipio agrees to do this, and lays it down that no progress can be made with the discussion of the nature of the State until it is recognised, not only that the popular saying is false, but rather that the truth is that it is impossible for the State to have any existence at all unless it is founded upon and repre- sents the highest justice. It is this conception which is ex- pressed in the definition of the State propounded by Scipio : * " £es publica, res populi, populus autem non omnis hominum coetus quoquo modo congregatus, sed coetus multitudinis juris consensu et utiUtatis communione sociatus." The common- wealth is the affair of the people, but the people is not any assemblage of men, gathered together in any fashion, but a gathering of the multitude united together under a common law and in the enjoyment of a common wellbeing.

Augustine in another passage comments on this definition, and asserts that Cicero defines the meaning of juris consensu " when he says that the State cannot exist without justice:

1 De Civ. Dei, ii. 21 ; Cicero, De Rep., ii. 43. 44, 8 De Rep., i 25. 39.






CHAP. I.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OP CICERO. 5

where there is no justice there can be no jus, and therefore no popvltLS, but only a nuimtttde which is not worthy of the name otpopvZus^ On these grounds, he elsewhere says» Cicero main- tained that when the government is unjust, whether a tyranny, an oligarchy, or a democracy, there is no res pvUica at all ; an unjust government is not merely evil and injurious, but de- stroys the very being of the State.*

Justice is, then, the foundation of law and of organised society, and Cicero is concerned to explain that he means by justice something which is wholly independent in its character of the consent of man. Cicero appears to have cited Cameades as maintaining that laws only arise out of the experience of utility, and that thus they continually vary in different places and times ; that there is no such thing as jus naturale ; that, properly speaking, there is no such thing as justice, or else that justice is mere foolishness, and the only source of virtue is human agreement.^ Cicero is as much shocked at these sentiments as any modem politician of respectable character would be, and denounces the theory of utility as the foundation of justice with much warmth and eloquence. It is not utility / / but nature^ which is the source of justice and law.* Cicero is " *^ clearly maintaining the same view of justice as that of Chry- si^us and the other Stoics as cited by Stobseus ^ and Plutarch,® . in opposition to the theory of Epicurus ^ and such thinkers as Carneades, who maintained that justice was the name for a convention devised among men for the advancement of their own utility.

Justice is a principle of nature, a principle which lies behind all the order of the world, the expression of a universal prin- . ciple or law of nature — the ultimate principle behind all law. Lactantius has preserved for us a passage from the *De Re- publica,' in which Cicero has with some real eloquence de- scribed this. There is a law which is the same as true reason accordant with nature, a law which is constant and eternal,

1 De Civ., xix. 21. ii. 18. ^

2 De Civ., iL 21. ' Stobaeus, EcL, ii. 184.

3 Lactantius, Div. Inst., v. 17 ; * Plutarch, De Stoic. Rep., 9. Cicero, De Rep., iii. 12. 21. ^ Diog. Laert, x. 150.

  • De Leg., i. 14.-16. Cf. De Finibus,






6 INTRODUCTION. [part i,

which calls and commands to duty, which warns and terrifies men from the practice of deceit This law is not one thing at Bome, another at Athens, but is eternal and immutable, the expression of the command and sovereignty of God.^ In his treatise on laws, Cicero carefully points out that all civil law is but the expression or application of this eternal law of nature. That which is not derived from it may have the formal character of law but not its true character. The people or the prince may make laws, but they have not the true character of jvs unless they are derived from the ultimate . law. The original source and the foundation of jus must be studied in that supreme law which came into being ages before any State existed.^

It is important, we think, to observe with some care this emphatic exposition of the principle and character of the law of nature. Cicero's treatment may leave a good deal to be desired in point of clear analysis, — ^we may indeed doubt whether Cicero had himself a clear conception of the subject with which he is dealing. But we think that we have said enough to show both the importance of the theory of natural law in the current philosophical system with which Cicero was in sympathy, and also the close relation of this conception to the theory of justice. The theory of natural law is to Cicero the form of the theory of justice in society, and it is also the groundwork upon which the whole structure of human society rests. Human society is founded upon nature; its cause is "naturalis qusedam hominum quasi congregatio." *

We may feel that while Cicero's treatment of the law of nature represents a stronger emphasis upon the conception than that which is characteristic of older thinkers, he does not do much more than develop conceptions which belonged to them* It is very different with the subject which we must next con- sider, Cicero's theory of human nature and its relation to the institutions of society.

^ Lactantius, Div. Inst., vi. 8 ; De 42 ; 16. 45. Of. De L^., ii. 4. Bep., iii. 22. ' De Rep., i. 25. 39.

» De Leg., i. 6. 19, 20; 10. 28; 15.






CfHAP. I.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OP CICERO. 7

There is no conception which is more fundamental to the Aristotelian theory of society than the notion of the natural inequality of human nature. Upon this turns not only his theory of slavery but also his theory of Government. To Aris- totle the institution of slavery is a necessary condition of civil- ised life and of a civilised social order, and it is natural, because there are some men so inferior to their fellows as to be natur- ally servila And again, to Aristotle the government of civil- ised society is always the expression of the superiority of some men over others. The most ideal government is that of the best man over his inferiors, next to that is the government of the aristocracy ; but even his ideal commonwealth is the rule of a small body of citizens, approximately equal in capacity and education, over a great unenfranchised multitude of inferiors, mechanical persons and slaves. It is a presupposition of his commonwealth that there should be a reasonable equality of virtue and capacity among all the citizens, or at least such a measure of it as, under a pareful system of public education, will render every citizen moderately competent for the dis- charge of public duties. But this equality is confined to the small body of the citizens: the great majority of the persons included in the commonwealth are wholly inferior to the citizens and incompetent for the responsibilities of public duty. By nature some men are fit for rule, others only for subjection. There is a naturally servile class, possessing only a small share of reason, enough only to render obedience to the developed reason of others. True excellence or virtue is not within the reach of all, but belongs only to a few.

These presuppositions of the Aristotelian theory arose natur- ally from the circumstances of Greek civilisation, though they had been questioned by some writers before Aristotle. In general culture, and perhaps even more in political culture, the Greek belonged to a different world from the races which surrounded him. The distinction between the Greek and the barbarian might be exaggerated by the Greek, but the diflfer- ence was real and profound. In art, in letters, in philosophy the Greek was not merely different from those who surrounded him, but belonged to another order. And in political matters






8 INTRODUCTION. [part L

the subjects of the barbaric despotisms of the East might well seem to the Greek citizen to confess their naturally servile character, for they did not even possess or desire to possess the political responsibility of the Greek citizen. Centuries after- wards we find a citizen of the Boman Commonwealth laying it down that the Boman Emperor was the lord of free men, while the barbarian ruler was the master of slaves.^ What Gregory the Great could say in the decline of the Boman Empire with truth of sentiment the citizen of the free Greek i^te felt as true in every fibre of his being.

There is no change in political theory so startling in its com-^ pleteness as the change from the theory of Aristotle to the later philosophical view represented by Cicero and Seneca. Over against Aristotle's view of the natural inequality of human nature we find set out the theory of the natural equality of human nature. There is no reseniblance in nature so great as that between man and man, there is no equality so complete. There is only one possible definition for all mankind, reason is common to all ; men differ indeed in learning, but are equal in the capacity for learning. There is no race which under the guidance of nature cannot attain to virtue. The same virtues are pleasing, the same vices are detestable to all nations; all men can be made better by learning the true conception of life. It is only the perversions which depraved habit and foolish conceptions have brought, which cause men to differ so much from each other. Nature has given to all men reason, that is, true reason, and therefore the true law, which is right reason commanding and forbidding.^ We shall see later how these

^ St Gregory the Great, Ep. xiii. 34. nosmet ipsos sumus. Quodsi depravatio

'^ De Leg., i. 10. 28-12. 33 : consuetudinum, si opinionum vanitas

" M, Sunt h89c quidem magna, non inbecillitatem animorum torqueret

quae nunc breviter attinguntur, sed et flecteret, quocumque coepisaet, sui

omnium, quae in hominum doctorum nemo ipse tarn similis esset, qiiam

disputation* versantur, nihil est pro- omnes essent omnium. Itaque, quse-

f ecto prsestabilius quam plane intellegi cumque est hominis definitio, una in

nos ad justitiam esse natos, neque onmis valet; quod argumenti satis est

opinione, sed m^tura constitutum esse nuUam dissimilitudinem esse in genere ;

jus. Id jam patebit, si hominum inter quae si esset, non una omnis definitio

ipsos societatem conjunctionemque per- contineret ; etenim ratio, qua una

spexeris. Nihil est enim unum uni tam prsestamus beluis, per quam conjectura

simile, tam par, quam omnes inter valemus, argumentamur, refeUimus,






CHAP l] the POUTICAL theory op CICERO-


9


sweeping generalisations recur in Seneca, and it can scarcely be doubted that we have here presented to ui the foundation of those dogmatic statements of the lawyers like Ulpian and Florentinus/ in which all men are presented to us as being by nature free, by nature equal. We are indeed at the b^^innings of a theory of human nature and society of which the Liberty Equality, and Fraternity " of the French Eevolution is only the present-day expression. To complete the parallelism of the conception, we may observe that the " Fraternity " of the Eev- olution is only a later form of Cicero's phrase,* " By nature we are disposed to love men ; this is the foundation of law."

We have ventured to suggest that the dividing-line between the ancient and the modem political theory must be sought, if anywhere, in the period between Aristotle and Cicero. We think that this cannot be better exemplified than with regard to the theory of the equality of human nature. Further on we shall have occasion to examine the relation of Christianity to this conception, but in the meanwhile it must be noticed that the appearance of this conception is not consequent upon Christ-


disserimuB, conficimus aliquid, con- cludimus, certe est communis, doctrina differens, discendi quidem facultate par. Kam et sensibus eadem omnia compre- henduntur, et ea, quae movent sensus itidem movent omnium, quseque in animis imprimuntur, de quibus ante dizi, inchoatse intellegentise, Bimiliter in omnibus inprimuntur, interpresque mentis oratio verbis discrepat sententiis oongruens ; nee est quisquam gentis uUius, qui ducem nactus ad virtutem pervenire non possit.

Nee solum in rectis, sed etiam in pravitatibus insignis est humani generis similitudo. . . . Quae autem natio non comitatem, non benignitatem, non gratum animum et beneficii memorem diligit? quae superbos, quae maleficos, quae crudeles, quae ingratos non asper- natur, non edit? Quibus ex rebus quom omne genus hominumsociatum in- ter se esse intellegatur, illud extremum est> quod recte vivendi ratio meliores efficit. Quae si adprobatis, pergam


ad reliqua ; sin quid requiritis, id ex- plioemus prius. AU» Nos vero nihil, ut pro utroque respondeam.

"M. Sequitur igitur ad participan- dum alium alio communicandumque inter omnes jus nos natura esse factos. Atque hoc in omni hac disputatione sic inteUegi volo, jus quod dicam, natura esse, tantam autem esse cor- ruptelam malae consuetudinis, ut ab ea tamquam igniculi extinguantur a natura .dati exorianturque et con- firmentur vitia contraria. Quod si, quo modo est natura, sic judicio homines * humani,' ut ait poeta, * nihil a se alienum putarent,' coleretur jus aeque ab omnibus. Quibus enim ratio a natura data est, isdem etiam recta ratio data est, ergo etiam lex, quae est recta ratio in jubendo et vetando ; si lex, jus quoque ; et omnibus ratio ; jus igitur datum est omnibus."

1 Dig., 11. 4 ; i. 5. 4 ; 1. 17. 32.

a De Leg., i. 15. 43.


/






1


10 INTRODUCTION. [pabt I.

ianity, however true it may be that the progressive translation of this great abstract conception into such measure of practical reality as it may now possess has been largely carried out under its influence.

Cicero already speaks with the cosmopolitan accent of modern civilisation ; to him the older conception of an absolute natural difference between the civilised man and the barbarian has become impossible. It is not diflBcult to recognise the historical circum* stances which probably were in the main instrumental in pro- ducing this change. With the rise of the Macedonian Empire, the intense but restricted culture of the Greeks became the culture of the world, losing much no doubt in intensity as it gained in expansion. The Greek went out into the world, and found that the barbarian whom he had thought to be incapable of rational cultivation was at least capable of reproducing his own culture. The conquest of the world by Hellenism had the necessary effect of changing the Hellenic conception of the world* Tl^e literature, the art, the philosophy of the Hellenic world might be on a lower plane than that of the Hellenic city, but it was Hellenic. If the Greek himself was thus compelled to admit that the barbarian was capable of entering into the commonwealth of Greek civilisation, if the Macedonian Empire convinced the philosophers of the homogeneity of the human race, this was necessarily and even more definitely the conse- quence of the Eoman Empire. The Latin conqueror indeed was himself, to the Greek, one of the barbarians, and more or less the Latin recognised this, — more or less he was compelled to recognise that his intellectual and artistic culture came to him from the Greek. The Latin brought indeed, in his genius for law and administration, his own contribution to the cosmopolitan culture of the world, but that was all he brought. It was im- possible for him to imagine himself to be the man possessed of reason and capable of virtue and to deny these qualities to others. The Eoman Empire continued and carried on the work of the Macedonian Empire in welding the countries of the Mediterranean basin into one homogeneous wholS. The homogeneity of the human race was in the Eoman Empire na mere theory of the philosophers, but an actual fact of experi-






CHAP. I.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OF CICERO. 11

ence, a reality in political and social conditions. If the phil- osopher had learned to believe in the homogeneity of mankind under the Macedonian Empire, he was confirmed and strength- ened in his belief by the experience of the Boman.

When we turn to Cicero's theory of government we may find what we think are indications of the influence of this con- ception. In the meantime we may point out that while in Cicero's writings the relation between the theory of equality and the theory of slavery is not drawn out, it is still worth noting that in one passage at least Cicero refers to the con- dition of the slave in a fashion different, at least in some respects, from earlier writers. We must, he says, act justly even to those of the lowest condition — that is, the slaves — of whom it has been well said that they should be treated as hired labourers ; they should be required to work, but should receive just treatment.^ The suggestion that the slave should be regarded in the same light as a hired labourer comes from the Stoic Chrysippus, and suggests an important contrast with Aristotle's conception of the inferiority of the position of the mercenary labourer as compared with that of the slave. It is certainly worth noting that the slave is recognised to have his just rights ; he is looked upon as a man with some independent personality. When we turn to Seneca we shall find that the relations of the theory of human equality to the independent personality of the slave is more fully drawn out.

There are indeed two fragments of the * De Eepublica ' which would seem to represent a somewhat different attitude to slavery from that which we have described. In the first of these, described by St Augustine, the question is raised as to the justice of the conquest of one nation by another, and, as St Augustine reports, it is maintained that such conquest is just because subjection (servitm) is useful for some men, as tending to check the tendency to licence. In tKe second passage, Cicero, as quoted by Nonius, seems to have been^distinguishing between the unjust form of slavery, where those who are capable of being sui are alterius, and some just form, presumably when those are slaves who are incapable of governing themselves.^

1 De Offi, i. 13. 41. ^ De Rep., iii. 24 ; De Civ. Dei, xix. 21 ; De Rep., iii. 25.






12 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

There can be little doubt that in these passages we find Cicero to be speaking under the influence partly at least of the Aristotelian nrinciple of the fundamental distinction in human nature ; we nnd him thinking of mankind as capable of being divided into those who are able to govern themselves and those who are not. But we venture to think that such passages do not in any serious measure weaken the effect of those which we have already discussed. It must be remembered that Cicero's eclecticism is in part the expression of a certain incoherence in his philosophical conceptions, and that it is not a matter for any great surprise that we should find him holding together opinions hardly capable of reconciliation.

It must be observed that the first quoted passage may also be taken as indicating a tendency to one particular solution ^

of son^ of the difl&culties of social theory, which became in the course of time of the greatest importance. It will be observed that Cicero speaks of subjection as being a remedy \^' for the tendencies to licence and evil, and this conception may be connected with Cicero's theory of the actual condition of human nature. In a passage which we have already quoted, Cicero points out that men would all be like each other, were it not for the perversion caused by depraved habit and foolish thoughts. Cicero at the same moment that he dogmatically maintains the fundamental similarity of human nature, admits that this is affected by the fact that human nature is con- ^ stantly corrupted, — that this corruption brings into human life conditions and distinctions which are not truly natural. Cicero, that is, draws a distinction between the truc^rJdeSl character of man and the acti;aL Human nature is actually often corrupt and depraved^ the fire of life, of truth, is ex- tinguished, and the contrary vices grow and flourish under the influence of evil custom.^ St Augustine represents Cicero as describing men as coming into being not only bare and fragile in body, but with a soul prone to terror, weak in will to labour, prone to lust, while yet a certain divine fire dwells in them.2 Cicero's treatment of the subjection of man to man seems to anticipate the attitude of Seneca and the Fathers to ~^

1 See p. 8, note 2. ^ De Rep., iii. 1.






CHAP, l] the political theory of CICERO. 13

the institution of slavery and to the other institutions of civilised society. We can see the germs of a theory of human society which was ultimately to trace the great institutions of mankind to the necessity of checking the faults of human nature, — ^which would tend to look upon the organisation of the State as the necessary consequence of the depravity of human nature and as its true remedy. The inadequacy of this conception of the organisation of society is to our own mind sufficiently obvious, and indeed since the "Contrat Social" the tendency of political philosophy is obviously to return to the larger view of the great thinkers who look upon the organisation of society rather as the method of progre ss^ both negative and positive, than as merely'the barrier to vice and disorder. But for eighteen centuries political theorists were governed in large measure by this conception. ^Cicero^ then, maintains the theory of natural human equality, but is partly conscious that this theory has to take account of the actual facts of human diversity and corruption.

We go on to consider his theory of the origin and character of the State. It would appear that Cicero was familiar with two theories: the one, that men were by nature solitary and had no inclination to the society of their fellows, but were driven by the dangers of life to seek each other out and to join together for mutual defence ; the other, which Cicero puts in the mouth of Scipio Africanus, who emphatically repudiates this conception, and maintains that men are naturally inclined to the society of each other.^ We shall probably not be far wrong in supposing that the first view had been maintained by Cameades and probably by the Epicureans, while the view of Cicero himself is that of Aristotle and of the Stoics. We shall see that Seneca illustrates very clearly a great diverg- ence between the attitude of the Stoics and the Epicureans towards the State.

Society to Cicero is a natural institution, and the organisa* tion of society in the State is the greatest work to which a man can set his hand : human excellence never comes so near

^ De Rep., I 25. 39, 40 ; Lactantius, Div. Inst., yL 10.


V






14 INTRODUCTION^. [part I.

to the divine as when it applies itself to the foundation or • preservation of states.^ Man is naturally made for society, and ' the great society of the State has grown up gradually on the \ foundation of the elementary form of human association, the family.^ Cicero evidently follows the same tradition as Aris- totle. We also find in him a conception of the development of the State which is worthy of notice, though its importance in political theory was scarcely perceived until the historical movement at the end of the eighteenth century, when Burke

recognised its profound significance. We mean the conception

\^ of the constitution of a State as an orga nic grow th in contra* distinction to the conception of it as a mecHanical product. At the beginning of the second book of the *Kepublic'^ Cicero -says that he will rather discuss the actual constitution of the Boman Commonwealth than create one out of his own imagination, and mentions vnth approbation the opinion of dato that the reason why the Eoman constitution was superior to all otheri^ was that it had not been devised by one man's wisdom or created by one man's labours, but r ather by th e ' wisdom and efforts of ma ny generations. mSTThteresting to ^oBserveThis^judg^^ appear that it had

any direct and immediate results in political thought.

Cicero, then, conceives of the State as being the natural method of human life. But he is careful to point out with all the emphasis that he can command that the State is not any chance association of men, whatever the methods and _J objects of the association. The State to be a State must ' b§ founded ujon justice, upon law, and it must exist for the promotion of the common wellbeing of all its citizens. This is the significance of that definition of the State which we have already quoted.* The Commonwealth is the affair of all the people, but the people is not any assembly of men gathered together in any fashion, but is a gathering of the multitude associated together under xi common law and in the enjoyment of a common wellbeing. The form of the government may vary, but the foundation of the State is

1 De Rep., i. 7. 12. « pe Rep., ii. l. 1-3.

2 De OflF., i. 17. 54. . * De Rep., i. 25. 39. See p. 4.






CHAP. I.] THE POUTICAL THEORY OP CICERO. 16

always this bond of justice and the common good There must be government that the State may have continuance, but this government must always be founded upon, and express, the first principles of the association. Government may be in the hc^ds either of one person or of a chosen few or of the whole people, and it will be legitimate if that first bond u^ of association is preserved, the bond of justice and the common good, if the State is well and justly governed. But if the government is unjust, whether it is that of the king or of the few or of the people, then Cicero maintains that the State is not to be called corrupt, but rather tha t it is no • State at all. ^ Who can call that a commonwealth {res ptcblica) wKere all are oppressed by the authority of one, and where there is no bond of law, no true agreement and union ? ^ So far Cicero would seem to follow the same general line of thought as Aristotle, the legitimacy of a form of government is determined by its end ; so long as this is the wellbeing^ of all, the focm of the government is comparatively immaterial But we find also in Cicero tracjssot a conception not perhaps strictly new, but receiving a new emphasis. The three forms of government, he says, are only tolerable; he is not really satisfied with any of them. The least satisfactory foAn to him is that in which the whole power is in the hands of the people. The very equality of this is, in his judgment, unjust, since there are no grades of dignity. But he is equally dissatisfied with the mere aristocracy or monarchy; and it is here that his conception assumes a new significance. The most just aristocracy, such as that of the Massilians, or the most just monarchy, such as that of Cyrus, is to him unsatisfactory, for under such forms of government there ia^ at least an appearance of slavery, and the multitude in such ^ a State can scarcely possess liberty.*

Cicero's identification of liberty with a^ s hare in p olitica l ^ p ower is another of the indications of the essentially modern

^ De Rep., i. 26. 41, 42 ; De Rep., tamen in ea conditione Bimilitudo quse-

iii., in St Aug., De Civ., ii. 21. dam servitutis," and '*yix particeps

^ De Rep., iii. 31. libertatis potest esse multitudo.

  • De Rep., i. 26 and 27; "inest






16 INTRODUCTION. [pabt i.

character of his political thought. We seem to be at the com- mencement of that mode of thought which has been so char- acteristic of modern democracy, that political liberty is identical with the possession of the franchise, that even the best govern-

  • ment is unsatisfactory which is not directly controlled by the

people as a whole. We are not here discussing the value of this conception in political philosophy, but it is interesting to ob- serve its appearance in Cicero. When we go on to consider the theories of the Koman Lawyers, we shall have to observe the fact that they knew of no other foundation of political V/ authority than the consent of the whole people, and we shall have to consider the relation of this to the development of the theory of consent or contract as the foundation of the State. The conceptions of the Eoman Lawyers and of Cicero are both related to the traditions of the Eoman Government, to the constitutional thepryjrtiich ha^j gown up^ under the Kepublic ; but we think that they are also related to that conc eption o f the natural equality of men with which we have already dealt. Indeed it isToBvious enough that Cicero's objection to mon- archy and aristocracy rests upon this basis, that every citizen has in him some capacity for political authority, some capacity which ought to find a means of expression. Cicero is, in truth, dissatisfied with all the three simple forms of government, both on account of their inherent character and because they all have a dangerous tendency to perversion : monarchy easily passes into tyranny, aristocracy into oligarchy, and democracy into the rule of the mob.^ He is therefore himself in favour of a foutth form of government, compounded of the three simple . elements, possessing some of the virtues of each, and possessing in greater degree the quality of stability .^ His conception of this is, we have little doubt, in large measure drawn from the history of Eome, and it is not very materially different from that' of earlier writers.^

Cicero, then, looks upon the true order of the State as being

\ founded upon the principle of justice, which is expressed in the

law, and secures the common wellbeing. It should give ta

every citizen some share in the control of the public life, and

» De Rep., i. 28. 44. « De Rep., i. 45. 69. » Cf. Polybius, vi. 11.






OHAP. I.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OF CICERO. 17

provide room for the exercise and recognition of the varying qualities and capacities of the citizens. The commonwealth is an organic development out of the natural association of the family, and at the same tinle it is the expression of the common will and consent, for every citizen has his share in its control. There is one passage in the * De Republica ' ill which this conception seems to be drawn out in a manner which nearly approaches the theory of a contract^ This judgment seems to be placed in the mouth of a defender of that theory, which, as we have said, reduced justice and virtue to a matter of agreement. It is, however, interesting to observe the presence of this con- ception in the political theory of the time ; it has antecedents in such a description of the contract as that which Plato gives in the "Laws." 2

We have thus seen how important in the political theory of Cicero are the three related conceptions of natural law, natural equality, and the natural society of men in the State. Nature is the test of truth and validity in law, in social order, in or- ganised society. We do not mean that Cicero has a very clear and precise conception of the meaning of nature ; generally he seems to use it as expressing the true order of things, though once at least he seems to use it as equivalent to the primitive, undeveloped order.* But generally his conception of natural law is sufficiently distinct. Behind all actual laws and customs of men there exists a supreme and permanent law, to which all human order, if it is to have any truth or validity, must conform. • This ultimate principle is the law and will of the power which lies behind all the external forms of the universe, and it is by it that all things live, while it also manifests itself, at least in part, to the rational consciousness of men. His conception of natural equality is clear enough. All men have reason, all men are capable of virtue. His conception is clear, but the relation of his conception to actual social conditions is not

^ De Rep., iii. 13 : " Sed cum alius tentes, ex quo existit id quod Scipio

alium timet, et homo hominem, et ordo laudabat, conjunctum civitatis genus.'*

ordinem, tum quia nemo sibi confidit, ^ Plato, Laws, iii. 684.

quasi pactio fit inter populum et po- ' De Off., i. 7. 21.

VOL. I. B






18 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

developed. He has repudiated the traditional philosophical justification of slavery, but he has not considered the conse- quences of his own judgment. He has not drawn out in this connexion that distinction between the original condition of

• things and the conventions of human society which is, as we venture to think, the first meaning of the distinction made by Ulpian and the other lawyers of his school between the jus naturale and the jus gentium. On the other hand, his conception of organised society in relation to nature is well developed and clearly applied. He conceives of society as being natural to man, and of social organisation as needing to conform itself to certain principles of justice and certain characteristics of human nature, if it is to be legitimate. The State must be just and must also provide for liberty.

' Cicero's conception of nature and natural law has then its ambiguities and perhaps its incoherencies, but it is evident that it is round this conception of nature that his philosophy of society revolves. " Ex natura vivere summum bonum," to live according to nature is the highest good, he says;^ nature is

. the guide of man, the true test of justice and goodness. But nature is not found by man in solitude or in misanthropy, but in the society and the love of his fellow-man.

1 De Leg., i. 21. 56.






19


CHAPTER II.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF SENECA.

When we turn from Cicero to Seneca we find ourselves in an atmosphere of a somewhat new kind. The change from the Republic to the Empire necessarily brought with it certain changes in the idea of the State, but, what is perhaps more than this, we find in Seneca a professed philosopher of one definite school, who tries to adjust his views of life and of society to the general conceptions of that school. Seneca may not be a very profound philosopher; it is very possible to feel that he often mistakes rhetorical sentiment for profound ethical emotion, and that he has little of that power ^'of critical analysis which might have given seriousness and force to his opinions: he is too much pleased with the fine sound of his own sentiments to examine them very carefully, and carry them out to their conclusions. But still, he does repre- sent to us in a literary form, always interesting and sometimes forcible, the theory of life and society of the Stoic schools of his time, and he presents them with a certain coherence and consequence which differs not a little from Cicero's expression of the preferences of a well-mannered and honourable-minded philosophical amateur. And yet, after all, while there are important differences between Cicero and Seneca in political theory, we think that they are governed by the same general conceptions, that they illustrate different forms of the same attitude to the theory of society.

It is somewhat curious to find that Seneca rarely ij^atjill ^ refers tojiaturaHaw, that he nowhere discusses the conception of law as related to some general principle of life and the






20


INTRODUCTION.


[part I.


world. We think that this does not mean that he has a conception of things dififerent in this respect from Cicero. For while he does not use the phrase "natural law," the phrase "nature" seems to occupy much the same place in his mind. To live according to his nature is the command of reason to man.^ It is nature which teaches a man the true method of life.^ Anger is foolish, for it is not natural.^ Nature is the test of goodness, everything which is good is according to nature, though there may be things in nature too trifling to deserve the name of good.* Nature is that which is perpetual, unchanging: that which is variable cannot be truly natural.^

We may at least gather from these phrases that Seneca looks upon nature as being or containing a principle which is the test of truth and goodness, to which man must conform himself if he would find the true method and quality of life. In the main he seems to conceive of it as the permanent principle and end of life, not as identical with its primitive forms. We shall have to consider the question presently in relation to his conception of the primitive character of society, and we shall see then that while he may occasionally at least use the word " nature " as representing the primitive,^ yet his general tendency is to look upon the completest perfection of human nature in a developed society as being the true " nature " in man.


v:


The conception of human nature in Seneca's writings is very similar to that which we have studied in Cicero. The con- ception of the eqiiglity of human nature is continued and developed in greater detail, but on the same lines as in Cicero's writings. The slave is of the same nature as his master, Seneca says, and he draws out this theory with real eloquence in the De Beneficiis. Some, he says, have denied that a slave can confer a benefit upon his master. Those who think


1 Ep. iv. 12. a De Otio, v. 8. 8 De Ira, i. 6. '

  • Ep. XX. 1.


' ConBol. ad Marciam, viL 3. ^ Ep. xiv. 2. 44, "non enim dat uatura virtutem : ars est bonum fieri."






OHAP. II.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OF SENECA. 21

thus are ignorant of the true principles of human nature. It is a man's intention, not his position, which gives the quality of a benefit to his action. Virtue can be attained by all, the free, the freedman, the slave, the king, the exile: virtue cares nothing for house or fortune, but only seeks the man. A slave can be just, brave, magnanimous.^ Again, we all have the same beginnings, the same origin; no one is in truth nobler than another, except so far as his temper is more upright, his capacities better developed. We are all descended from one common parent, the world; to this we must all trtuxe our origin, whether by splendid or by humble steps.* It is fortune that makes a man a slava^ Slavery is hateful to all men ; the kindliness of a slave towards his master is therefore only the more admirable.* And, finally, slavery is after all only ex- ternal, only aflfects the body of a man: he errs greatly who thinks that the condition of slavery affects the whole man; his better part has nothing to do with it She body may belong to a master, the mind is its own (^ juris ) : it cannot be given into slavery.^

These phrases may no doubt be said to be rhetorical, and it would be foolish to overpress their practical significance, but at the same time they seem to complete the impression which Cicero's writings have given to us, of the^^great change which had come over the philosophical conception of human nature. It may indeed be urged that AriBtotle not only indicates that, even in his time, a conception of the unnatural character of slavery was already current, but even that Aristotle himself is somewhat uneasy in his judg- ment as to the institution. Still, Aristotle's conception of the profound differences in human nature had, as we have said, its basis in what might well appear to the Greek mind the actual facts of life. Seneca's treatment of human nature shows us again how completely the Aristotelian view had gone; his view of human nature is in all essentials the view of modern times. Nothing indeed could be more significant than the stress

^ De Ben., iii. 18. * De Ben., iii. 19.

a De Ben., iii. 28. * De Ben., iii. 20.

' De Ben., iii. 20.






"-^■


22 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

Seneca lays upon the freedom of the soul. It is just where Aristotle found the ground and justification of slavery that Seneca finds the place of unconquerable freedom; the body may be enslaved, the soul is free.

It must not be thought that this speculation upon slavery is wholly abstract, and haa no practical significance. Wlien we consider the theories of the lawyers, we shall have oc- casion to compare the development of their theory with the actual legal modifications of the condition of the slave. It is worth while to compare Seneca's theory of slavery with his conception of the relations of metster and slave in actual life. In one of Jiis letters he deals with the question in detail. He represents himself as having heard with pleasure from his friend that he lived on intimate terms with his slaves: he finds that such conduct is eminently worthy of his good sense and learning. He bids him remember that if they are slaves, they are humble friends, nay, rather, they are fellow- slaves. This man whom you call your slave is sprung from the same source, dwells under and rejoices in the same heaven, breathes the same air, lives the same life, dies the same death as you: you might be the slave, he the freeman. He is a slave, but perchance he is free in his soul. Who is not a slave ? one man is in bondage to his lusts, another to avarice, another to ambition, all men to their fears. live with your slaves kindly and courteously, admit them to your conver- sation, to your counsels, to your meals ; let your slave rever- ence you rather than fear you. Some may argue that your slaves will become your clients rather than slaves, that the masters will lose their dignity; surely it is enough that the master should receive the same honour as God, who is reverenced and loved.^ We may find much of merely rhetorical sentiment in all this, but sentiment is only the reflection of tlie actual conditions and tendencies of life. It has often been observed that, as Roman society lost its primitive vigour and moral quality, it also grew more human e. Certainly the development of the humane sentiment is very clear. Seneca then looks upon human nature as fundamentally the same in

1 Ep. V. 6.






CHAP. II.] THE POUTICAL THEORY OF SENECA. 23

all: we again find that we are » close to the legal theory of the original and natural equality and liberty of men.

So far Seneca illustrates the same position as Cicero. But in his case these conceptions are related to others, which Cicero ^ either passes over or rejects. Behind the conventional institu- tions of society there lay a condition in which these institutions had no place. Before the existing age there was an age when men lived under other conditions, in other circumstances, an age which was called the golden. In this primitive age men lived in happiness and in the enjoyment of each other's society. They were uncorrupt in nature, innocent, though not wise. They were lofty of soul, newly sprung from the gods, but they_were not perfect or completely developed in mind and souL They were innocent, but their innocence was rather the result of ignorance than of virtue ; they had the material out of which virtue could grow rather than virtue itself, for this properly only belongs to the soul trained and taught and practised : men a re bo rn to virtue but not in possession of it It is important to notice these points in Seneca's theory, for they serve to dififerentiate his position from that of some later theorists of the state of nature. In this primitive state men lived together in peace and happiness, having all things in common ; there was no private property. We may infer that there could have been no slavery, and there was no coercive government Order there was and that of the best kind, for men followed nature without fail, and the best and wisest men were their rulers. They guided and directed men for their good, and were gladly obeyed, as they commanded wisely and justly. The heaviest punishment they could threaten was expulsion from their territories.^

We have here a statement of that thQory_ftt. the-state gf ' nature, which was to exercise a great influence upon the whole cKaiacter of political thought for nearly eighteen centuries. It is true that the conception of the state of nature in Seneca is not the same as in some other writers ; but the importance of the theory for our inquiry lies not so much in the particular

^ Ep. xiv. 2.






V


V


24 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

forms in which men held it, as in the fact that in all forms it assumed a distinction between primitive and conventional institutions which largely influenced the ideal and sometimes even the practical tendency of men's thoughts.

Seneca does not regard this primitive condition as one of per- fection, rather as one of inagpence — we may say that he regards it as representing the undeveloped, not the developed, " nature " of man — and he is thus in sharp contradiction to those who look upon this as the " natural " condition in the full sense of the word. But still it was a state of happiness, of at least negative virtue and goodness. Men passed out of it, not through the instinct of progress, but through the growth of vice. As time passed, the primitive innocence disappeared; men became avaricious, and, dissatisfied with the common en- joyment of the good things of the world, desired to hold them in their private possession. Avarice rent the first happy society asunder. It resulted that even those who were made wealthy became poor; for desiring to possess things for their own, they ceased to possess all things. The rulers grew dis- satisfied with their paternal rule ; the lust of authority seized upon them, and the kingship of the wise gave place to tyranny, so that men had to create laws which should control the rulers.

Seneca thus looked upon the institutions of society as being theresuljfljof-wjerof the corruption of human nature: they are conventional institutions made necessary by the actual defects of human nature rather than the natural conditions of ideal progress. This point is so important in relation to later theory that it will be well to notice his conception of human nature somewhat more fully. In another of his letters he discusses the proper characteristics of human nature^ Man, he says, is a rational animal; that is his peculiar quality^ and reason bids man live according to this his true nature, a thing which ought to be most easy, but is made difl&cult by that universal madness which possesses mankind.^ And in another letter we find him carrying out this idea in sentences which remind us forcibly of Christian theology. It was a true judg- ment, he says, of Epicurus, that the beginning of salvation

1 Ep. iv. 12.






CHAP. II.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OF SENECA. 25

{salutis) is the recognition of sin. If a man does not recognise his faults, he will not be corrected ; it is idle to think of im- provement while a man confuses his evil with good. Therefore let a man accuse himself, judge himself.^

We have already seen in Cicero some traces of this theory of the corruption or faultiness of human nature ; in Seneca it is more clearly and explicitly drawn out. And if we now put this together with his theory of primitive human life, we see that SenecaVvifiw is, iQ.all impiirtant_£oints, the.samajw-that^J the A Christian Fathers, tha^jaan was once innocent and happy, but has' gfUWlTcorrupt And, further, we find that what Cicero on^^-TSUggests as the cause of the subjection of man to man, Seneca holds of the great institutions of society, property and coercive government, namely, that they are the conseq^uences of and^ the resaedigaiQU^. Private property is a necessary con- dition of a social order in which few men can rival Diogenes in his contempt for all wealth, and the best thing is that a man should have enough to keep him from poverty, but not so much as to remove him far from it.^ And in the same way organised government and law is a necessary protection against tyranny. Seneca, that is, seems clearly to draw a sharp dis- tinction between the conditions suitable to man, had he con- ^ tinned innocent, and those which are adapted to the actual facts of the perversion and corruption of human nature. The great institutions of organised society are conventions adapted to the latter conditions, good as_remedies, but not properly to be called, good in themselves. The coercive state is a great institution to which, as we shall presently see, men owe their service; but its actual form is not so much a consequence of man's true nature as a remedy for his corrupted nature.

So far Seneca's view is on the whole clear, perplexed only by the intrusion of the perpetual paradox of the promotion of good through evil ; for it must be carefully borne in mind that Seneca's prtoitixe-man^thonghJcnocent and.happy^ ^ true virtue, ' while man as we know him is oppressed by vice and misery, but is yet capable of virtue. But here we come to a point in Seneca's theory which requires careful notice, if we are not to

^ Ep. iii. 7. 2 De TraDquillitate, viii.






26 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

misapprehend him, and in which also we find interesting matter for comparison with certain tendencies in the theory and practice of Christianity. Seneca uses phrases of great force and plainness to emphasise the conception of the sell«^ufficiency of the truly wise man. No one can either injure or benefit the wise man ; there is nothing which the wise man would care to receive. Just as the divine order can neither be helped nor injured, so is it with the wise man: the wise man is, except for his mortality, like to God Himself.^ It is only in some general, outward, and loose sense that it may be said that the wise man can receive a benefit.^

The conception of the self-suflBciency of the wise man had "^apparently developed in the later schools of philosophy, and at first sight it would seem as though this conception would necessarily greatly affect the conception of the relation of the individual to society. It seems clear that Epicurua ^nd his school had applied it so as to destroy the notion of the necessary duty of the individual to society; but it is also quite clear that the Stoic writers had very clearly and emphatically repudiated the Epicurean view upon the latter point, and that, while generally maintaining the conception that the philosopher was independent of the help of society, they taught the imperative duty of serving society.

We should venture to suggest that this fact is closely con- nected with the character of the Stoic ethical ideas, at least as they are represented by Seneca. In one of his letters Seneca, discussing the nature of liberal studies, seems to deny any value to those which are not related to the moral life ;^ his tone indeed is curiously like that of many religious writers on education. Seneca seems undoubtedly to look upon knowledge as advantageous only so far as it tends to make man better. He looks upon the philosophic life of meditation as the highest life ; but he justifies the view by the argument that in the long- run it is the philosopher with his contemplation of nature and goodness who does most for the service of mankind. Nature, he says, meant that man should both act and contemplate, and

^ Ad Serenum, "Nee injuriam," &c., ^ De Ben., vii. 4, &c.

viii. * Ep. xiii. 3.






CHAP. II.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OF SENECA. 27

indeed men do both, for there is no contemplation without action.^ The wise man, therefore, in Seneca's view may give his time f to contemplation, but this does not mean that he is exempt from I the obligation to the service of society. There is in Seneca's mind no real inconsistency between his view of the self- sufficiency of the wise man and his general theory of the relation of man to society. He has given ample expression to this theory in several treatises. Man is by nature drawn to ^ love his fellow-man : man is born to mutual service or helpful- ness.^ The Stoic doctrine is that man is a soQial animal, bom to serve the common good ; ^ and in his definition of the highest good in his treatise on the Blessed life it is interesting to observe that the temper of mind which constitutes this includes the qualities of humanity and helpfulness. The highest good is a temper which despises the accidents of life, which rejoices in virtue, or, the unconquerable temper of a man experienced in life, tranquil in action, of a great humanity and care for those with whom he is concerned.* Seneca is clear in main- taining that man is bom to live in society and to serve it: his necessities may not drive him to this, but the true dis- position of soul will do so.

The wise man, therefore, is driven to take his share in the work of society and, if it is possible, of the State. Part of a treatise which he devoted to this subject, the *iDe Otio,' has come down to us, and furnishes us with a fairly com- plete picture of the current opinions on the subject. There was evidently a very clear difiference between the Stoics and Epicureans upon the subject. Epicurus had said, "The wise man will not take part in the business of the common- wealth, unless some special cause should arise." Zeno, on the other hiand, had said, "The wise man should take part in the business of the commonwealth, unless some special cause should prevent him." Seneca admits that there may be conditions of public life which make it impossible for the wise man to do any good in public afifairs, and in such a case he will

1 De Otio, V. 8. s jy^ Clementia, i. 3, 2.

2 De Ira, i. 6. * De Vita Beata, iv.






28 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

withdraw from them.^ But even this does not mean that he will cease to serve the State. The philosopher and moral teacher serve the commonwealth as well as the politician ; even under the thirty tyrants Socrates was able to be of use to the Republic.^ The true rule of man's life is that he should be of use to his fellow-men, if possible to many ; if this cannot be, then to a few at least of his neighbours. If even this is impossible, then let a man improve himself, for in doing this he is really working for the public good, for just as a man who depraves himself defrauds others of the good he might have done them, so a man who studies his own improvement really serves others, because he is rendering himself capable of being of use to them.^

Seneca then clearly maintains that the wise man is constantly bound to the service of society, and even if possible to that of / the State. But he bids men remember, if it seems impossible to serve the State, that there are after all two commonwealths, the one that of the State in which we are born, the other the greater commonwealth of which the gods are members as well as men, a commonwealth whose bounds are only to be measured with the circuit of the sun ; and he doubts whether the greater commonwealth may not be best served in retirement, in phil- osophic meditation upon virtue, upon God and the world.* Such philosophic meditation is itself action ; nature calls us both to act and to contemplate, and this contemplation cannot be with- out action.^ Zeno and Chrysippus worked more for mankind than if they had led the armies of a nation or held its offices or made its laws: they made laws not for one state but for mankind.® This conception of the universal commonwealth is interesting and suggestive, in its relation to the theory of human nature, which we have already considered. We may perhaps feel that Seneca's mode of handling the subject sug- gests to our minds some doubt whether his hold upon the con- ception of the organic relation of human nature and progress to the organised society of the State is quite certain. Had the

1 De Otio, iii. * De Otio, iv.

2 De Tranquillitate, v. ' De Otio, v. 8.

' De Otio, iii. * De Otio, xxxii.






CHAP. II.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OF SENECA. 29

materials been more abundant, it would have been interesting to consider its relation to such a conception as that of Origen, ^-^ who defends the Christians against Gelsus, who blamed them for their reluctance to take office and bear arms: he urges that they are members of another society (avarnfm irarpLho^), and that their service in the Church of God is directed towards the salvation of mankind.^ There have, no doubt, been always traceable in the political theory of mediaeval and modern times two tendencies of thought, the one national, the other cosmo- - politan, and though it is perfectly true that these ideas are not incompatible with each other, yet historically they have some- times come into conflict.

Seneca, then, has a very clear general view as to the necessity of the State, of its fundamental importance in human life : he is even anxious to clear the philosophers of his time of the charge which seems to have been commonly made against them, that they were disloyal, or at least indifierent, to the State; he urges that no men are more grateful to the State than the philosophers, for it is under its protection that they are able to enjoy leisure for philosophic meditation.^ He fully recognises that the State is necessary under the actual conditions of human nature, if only as a remedy for the cor- ruption of human nature.

With regard to the conception of liberty and the best form of government Seneca seems to waVer and hesitate. If Lac- tantius is correct in attributing to Seneca ^ fragment which he has preserved, he gives an account of the expulsion of the Tarquins, representing it as due to the hatred of slavery, and says that the Eoman people determined to make the law rather than the king supreme. The Eoman Commonwealth reached its maturity under this free government ; but at last, when it had conquered the world, it turned its arms upon itself and finally returned as to a second childhood under the rule of one man. Bome lost its liberty, and its old age was so infirm that it could not stand without the support of a master.^ The

1 Contra Celsum, viii. 73. 76. ^ Ep. ix. 2.

2 Lactantius, Div. Inst., vii. 15.






30 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

same conception of the end of the Republic is presented in another place, where Seneca praises Cato, who, when his sword could not give his country liberty, turned it upon himself and so liberated himself ; ^ and again, when he speaks of the same Cato as having struggled to maintain the tottering common- wealth, and when it fell, as falling with it — for Cato did not survive liberty, nor liberty Cato.^ In these passages Seneca seems to think of liberty as being related to a certain form of government, and that this government is the only one suited to the character of a mature nation.

But in another treatise Seneca's tone is markedly difiFerent. He speaks indeed in praise and admiration of Brutus ; but adds that in slaying Caesar he greatly erred, both as a philosopher and as a practical statesman. Brutus had forgotten the Stoic doctrine when he allowed himself to be terrified by the mere name of king, for the best form of State is the just monarchy. And he showed himself a man of little insight into the actual conditions of Eoman Society, when he refused to recognise that the ancient character of the Eoman people was gone, and that men were contending not as to whether they should be sub- jected to some one man, but only as to whom they should serve.^ Seneca gives us to understand that the technical Stoic doctrine of government, like the Aristotelian, treated the form of government as being a matter of indifference so long as its end was just ; and the contrast with Cicero's view is at least worth noting.

His acquiescence in the practical necessities of Eoman life is also worth observing, and we may reasonably connect with this a very interesting treatment of the place of the Emperor in the State, which we find in the * De Clementia.' Seneca is recommending clemency to the Emperor, and appeals to his sense of responsibility, to the magnanimity of soul which so great an ofl&ce requires. The Prince should show himself such towards his subjects as he would wish the gods to be towards himself.^ He should remember that he out of all mankind has

^ " Quare aliqua incommoda," &c., ii. ' De Ben., ii. 20.

^ Ad Serenum, " Nee injuriam," &c., * De Clementia, i. 7.






CHAP. II.] THE POLITICAL THEORY OF SENECA. 31

been chosen to act in the place of the gods : the life and death, the fate and lot, of all men are in his hands.^ He is the source of the laws which he has drawn out of darkness and obscurity, and he will keep himself as though he were to render an account to those laws.* The ruler, whether he is called prince or king, or hj whatever other name he is known, is the very soul and life of the commonwealth. He is the bond which keeps the State together, and to his protection, therefore, all the people will devote themselves.^ Nothing can check his anger, not even those who suffer under his sentences will resist ; how great then will be his magnanimity if he restrains himself and uses his power well and gently.*

These phrases are evidently rhetorical, and it would be unwise to insist too much upon them; but their recognition of absolutism, and their tendency to think of this as resting in some sense upon the divine providence, are at least worth noticing. When we come to discuss the theories of the Christian Fathers, we shall have to consider very carefully t&is theory of the divine source of government and the divine authority of the ruler. It would be going too far to say that Seneca has any clearly defined conception of this kind in his mind; but it is at least interesting to observe his tendency towards this, and it may very well be compared with a similar tendency in Pliny's Panegyricus.^

When we look back and try to sum up the general results of our examination of Seneca's political theory, we see that the most important difference between him and Cicero is to be found in his developed theory of the nrimi^ve state of in » nocence, the state before the conventional institutions of society existed, and the consequent theory that these institu- tions are only the results of, and the remedies for, the vices of human nature. In the course of our investigation we shall have to consider the history of this theory, to pursue it through many forms. We inust again observe that, in Seneca's judg- ment, the fact that the innocent and unconventional state was

^ De dementia, i. 1., " qui in terris ^ De dementia, i. 3. and 4.

deonim vice fungerer ? " * De dementia, i. 5.

  • De dementia, i. L Pliny, Panegyricus, 1.






32 INTRODUCTION. [part i.

fu primitive does not at all mean that it was the complete

^^^"^^ » expression of the true nature of man; on the contrary, while

^ we must admit such an occasional ambiguity in his use of the

' phrase " nature " as we have pointed out, it is quite evident that

^A ,j , Seneca conceived of the primitive state as being one in which

i ' ^ \ man was yet undeveloped and imperfect, and that, while the

actually existing conditions of society may be unnatural in so

far as they arise from the vices and perversions of human

nature, yet they are natural in so far as they are the methods

/by which man may, under the actual conditions of life, go

forward and advance to'wards perfection.






PART IL

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE ROMAN LAWYERS.


CHAPTER III

THE THEORY OF THE LAW OF NATURE.

Wb have in the previous chapters attempted to examine the general character of political theory in the first century before Christ, and the first century after, in order that we may be better able to understand the historical position and signifi- cance of the conceptions of the Boman Lawyers of the Digest and the Institutes of Justinian, and the Christian Fathers from the first to the seventh century. It will not be doubted by any one who is acquainted with the political theory of the mediaeval writers that their conceptions are based in large measure upon; the Lawyers and the Fathers. They may often cite these in a very external and mechanical fashion, and, as we hope to show later, their political theory is as much affected by, and as closely related to, the actual conditions of their own times, as any other living system of political thought, yet the descent of their theories from those of the Lawyers and Fathers is unmistakable.

In this section of our work we propose to examine the general character of the political theory of the lawyers. We cannot usefully approach the Fathers until we have done this, for it ^ is clear that the theory of the Fathers is primarily derived ; from that current in their time. We shall have to consider

VOL. I. c






34 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

how far these general conceptions of their time are modified under the influence of strictly Christian or Jewish conceptions, but we think it is certain that the general structure of their theory is in no way original. How much they may have derived directly from the lawyers it may be difficult to say, but we must study the lawyers in order that we may come to some conclusion as to the general character of the political theory of the Empire apart from Christian influence. The Digest and the Institutes of Gains and Justinian are the best guides which we have for this inquiry, while it may be true that there are a good many points in which the Fathers may be thought to be nearer the general opinion of their time than the lawyers.

It has been sometimes supposed that the jurists are in the main disciples of one philosophical school — that they do more or less consistently adhere to the Stoic tradition. We venture to think that there is no sufficient evidence for such a judg- ment, that there is no sufficient reason for saying of the lawyers as a body that they belong quite distinctively to any one philosophical school. It is indeed possible that some of the lawyers came nearer to this position than others ; the obvious divergence among the lawyers on the great question of the jiis naturale may have some relation to disputes which are rather philosophical than legal. But in the main it would seem that it is best to r^ard the lawyers not as professed philosophers but rather as intelligent and able men, who when they turned from the sufficiently engrossing practical work of the interpretation and application of law to the changing con- ditions of Roman Society and speculated upon the foundations of Society and social life, took up the conceptions current among educated men without very carefully inquiring how far these were the doctrines of one school of philosophers rather than of another. Indeed one is more than half disposed to think that Ulpian, who, if any jurist, might be thought to show a specu- lative turn, intends to depreciate philosophy, when he somewhat pointedly contrasts the true philosophy of the lawyer as such, the study of justice, of the lawful and the unlawful, of the method of deterring men from evil and drawing them to good,






CHAP. III.] THB THEORY OF THE LAW OF NATURE. 35

with some feigned and presumably unprofitable system, which he does not further define.^ At the same time, it is true that in some very important points the Jurists seem to follow a tradition which is the same as that of the Stoics, that their conception of justice and of the nature of law is obviously related to that of the Stoics and opposed to such views as those of Epicurus and the later Academics.

The lawyers, then, are not, properly speaking, philosophers, or even political philosophers. There is little or no trace in their work of original reflection upon the nature of Society and its institutions ; they seem to use the commonplaces of the polit- ical thought of their time just as any intelligent man might use those of the present day : natural law and natural equality do not perhaps mean much more to them than evolution or pro- gress mean to the modern politician. But it must at the same time be recognised that the use which they made of certain conceptions not only serves to show us the general tendencies of political thought in their time, but did much to give those conceptions a clearness and precision which hitherto they had scarcely possessed.

We are fortunate in being able to examine the political theory of the Eoman Lawyers at two distinct periods, widely separated from each other in time. In Justinian's Digest are preserved fragments of the work of the great lawyers oTthe ^ second and the^rly Yeays>^ theJthicd xeatury, and in the Institutes of Justinian we have a handbook of law drawn up byThelawyers of Justinian's Court in the sixth, century. In the Code we have a collection of the most important Imperial constitutiotls be- longing to the period from Hadrian to Justinian, which serve in some measure to illustrate the principles of law expounded in the Digest and Institutes. We are thus able to study the political theory of the lawyers, not as a thing fixed and un- €tlterable, but as living and changing; we are able to some extent to discover which of the various legal theories of the second century did as a matter of fact dominate the general couifse of thought : for though it is true that the writers of the Institutes seem almost nervously anxious to combine the most

1 Dig., i. 1. 1.


i/


-^

^






36 POLITICAL THEORY OP ROMAN LAWYERS. [PART II.

divergent views of the great lawyers of the second century into one whole, yet they are unable to prevent us from conclud- ing with some reasonable confidence as to the character of their own opinions. We are also able within the second and third centuries to trace in some measure the course of political theory and to study the conflict of opinion between various legal schools. The selections of which the Digest is made up are fortunately always cited with the names of the authors, and though Justinian ^ warns us that by his authority the compilers of the Digest were empowered to omit, and even alter, anything that seemed to them unwise or erroneous in the ancient writers, yet we have no reason to think that this power was very largely exercised. We are able in a few cases, especially in that of Gains, Whose Institutes have been preserved for us, to compare the original work of the great lawyers with the selections of the Digest; and though, as we shall have occasion to notice, some changes seem to have been made, yet our impression is that the compilers of the Digest did not avail themselves greatly of this authority to alter the selections which they made, at least on those matters with which we are here concerned.

The first subject which requires our attention when we ap- proach the political theory of the lawyers is their theory of natural law, its relation to the law of nations and to the civil law. The subject is certainly perplexed and difl&cult, for we may doubt whether any of the lawyers had very clear concep- tions upon the matter, and it has been rendered even more obscure by the attempt of the compilers of Justinian's Insti- tutes to combine conceptions of the subject which are really incoherent, if not contradictory. There is no doubt that we find in the great lawyers of the second century not one view, but two. There can be no reasonable doubt that Gains in .the middle of the second century recognise d no o ppositio n be- tween the jus naturale and the jus gentium ; while Ulpian at the end of the second century sharply distinguishes the one from the other. We shall endeavour to point out what we

1 Cod., i. 17. 1, 7. (Prefixed to Digest.)






CHAP. III.] THE THEORY OF THE LAW OP NATURE. 37

think to be the significance of this change of view and the reasons which convince us that the view of Ulpian is that which ultimately prevailed and so became the foundation of the mediaeval theory upon the subject.

We cannot approach the subject better than by examining the views of Gam s upon the jus gentium. In the first words of his Institutes, which are also embodied in the Digest, there are two propositions which are of the greatest importance : the first, that the jus gentium is universal, embodies principles which \y^ are recognised by all mankind ; the second, that these principles have been taught men by naturcUis ratio} We must turn to other passages for additional details with regard to the jus gentium. In a section of the Digest taken from a work of Gains which has not been preserved, and in which Gains dis- cussed the origin of property in various things, we have the important statement that the jtts gentium is coeval with the * human race,— embodies those principles which from the first beginnings of human life were taught to mankind by their natural reason.^ In a third passage Gains connects with the jus gentium another quality of great importance. Property by " tradition," he says, belongs to the jus gentium, and is clearly consistent with natural equity.'

, When we put together these various conceptions which Gains connects with the jus gentium, we see that he conceives of it as that body of principles or laws which men have always L/ lecgmed from their reason to recognise as useful and just. The jus gentium is primitive, universal, rational, and equitable.

^ Gaius, Inst., i. 1; Dig., i. 1. 9 : gentium, quod ratione naturali inter

" Games populi qui legibua et moribus omnes homines perseque serratur, quar-

reguntur, partim suo proprio, partim undam jure civili, id est jure pro-

communi omnium hominum jure utim- prio civitatis nostrse. Et quia anti-

tur; nam quod quisque populus ipse quiua jus gentium cum ipso genere

sibi jus constituit, id ipdus proprium humano proditum est, opus est, ut de

est, Yocaturque jus civile, quasi jus hoc prius referendum sit."

proprium civitatis ; quod vero naturalis 'Dig., zlL 1. 9, 8: "Hse quoque

ratio inter omnes homines constituit, res quse traditione nostrse fiunt jure

id apud omnes populos perseque cus- gentium nobis adquiruntur : nihil enim

toditur Yocaturl^ue jus gentium, quasi tam conveniens est natural! sequitati

quo jure omnes sentes utuntur. " quam volimtatem domini volentis rem

'Dig., zli. 1. 1: "Quarundam suaminaUumtransferreratamhaberL" rerum dominium nanciscimur jure






38 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

Grains does not often nse the phrase jus nattirale, bnt from those passages in his writings where it occurs we concluda that it has much the same meaning to him as ratio naturcUis. In his Institutes he speaks in one sentence of property as being alienated and transferred by "tradition" under the jus naturale, and in the next, refers to this as agreeable to naturalis ratio} \ There is no trace in any writing of Gains which has survived y^ to us of any opposition between the jus gentium and the ju^ naturale ; such an opposition would indeed seem to be wholly incompatible with the character of the jus gentium as he conceives it.

It would seem, then, that the jus gentium of Gains is not greatly different from natural law as we have seen that Cicero miderstood it, except that, as we may perhaps say, Cicero is f)hinking of this as a part of the eternal law of God, while Gains is only thinking of law in relation to the world. But they agree in thinking of law as a rational and just principle of life which is not enacted by men, but is the expression of the universal and natural reason and sense of justice. The theory of law which is held by Gains, then, is not limited to the conception of the positive law of any one state, but is founded upon a con- ception of law, universal, primitive, and rational We shall see later that the civil law of any particular state is at least in some measure dominated by this general principle of law.

We may infer that Gains is, like Cicero, a follower of the Stoic theory of law and justice, regarding them not as some- thing which men create for their own utility, but as something / which they learn. Law in its general sense does not express the will of man, but is rather that which he rationally appre- , hends and obeys. The conception of the jus gentium which we jlerive from an examination of these passages of Gains is the same as that expressed in the definition of the jus ruiturale, which Paulus, a lawyer of somewhat later date, gives us.^ We have no reason to think that Paulus drew any distinction be-

^ Gaius, Inst., iL 65 and 66. dicitur, ut est jus naturale. Altera

^ Dig., L 1. 11: "Jus pluribus modo, quod omnibus aut pluribus in

modis dicitur : uno modo, cum id quod quaque civitate utile est, ut est jus

semper sequum ac bonum est jus civile."






OHAP. III.] THE THEORY OF THE LAW OF NATURE. 39

tween the jus naturale and the Jtcs gentium, — ^we have no evi- dence that he did so; and in any case this definition does not seem to take any such distinction into account, and indeed seems clearly, at least for the purpose in hand, to exclude it.

Grains then recognises no distinction between thejics ncUurcUe and thejvs gentium. In the beginning of the third century we find three lawyers who do clearly oppose the jtis gentium to the fu8 naturale or natura. Tryphoninus says that liberty belongs to thejvs n^aturale, and that lordship was introduced from the fus gentium} Florentinus asserts that slavery is an institution of the jvs gentium, by which one man is, contrary to nature, subjected to another.^ ^ Ulpian^ expresses the same opposition . when he says that the manumission of slaves belongs to the Jus ' gentium, for by the jus naturale all men were born free and slavery was unknown ; but when slavery came in by the jus gentium, then manumission also came in.' Ulpian has also drawn out the distinction between the jus gentium and the jus naturale in set terms. Private law, he says, is tripartite — if is gathered from natural precepts, or those of nations, or civil laws ; // there are three kmds of jus, the jus naturale, the jus gentium, and the jus civile. And he goes on to define their several characters. The jus naturale is that which nature has taught all animals ; it is not peculiar to the human race, but belongs tOb^ . all animals. From this law springs the union of male and female, the procreation and bringing up of children. The jus ^ gentium, on the other hand, is that law which the nations ot mankind observe : this is different from natural law, inasmuch as that belongs to all animals, while this is peculiar to men.^

^ Dig. , zii. 6. 64 : " Ut enim libertaa nascerentur nee esset nota manumissio,

naturali jure continetur et dominatio cum Benritus esset incognita : sed

ex gentium jure introducta est." (I poeteaquam jure gentium servitus in-

owe this reference to an article on the vasit, secutum est beneficium manu-

'* History of the Law of Nature: a missionis."

preliminary study," by Sir F. PoUock.) * Dig., i. 1. 1, 2, 3, and 4 : "Priva-\

' Dig., i. 5. 4: *' Servitus est con- tum jus tripertitum est; collectum

stitutio juris gentium, qua quisdominio etenim est ex naturalibus prsdceptis

alieno contra naturam subicitur." aut gentium aut civilibus. Jus natur-

' Dig., i. 1. 4: " Manumissionee ale est, quod natura omnia animalia

quoque juris gentium sunt . . . quse docuit: nam jus istud non human!

res a jure gentium originem sumpsit, generis proprium, sed omnium ani-

utpote cum jure naturali omnes liberi malium, qu» in terra, quae in mari nas*


CjOOQ IC ^ 


40 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part ll.

In considering this subject we must be careful to keep clearly apart the two points suggested by these phrases of Ulpian : first, the definite separation of the jus naturale from the jvs gentium, which is common to the three jurists ; and secondly, Ulpian's definition of the jtts naturcUe, which is peculiar to himself. The first is clear and distinct; whatever may be the character of the difference, the fact of the difference is something quite unambiguous. We cannot say the same with regard to his definition of the jtcs naturcUe. --^^ As Ulpian presents this here, the jus naturcUe would seem to be something of the nature of the general instinct of animals, not properly speaking rational or ethical; while he does not actually contrast the rational character of the jus gerUium with the irrational instinct of the jus naturcUe, at least he says that it is peculiar to men. To consider the definition fully, we must notice Ulpian's use of the phrases Natural Law and Nature in other placea The first passage where the phrase recurs is that to which we have already referred, in which he tells us that manumission is an institution of the jvs gentium, for by natural law all men were born free.^ Another passage which may very well be compared with this we find in the fiftieth book of the Digest. In this Ulpian says, that as far as concerns the civil law slaves are held pro ntUlis; but this is not so by natural law, for as far as natural law is concerned all men are equal.^ In another place he says that a man seems naturaliter" to possess that of which he has the usufruct;' and again, that nothing is so natural as that an agreement should be dissolved by the same method as that by which it was made ; ^ and in another

cuntur, avium quoque commune est. ^ I^ig*) >• 1* 4.

Hinc descendit maris atque feminse ^ ^ig*t ^ 17. 32 : "Quod attinet ad

conjunctio, quam noe matrimonium jus civile, servi pro nullis habentur:

appellamus, hinc liberorum procreatio, non tamen et jure naturali, quia, quod

hinc educatio : videmus etenim cetera ad jus naturale attinet, omnes homines

quoque animalia, feras etiam istius aequales sunt."

juris peritia censeri. Jus gentium est, ^ Dig., xlL 2. 12 : "Naturaliter vide-

quo gentes humanse utuntur. Quod tur possidere is qui usum fructum

a naturali recedere facile intellegere habet."

licet, quia illud omnibus animalibus, * Dig*} 1* 17. 35 : "Nihil tam natur-

hoc soils hominibus inter se commime ale est quam eo genere quidque dis-

. sit." solvere, quo coUigatum est."






CHAP. III.] THE THEORY OF THE LAW OF NATORE. 41

passage still he says that it is by nature just that a man should enjoy another man's liberality only so long as the donor wishes.^

We do not feel very clear as to the judgment which ought to be pronounced on the meaning of natural law and nature in these passages : they are not perhaps absolutely inconsistent with the character of the precise definition we have already quoted, but yet they leave with us the impression that they do not quite \ , correspond with it. When Ulpian says that by natural law men were once free and are still equal, it scarcely seems ade- quate to explain this as meaning that as far as their animal instinct was concerned they were free and equal, but by a rational system of order they are unequal and some are slaves of others. We doubt whether Ulpian had really arrived at a complete and coherent conception of the law of nature: it would rather seem that he had for some reason judged that some distinction between the law of nature and the law of nations should be made, but that he was not very clear as to the nature of the distinction.

We do not get much help towards understanding this dis- tinction from the other jurists. We have seen that Florentinus and Tryphoninus make the same distinction as Ulpian, but we do not possess any definition either of the/i^ naiurale or the/w^ gentium written by them. We can only say that the character of the opposition between the jus gerUmm and the jvs naiurale or natura, as they present it, does not suggest that they under- stood jus nMurale or natura to be equivalent to an animal instinct. Of the other jurists of the second century, as far as the fragments of their work enable us to judge, some appear to make no distinction between the jus naturale and the jus gentium, while others give us no indication of their view. Mar- cianus ^ and Paulus ® seem to know nothing of the distinction ; Pomponius uses the phrase /ws naturce, but does not define it.*

So far, then, as the lawyers of the second and third centuries are concerned, we cannot say that we can g et a filftar light upon the nature of the distinQtipB b^^we*^^ ^-^^ ^-»^ ^^ %t.iirft

1 Dig., xUii. 26. 2 : "Est enim na- ^ Djg^^ ^ g^ 2 and 4.

tura aequum tamdiu te liberalitate mea ^ Dig., i. 1. 11.

uti, quamdiu ego velim," * Dig., 1. 17. 206.






42 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [pART IL

x.^^ find the Law of Nations : t h^tact :oi the distinction is clear , the ^ound of the distinction remains somewhat uncerta in. We think that we cap find an explanation of this with the help of a passage cited in the Digest from the writings of a >i^ , jurist of the fourth century, a passage in the Institutes of^y^\>^ Justinian, and the definition of the 7us naturcUe and the jm '^ gentium given by St Isidore of Seville, a Christian writer of xhe beginning of the seventh century.

There is preserved in the Digest a passage from the writings of Hermogenianus, a jurist of the time of Constantino, which is undoubtedly interesting, though not free from ambiguities. We have here a list of institutions which come under the jvs qervtium^^ and we have the strong impression that Her- mogeiiianus is contrasting these with other institution s which bejrnig to the jus naturale or giving an account of the origin of institutio ns wfiicE had no existence under theji^ naturale . This impression is difl&cult to resist when we compare with Her- mogenianus the other passages to which we have just referred.

In the first of these the compilers of the Institutes, after giving an^ account of the jus naturale, the jus gentium, and the jus civile, come back to the subject of the jus gentium and explain that it is a system of law common to all^ manki nd and represents the experience of the human race, for in process of time wars, captivities, and slavery arose, and these are con- trary to the jus naJtural e} We cannot say that the writers of the Institutes had the passage of Hermogenianus immediately before them, but there is certainly a considerable correspond- ence of thought between their words and his.

St Isidore also defines the jus natural e and the jus civile , and

^ Dig., i. 1. 5: *'Ex hoc jure gen- tatibus gentes humanse qusedam sibi

tium introducta beUa, discretse gentes, constituerunt : bella etenim orta sunt et

regna condita, dominia distincta, agris captivitates secutse et servitutes, quse

termini positi, aedificia coUocata, com- sunt juri natural! contrarise. Jure

mercium, emptiones venditiones, loca- enim naturali ab initio omnes homines

tiones conductiones, obligationes in- liberi nascebantur. Ex hoc jure gen-

stitutSB : ezceptis quibusdam quae jure tium et omnes psene contractus intro-

civili introductse sunt." ducti sunt, ut emptio venditio, locatio ^

^ Inst.,!. 2. 2: "Jus autem gentium conductio, societas, depositiuu, mu- *

omni humano generi comn\une est. tuum et alii innumerabiles." Nam usu exigente et humanis necessi-






CHAP. III.] THE THEORY OP THE LAW OF NATURE. 43

then comes to the jus gerUiurrtf, anii gives us a list of the institu- tions which belong to this, such as wars, captivities, slavery, treaties of peace, &c.^ Again, we cannot say that St Isidore's definition is founded upon the passage from Hermogenianus, but at least it seems to us clearly to belong to the same tradi- tion and to be closely related to the passage in the Institutes.

The impression which these passages leave upon us is this : that t he writers have present to their minds some primitive circumstances, some primeval or natural institutions of thet^ human race, as disting uis hed from eve n the oldest and most universal conventional institutions of human society. St Isidore indeed describes the jtcs naturcde as that which is held "in- stinctu naturae, non constitutione aliqua." * We think that the position of Ulpian, Florentinus, and Tryphoninus may legit- imately be interpreted with their assistance. "W^e ahauld suggest that the cause which produced the theory of a law behind the univeraal law of all nations was a judgment, that some at least of the institutions which were as a matter of fact ^ ^ uni versal, an d were reckoned to belong to the jits 5^^^^^, yf \^ could not be looke d upon as, properly speaking, primitive or natural in the full sense of the word. We venture to think that here we trace the influence of that mode of thought about ^.\-s<^ the primitive conditions of human life which we have seen in Seneca , and which we may gather was representative of the general character of at least i3ome Stoic theories.

Ulpian clearly conceived of man as having originally been free, and maintained that slavery only came in later.^ That is, with respect at least to the institution of slavery he has in his mind some primitive state, before this conventional institution was introduced. Florentinus * and Tryphoninus ^ do not throw any clear light on the subject, but they seem to agree with Ulpian. There are no direct references, so far •

^ St Isidore of Seville, Etymologies, gentium, quod eo jure omnes fere

V. 6 : "Jus gentium est sedium occu- gentes utuntur." patio, sedificatio, munitio, bella, cap- ^ St Isid., Etym., v. 4.

tivitates, servitutes, postliminia, feed- ^ Dig>f i* 1* 4.

era pacis, inducise, legatorum non * Dig., i. 5. 4.

yiolandorum. religio, connubia inter ° Dig** xii. 6. 64.

alienigenas prohibita : et inde jus


LjOOQ IC 


\0^


44 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [PART il.

• as we have been able to see, in the lawyers of the Digest to a primitive state of nature; but we think that this is really

.implied in the attitude of Ulpian, Florentinus, and Tryphoninus to slavery. We should suggest that it is in connexion with this that the distinction between the jus ncUurale and the jm gentium arose. The passage from Hermogenianus which we have already cited seems to us to belong to a further develop- ment of the same theory. We shall see in a later chapter that t here can be no doubt that the Christian Fathers generally accept the theory of the primitive state of nature in which the conventional institutions of society did not yet exist, while they^ve this theory a peculiar turn by bringing it into connexion with the theory of the fall. /

We think therefore that the distinction made by Ulpian between the jus naturcUe and the jus gentium is really connected, ^ ^though Ulpian may not have been fully conscious of the fact, with a tendency to conceive of some state of nature as lying behind the actual conditions of human life. Ulpian's defini- tion of the jus naturale is not governed by this mode of thought ; but we would suggest that this should be taken mainly as illus- trating the fact thtft he had not arrived at any very clear conception of the whole subject At least, whatever doubt we may continue to feel as to the true significance of Ulpian's distin?tioil and definition, there can be little doubt that the tendency of legal theory was towards the distinction between the primitive and the conventional of which we have spoken. The Institutes of Justinian not only reproduce Ulpian's tripartite / definition otjus, but in the passage we have already cited ^ they more or less definitely give us an account of the process through which the institutions of thejtts gentium came into existence.

What the ultimate significance of this theory of natural law, as embodying the primitive principles of human life, was to be, we shall have occasion to consider later: we shall see in the Christian Fathers that the natural law represents a body of

'principles more or less ide al and adapt ed to a state of innocence, but not theref ore related to the actually exi sting condition of i mperfection.

1 Inst., i 2. 2.






45


CHAPTER JV.

SLAVERY AND PROPERTY.

In considering the subject of natural law and the law of nations we have cited many of the passages which relate to the theory of slavery and equality. But the subject is one of such import- ance that even at the risk of some repetition we must examine some of these over again. We have seen that there is no point in which the Aristotelian mode of thought is more sharply con- trasted with that of Cicero and Seneca than in the treatment of the equality of human nature. We have suggested that this change in the conception of the actual conditions of human nature can be accounted for in large measure by the new experience of the cosmopolitan Empires, by the fact that the Greeks in impressing their culture upon the countries of the Mediterranean seaboard discovered that after all the barbarian was possessed of reason and capable of virtue and of culture. However the change of conception may have taken place, there is no doubt that it did come about, there is no doubt that both Cicero and Seneca bear evidence to the fact that the older view was disappearing^ It is of great importance to make ourselves clear upon the position of the Roman lawyers with regard to this matter : we may well imagine that the technical lawyers would be the last to yield to the new views, the most conserva- tive of conceptions relating to so great and fundamental a social institution as that of slavery.

When we examine the writers of the ' Digest ' in their chrono- logical order, we discover that the appearance of the distinction^ which we have been considering, between the natural law and the law of nations corresponds in point of time with the appear-






46 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS, [part li.

ance of certain new phrases about human nature, with the dogmatic assertion of natural liberty and equality. It must not be supposed, however, that the older jurists of the Digest show us any trace of a belief that slavery is founded upon natural inequality. If they are silent on the theory of natural equality, they are equally silent, so far as we have found, on the opposite theory.

Gains nowhere gives us any complete account of the origin of slavery. He assumes the distinction between the slave and the freeman as being one of primary importance in the classifi- cation of the law of persons,^ and he gives us an account of the legal position of the slave and says that the slave is in potestcUe, ^ and that this condition of slavery exists under the jus gentium, that everywhere the masters have the power of life and death over their slaves, and that T/^tever the slave acquires belongs to his master.^ In another passd^ge of the Digest he is cited as laying it down that slavery arises from capture in war.^ This is the only explanation of the origin of slavery which Gains ^gave, so far at least as the evidence of his remains goes. Marcianus, a later jurist, is cited in the Digest as laying it down that slaves come into our possession by the jic$ gentium when they are captured in war or are born of our slave women.* We may conjecture that his statement would repre- sent the views of Gains as well as of himself. These jurists then look upon slavery as an institution of the jus gentium, and taking into account what Gains meant by the jus gerdium, we infer that they looked upon the institution as rational and just; but they must not therefore be understood to hold the same views with regard to the inequality of human nature as Aristotle. Indeed it is noticeable enough that they have no i^xplanation to offer of the origin of the institution, except as connected with war.

When we come to Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus at the close of the second century, we find that remarkable turn of theory whose expression we have already noticed in con-

^ Gaius, Inst., i. 9 ; Dig., I 5. 3. statlm capientium fiunt . . . adeo qui-

2 Oaius, Inst., i. 62. Dig., i. 6. 1. dem ut et liberi homines in servitu-

' Dig., xli. 1. 6, 7: "Item quse tern deducantur."

ex hostibus capiuntur jure gentium * Dig., i. 5. 5, 1.






CHAP. IV.] SLAVERY AND PROPERTY. 47

sidering the meaning of "natural law." It will be as well to put together these phrases in this new connexion. In the first place we may perhaps put the famous phrase of Ulpian : Quod ad jus naturale attinet, omnes homines sequales sunt"^ It is just possible that this phrase is a little more technical than might at first sight appear, for Ulpian is evidently dis- cussing the legal position of the slave, and the equality of which he speaks may conceivably have had primarily a technical signification, as equal in position before the law. Still, the phrase is very noteworthy in its bold and direct character. The impression it makes is not weakened but rather confirmed when we turn to his equally famous phrase, "cum jure naturali i omnes liberi nascerentur," ^ Slavery had no place under the/ jus naturale, but came in under the jvs gentium. By the law! of nature men were free and equal. '

When we turn to Florentinus we feel that this conception of the natural freedom of man is again confirmed. Slavery is an institution of the jus gerUium and contrary to nature. We even seem to trace a half-apologetic tone in the famous explana- * tion of the name " servus " which Florentinus adds. The slave is called so because he is preserved alive and not slain as he might be by the laws of war,* Tryphoninus, again, expresses the same judgment with great clearness, when he says that liberty belongs to natural law, lordship was introduced by the ju3 gentium,^

^ Big., 1. 17. 82: "Quod attinet uno naturali nomine homines appel-

ad jus civile, servi pro nuUis habentur : laremur, jure gentium tria genera esse

non tamen et jure naturali, quia, quod coeperunt : liberi et his contrarium

ad jus naturale attinet, omnes homines servi et tertium genus liberti, id est

sequales sunt." hi qui desierant esse servi."

^ Dig., i. 1. 4 : " Manumissiones ^ Dig., i. 5. 4 : " Libertas est natur-

quoque juris gentium sunt. Est autem alis facultas ejus quod cuique facere

manumissio de manu missio, id est libet, nisi si quid vi aut ^re prohibe-

datio libertatis : nam quamdiu quis in tur. Servitus est constitftio juris gen-

servitute est, manui et potestati sup- tium, qua quis dominio alieno contra

positus est, manumissus liberatuf po- naturam subicitur. Servi ex eo appel-

testate. Qusa res a jure gentium lati sunt, quod imperatores captivos

ori^em sumpsit, utpote cum jure vendere ac per hoc servare nee occid-

naturali omnes liberi nascerentur nee ere solent."

esset nota manumissio, cum servitus * Dig.,xii. 6. 64 : " Ut enim libertas

esset incognita: sed posteaquam jure naturali jure oontinetur et dommatio

gentium servitus invasit, secutum est ex gentium jure introducta est." beneficium manumissionis. Et cum






48 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part li.

It may be urged that these are meaningless phrases, illus- trating only the progress of an unpractical, sentimental speculation, which had no relation to the actual conditions of life. We think that this would be an exaggerated mode of speaking. These sentiments, just as those of Cicero and Seneca, were indeed held by men of whom we may fairly say that they never dreamed of overturning the actually existing con- ditions of society which were founded upon the institution of slavery, but that is not the same thing as to say that their phrases were meaningless and had no relation to the actual facts of life. We have seen that the sentiment of human equality was the result of the actual experience of the Mediterranean world, — that it only represents in theory an experience in fact. We venture to think that the theory of equality could not but react upon the theory of slavery, could not but alter the judgment of men as to its origin ; and when we turn to examine the actual conditions of slavery as they are illustrated in the Eoman Jurisprudence, we see that the change of theory was at least parallel with a change in the conditions of slavery.

If we turn back to that phrase of Gains in which, as we have already seen, he describes the legal condition of the slave, we shall find it useful to notice that the words to which we have referred are followed by a sentence in which he tells us that the unrestricted power of the master over his slave, of which he has just spoken, did not any longer exist within the Eoman Empire, and that all excessive cruelty on the part of the master was prohibited.^ In the Digest, where these words are quoted, the compilers seem to have inserted "legibus cognita" after

^ Gaius, Inst., i. 53: *'Sed hoc cipis constitutionem coercetur: nam

tempore neque civibus Romania, nee consultus a quibusdam prsesidibus

uUis aliis hominibus qui sub imperio provinciarum de his servis, qui ad

populi Romani sunt, licet supra fana deorum vel ad statuas principum

modum et sine causa in servos suos confugiunt, prseoepit ut, si intoler-

ssevire : nam ex constitutione sacratis- abilis videatur dominorum saevitia,

simi imperatoris Antonini, qui sine CQgantur servos suos vendere ; et

causa servum suum occiderit nl^n minus utrumque recte : male enim nostro

teneri jubetur, quam qui alienum ser- jure uti non debemus ; qua ratione et

vum occiderit. Sed et major quoque prodigis interdicitur bonomm suorum

asperitas dominorum per ejusdem prin- administratio."






CHAP. IV.] SLAVERY AND PROPERTY. 49

" sine causa " and to have read " puniri " for " teneri," ^ changes which are interesting as exhibiting the tendency to a growing strictness.

It is certainly worth noticing that the Eoman Law had thus begun to limit the strict rights of the master and to interfere in the condition of the slave. In other references in the Digest we can trace this tendency back to the middle of the first century. Modestinus teUs us that, by an edict of the Emperor Claudius, if a slave were deserted by his master on account of his suffering from severe illness, he was to receive his freedom ; ^ and that Vespasian decreed the liberation of slave women whose masters prostituted them, when they had been sold under the condition that they should not be prostituted.* Ulpian says that Hadrian had banished for five years a certain lady, who on the very slightest grounds had outrageously ill- treated her slave women.*

Ulpian gives us at length a rescript of Antoninus Pius which, as he understands it, defines the law in the case of a master outrageously ill-treating his slaves or driving them to un- chastity. The Emperor is anxious not to interfere with the rights of masters, but he judges that it is to their interest that those who are unjustly ill-treated should be protected, and he therefore, in a particular case referred to, orders that the slaves who had fled to the Emperor's statue — if it was found that they had been treated with greater severity than was just, or had been infamously injured — should be sold, and not restored to their masters.^

It is natural and reasonable to connect these tendencies of

^ Big., i. 6. 1, 2. inum jus suum detrahi : sed domin-

^ Dig., xL 8. 2. orum interest, ne auxilium contra

  • Dig., xxxvii. 14. 7. ssevitiam vel famem vel intolerabilem
  • Dig., L 6. 2. injuriam denegetur his qui juste

'Dig., i. 6. 2: "Si dominus in deprecantur. Ideoque cognosce de

servos ssevierit vel ad impudicitiam querellis eorum, qui ex familia Julii

turpemque violationem compellat, quse Sabini ad statuam confugerunt, et si

eint partes prsesidis, ex rescripto divi vel durius babitos quam sequum est

Pii ad .^nium Marcianum proconsulem vel infami injuria affectos cognoveris,

Bseticse manifestabitur. Cujus re- veniri jube ita, ut in potestate domini

Bcripti verba heec sunt: 'Dominorum non revertantur. Qui si mese consti-

quidem potestatem in suos servos illi- tutioni £raudem fecerit, sciet me ad-

batam esse oportet nee cuiquam horn- misaum severius exsecuturum. VOL. I. D


) ))






50 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part li-

the Koman jurisprudence to regulate and ameliorate the con- dition of the slave with that great change in the conception of human nature of which we have spoken. It will be remem- bered that Cicero urges that the slave should be treated with justice, and that Seneca exhorts men to live with their slaves as friends and companions: the tendency of the Soman law to recognise certain elementary claims of humanity is naturally to be related to the recognition of the fact that the slave wad essentially of the same nature and possessed of the same powers of reason and virtue as his master. We are well aware that the great changes in the position of the slave and the gradual disappearance of slavery in Europe must be traced in large measure to the operation of economic forces, just as is the case with the disappearance of villeinage in later times; but it is not therefore necessary to overlook the influence of the senti- ment of human nature on social conditions. The economic and ethical foundations of society are not to be separated from each other, nor will historical truth be best served by insisting exclusively on one aspect of human life alone.

Whatever may be our judgment upon the matter, it is at least of importance to observe the fact that the lawyers, as well as those writers whom we have already examined, clearly indifiate t.}^ft|. thft thftorv of nft^fftl in^.Qualitv had dis- ...appeac&d^&nd that at least by the end of the second century ^ the theory of a natural equality and natural liberty of human nature was firmly established. In later chapters we shall have' to consider the relation of these theories to Christianity, but in the meantime we must make it clear to ourselves that Christian- ity did not produce these theories of human nature, but rather brought the same theories with it, whether derived from the saine general sources or having antecedents of their own we shall have to consider. It may with much force be urged that in this matter Christianity turned what was to some extent an abstract theory into something which is continually tending to make itself real in outward fact; but when this is urged, those practical tendencies of the Boman Jurisprudence, of which we have spoken, must not be overiooked.

Our examination of the theory of slavery has then resulted






OHAP. IV.] SLAVERY AND PROPERTY. 51

in our finding that at least with regard to this institution we may very well conjecture that the tendency of Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus is to contrast the actual con- ditions of society with some primitive state in which such an institution did not exist. We have seen that in Seneca's theory this primitive condition is contrasted with the actual, with special reference to the absence of the institutions of property and coercive government With regard to that par- ticular form of property called slavery, we may feel that Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus tend to the same opinion.

We must now consider the legal view of the origin of the institution of private property. We do not discuss the legal conception of property, — such a discussion would take us far away from our subject, — and we endeavour to confine ourselves to an inquiry into the view of the jurists as to the origin of property and its relation to natural law.

The earliest writers whom we have observed to be cited . in the Digest on the subject are Labeo and Nerva Filius, two jurists of the first century. Paulus quotes both these writers, and we gather that Labeo and Nerva Filius treat of property as arising naturally from the occupation or capture of that which previously had belonged to no one.^ We may compare a passage from Neratius, a jurist of the time of Trajan, from which we gather that, some things are brought forth by nature which are not in the dominion of any one, and that these, as fishes and wild beasts, become the property of any one who captures them.^ This is the foundation of the treatment of the origin of property by Gains. In that passage to which we have already referred this is drawn out with much detail It is by the law of nations that we acquire the possession of many things, such as wild animals and

. ^ Dig., xli. 2. 1 : '^Possessio appel- Nerva filius ait ejusque rei vestigium

]At^ est, ut et Labeo ait, a sedibus remanere in his, quae terra mari coelo-

quasi positio, quia naturaUter tenetur que capiuntur : nam hsec protinus

ab eo qui ei insistit, quam Qrseci eorum fiunt, qui primi possessionem

Karoxfitf dicunt. Dominiumque re- eorum adprehenderint."

rum ex naturali possessione ooepisse ^ Dig., xli. 1. 14, 1.






52 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

the property of our enemies; and it is by the same law^of nations that we acquire things by "tradition": other things we acquire by the civil law.^

If we turn now to Marcianus we find that he maintains the same view and tells us in set terms that some things are by natural law common to all, some are private property .^ We have already seen that the jus ncUurale of this passage seems to be the same as the Jiis gentium of other passages from Marcianus, — that he does not distinguish between the two. Paulus also tells us that certain methods of acquiring private property belong to the law oL nature and are natural^ It would seem clear, then, that those writers who make no dis- tinction between the jus naturale and the jus gentium looked upon the institution of private property as being primitive, rational, and equitable.

We turn now to those writers who make this distinction. It must be observed that we have very little information as to their conception of the origin of the institution of property. We have only noticed two passages from their writings which seem to bear on this. The first of these is contained in a defini- tion of Precarium by Ulpian.* This definition does not help us very much; it would be quite improper to conclude from it that he looked upon all forms of private property as belong- ing to the jus gentium. The other passage, which is from

^ Dig., xli. 1. 1 : Quarundam re- veniens est natural! sequitati quam

rum dominium nanciscimur jure gen- voluntatem domini volentis rem suam

tium, quod ratione naturali inter omnes in alium transferre ratam haberi."

homines perseque servatur, quarundam Cf. Gains, Inst., ii. 65-69.

jure civili, id est jure proprio civitatis ^ Dig.> i. 8. 2 : Quaedam naturali

nostras. . . . Omnia igitur animalia, jure conununia sunt omnium, qusedam

quae terra, mari, coeloque capiuntur, id universitatis, qusedam nuUius, plera-

est ferae bestiae et volucres pisces capi- que singulorum, quae variis ex causis

entium fiunt. ..." cuique adquirimtur."

xli. 1. 3: Quod enim nullius est ' Dig** xviiL 1. 1, 2: "Est autem

id ratione naturali occupanti con- emptio juris gentium." Dig., xix. 2. 1 :

ceditur. ..." *'Locatio et conductio cum naturalis

xli. 1. 5, 7 : " Item quae ex hostibus sit et omnium gentium."

capiuntur, jure gentium statim capi- * Dig., xliii. 26. 1 : " Precarium est,

entium fiunt. . . ." quod precibus petenti utendum con-

xli. 1. 9, 3 : " Hae quoque res, quae ceditur tamdiu, quamdiu is qui con-

traditione nostrse fiunt, jure gentium cessit pafcitur. Quod genus liberali-

nobis adquiruntur : nihil enim tam con- tatis ex jure gentium descendit."






CHAP. IV.] SLAVERY AND PROPERTY. 53

Florentinus/ seems to show that his general theory of the origin of private property was much the same as that of the writers whom we have before examined. We should con- jecture that Florentinus is describing one of the forms of appropriation of things which were before nvllius. However this may be, one thing is clear, that Florentinus treats of one form of private projierty as belonging to the jus naturale. The institution of private property, then, to Florentinus is primitive and natural, and not like that of slavery, which is contrary to nature. So far then as our evidence goes, we can only say that Florentinus agrees with the other writes in looking upon property as a natural institution, even though he differs from them on the relation of the Jvs gentium to nature; and that with respect to the position of Ulpianwe have no information.

It only remains again to consider that passage from Her- mogenianus^ which we have already had occasion to examine in connexion with the question of the contrast between the institutions of the jus gentium and those of the jus naturale. Again we have to lament our ignorance of the general position of Hermogenianus. We cannot but retain the impression that he is contrasting these institutions with others which belong to the jus naturale or to the jus civile. We have at least to notice the description of the dominia distincta as belonging to the jus gentium, and we have the impression that he looks upon this form of property as belonging to a condition of things not perhaps entirely primitive. Our interpretation of Hermogenianus is naturally affected, as we have already said, by a comparison with the Institutes of Justinian' and the Etymologies of St Isidore;* but we have already cited these* and we need not again go over the ground.

Our examination of the Koman Lawyers with regard to the origin and character of private property has yielded us the following results. Those lawyers who, like Gains, make no

^ Dig., i. 8. 3 : '*Item lapUli, gem- regna condita, dominia distincta, agris

mae ceteraque, qusB in litore invenimus, termini positi," &c. jure naturali nostra statim fiunt.** ^ Inst., i. 2. 2.

2 Dig., i. 1. 6 : "Ex hoc jure gen- * St Isidore, Etym., v. 6.

tium introducta bella, discretae gentes,






54 POLITICAL THEORY OP ROMAN LAWYERS. [pabt ll.

distinction between the jus imturale and the jus gentium clearly look upon the institution of private property as ratiqnal, just, and primitive. They know nothing of any condition of human life where private property did not exist. It is likewise clear that Florentinus, although he distinguishes between nature and the fus gentium, also holds that private property is natural, belonging to the jus naturale, and therefore primitive as well as rational. The position of Ulpian and Hermogenianus is un- certain. We have no means of arriving at any confident con- clusion with regard to their views, although we may incline to think that Hermogenianus very possibly reckoned private property as belonging to the jus gentium and not to the jus naturale.

The Lawyers, then, do not, so far as the theory of property is concerned, give us much help in studying the development of the theorj^ of a state or condition of nature. We have seen that with^ regard to the institution of slavery Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus certainly seem to incline to con- trast the primitive with the actual, but there is no evidence of any tendency to develop this with reference to other in- stitutions. We have seen that this theory was current among the Stoic thinkers ; we shall find it again in the Fathers, and we shall see that XJlpian's distinction of the jus naturale from the jus gentium is one of the conceptions which ultimately gave it clearness and precision. But, except with reference to slavery, it does not appear that even the school (if we may call it so) of Ulpian developed the theory of the state of nature with any clearness, or indeed that the conception is very distinctly present to their minds at all, for even their treatment of slavery tends rather to fall in with such a theory than to be definitely and consciously, by them, related^to it.






55


CHAPTER V.

THE THEORY OP THE CIVIL LAW.

We have seen with what emphcesis Cicero maintains that all law is derived from the one eternal law of God, which is the same as the principle of justice and reason in man's heart ; we have seen how indignantly and scornfully he repudiates the notion that unjust laws are true laws (jura), h*w emphatically he maintains that neither kings nor people can make that to be law which is not the expression of the eternal principles of justice. We have now to consider what is the principle and definition of the civil law in the great jurists. We must adopt the chronological method in examining our subject, for though, as we think, there is little trace of variation among the lawyers on this subject, yet we cannot but recognise the fact that there are some ambiguities in their statements, and at any rate we cannot arrive at the same certainty with regard to some of them as with regard to others.

We commence our inquiry with Gains, and, indeed, a sentence of his Institutes indicates the legal conception of the relation between the positive law of the State and the principles of reason, as clearly as any passage we can find. He is speaking of the guardianship or tutelage of those who are under age, and says it ought to be a principle of the law oJE every State that those under age should be under guardianship, for this is agree- able to natural reason.^ Natural reason is the guide and director of all civil legislation ; this natural reason is itself the source of

  • Qaiufl, Inst., i. 189: "Impuberes ration! conveniens est, ut is qui per-

quidem in tutela esse omnium civit- -fectse setatis non sit alterius tutela atum jure contin^t, quia id naturali regatur."






56 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part li.

the jus gentium, and therefore controls both the general law of mankind and the particular law of any one State. The concep- tion of law as necessarily conformed to some general principle apart from the caprice of any individual or group of individuals is sufficiently indicated in this phrase.

The matter is, however, much more completely developed by Marcianus early in the third century. He cites two most im- portant Greek definitions of law, whose significance for our purpose is very great. He first cites a definition of law put forward by Demosthenes and then one of Chrysippus, whom he describes as " philosophus summae stoicse sapientiae." Mar- cianus makes no comment on these two definitions, and we may take it that he accepted them as representing his own conception of the subject. It is evident enough that the standpoint of the two writers is not by any means the same ; but, at the same time, there is a very substantial agree- ment between them on some of the most important points of the conception of law. In the first place, they both of them regard law in the general sense as being something which is related to the divine or universal order as well as to the regulation of any particular State. Every law, Demosthenes says, is discovered and given by God ; while Chrysippus treats law as the ruler of all things both divine and human. Law, according to Demosthenes, is intended for the correction of offences; while Chrysippus says that it is the norm or standard of things just and unjust. Both Demosthenes and Chrysippus bring their definitions into relation with civil law, by defining law, in the sense in which they are using the term, as being that which all in the State must obey and as belonging to all living creatures which are by nature political. To these more general conceptions Demosthenes adds certain specific condi- tions of the civil law — ^namely, that it should be set forth by the wise man, and should be agreed to by the whole State : to these we shall have to return when we consider the nature and source of authority in the State.^

^ Dig., i. 3. 2: "Nam et Demos- 0€a0€u 8*i »oX\i, Koi fudXurra Uri iras thenes orator sic definit: rovrh 4<rri iarl v6/jms tZpmuL fihv Koi ISopov Btov, ¥6fios, f vajrras ivOp^ovs »fKwr^«€i vti- B^fM 8i kyBp^wv ^povlfuav iTap6p$tfffM






CHAP, v.] THE THEORY OP THE. CIVIL LAW. 57

These definitions of Demosthenes and Chrysippus bring out very clearly what we have already seen is indicated by Gains, that civil law is to be regarded, not primarily as expressing the will of any community or person in a community, but as the particular application in any community of the principles of the universal reason and justice. This is indeed substantially the same view as that of Cicero. We do not suggest that Marcianus is to be considered as a strict disciple of the Stoic school; but clearly enough he, like Cicero, follows the Stoic conception of justice and law, as contrasted with that of the^ Epicureans or the later Academics.

So far we have examined the opinions of those to whom the distinction between thejics naturale and XhQ jus gentium had no special meaning, and we have seen that this does not in the least affect their view of the relation between the civil law and the general or universal principles of justice. We turn to the view of Ulpian, as representing the new theory, and we find him maintaining the same view with greater detail, but on the same general lines.

The compilers of the Digest open that work with a very significant and important statement by Ulpian on this subject.^ Nothing could well be clearer than the general tendency of these sentences. The jurist must understand that law is the art of the good and just, that it is his duty to study the meaning of this, to distinguish the just from the unjust, to draw men to do what is good. The law, that is, which the jurist has to deal with, is not to be looked at simply as a

84 r&¥ iKovciay koI aKova-lav afiapn/jfid- ^ Dig., i. 1. 1 : " Juri operam da-

T»y, T6\€ois 9h <rvyd4\ia\ Koirfi, Kad* ^v turum prius nosse oportet, undo nomen

ivcuri vpoff'fiKti (gy to7s iv rg w6\€i, juris desoendat. Est autem a justitia

Sed et philosophus summse stoicse sapi- appellatuiu : nam ut eleganter Celsus

entise Chrysippus sic incipit Ubro, quern definit, jus est ars boni et sequi. Cujus

fecit T€p\ ySfiov : S v6ims ximtov i<rr\ merito quis nos sacerdotes appellet :

fiaviKths Bfiuy rt Koi ityOpwrlvoty Tpay- justitiam namque colimus, et boni et

fidrwy * 8f 7 8i ainhv irpoardrny r« ttyat sequi notitiam profitemur, sequum ab

r&y KttX&y Kal r&y aiffXP»v Kctl 2(f>xovTa iniquo separantes, licitum ab illicito

fcal iiy€fx6yaf Koi irard rovro Ray6va re discementes, bonos non solum metu

%tyag iiieaiuy Koi &BIkuv Kal r&y ^6<r€t pcenarum, verum etiam prsemiorum

•Ko\iTiK&y C4^yj xpoaraKTiKhy fihy Sy quoque ezhortatione efficere cupientes,

iroi7ir4oVf &iroyop«vnKhv ih &y oif xoiri- veram Disi fallor philosophiam, non

Hoy*** simulatam afiectantes."






58 POLITICAL THEORY OP ROMAN LAWYERS, [part n.

series of positive regulations of any particular society, but rather as the expression of the perpetual principles of justice and goodness.

These views are further illustrated in the well-known phrases in which Ulpian attempts to define the nature of justice, the main principles of law (Jm), and the true character of juris- prudence.^ These famous phrases, repeated constantly through- out the Middle Ages and later, may suggest to us that Ulpian was rather a facile and rhetorical than a profound thinker upon law : we may feel that these sentences, for all their admirable sound, carry us little further, and that we do not know much more about the nature of justice than we did. But regarded historically, these words are of the greatest importance, not merely as assuring us of Ulpian's position, but as forming one of the most important links in the chain by which the theory of law of the ancient world was handed down to mediaeval and so to modern thinkers. The general view of Ulpian, then, is obviously the same as that of Marcianus and that which is indicated in the sentence of Grains which we have already quoted.

We have, however, another statement of Ulpian's in which the relation between the civil law and the natural law is more specifically, but also more ambiguously, dealt with.^ We cannot but regret that the compilers of the Digest have not preserved for us a more detailed explanation of these some- what ambiguous phrases. They are obviously capable of a meaning in harmony with the conclusions which we have drawn from the statements we have already examined, but they might also bear a somewhat different construction. It is easy enough to understand what Ulpian means when he speaks of the civil law as being something added to ihQJus commune, a phrase which seems to mean simply the jus naturale and jus gentium, as being universal in their application, but it is not so

^ Dig., L 1. 10 : " Justitia est con- ^ Dig., i. 1. 6 : "Jus civile est, quod

stans et perpetua voluntas jus suum neque in totum a naturali vel gentium

cuique tribuendL Juris praeoepta sunt recedit, nee per omnia ei servit : itaque

h8ec;honesteyivere,alterumnonlsedere, cum aliquid addimus vel retrahimus

suum ouique tribuere. Juris prudentia juri communi, jus proprium, id est

est divinarum atque humanarum rerum civile efficimus." notitia, justi atque injusti scientia."'






CHAF. v.] THE THEORY OF THE CIViL LAW, 59

easy to understand what he means by the jus civile as something which may take away from the/u^ commune.

The first phrase which suggests itself as possibly famishing us with the means of comment on Ulpian's words is that phrase of Florentinus which we have so frequently cited,^ slavery is an institution of the jus gentium and contrary to nature. It is true that Florentinus is here speaking of the relation of the jus gentium to nature, but it would seem that the words might be applied to the relation of the jus civile to nature. Ulpian has expressed the same opposition, with ref- erence to the same institution. By the jus naturale, he says, men were bom free ; by the jus gentium they are enslaved ; * and in another place, as we have seen, he has contrasted the relation of the jtcs civile with that of the jus naturale on the subject of the equality of men.'

We seem to find in these phrases of Florentinus and XJl^jan illustrations of what Ulpian may mean by the civil law as taking away something from the jus naturale ; but we are still far from clear as to how this is to be explained in conformity with the general conception of law which he seems to maintain. The word jus is, he has told us, taken irom justUia ; jus is the "ars boni et sequi"; of the lawyers he has said, "justitiam namque colimus et boni et sequi notitiam profitemur." Jus- tice, then, must reside either in the jus nattcrale or the jiis gentium or the jus civile, or in all of them. It is possible to maintain that Ulpian does not connect it specially with the jus naturale. We have seen that his definition of that system of law leaves us very uncertain whether he had any clearness of conception about it ; but it is very difficult to suppose that in that case he did not find justice in the jv^ gentium^ where, as we have seen, it would appear that the lawyers who take the same view as Gaius, found it.

We should suggest that the explanation may again be found in the relation of the conceptions of Ulpian and Florentinus to the theory of a natural state antecedent to the conventions of organised society ; and that, just as Seneca looks upon the institutions of property and organised government as the

1 Dig., i. 6. 4. 2 Djg.^ i, 1, 4, 8 pig.^ 1. 17. 82.






60 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

result of the progress of vice among men, and yet regards them as adapted to, and therefore justifiable under, the actual conditions of human life, so Ulpian and Florentinus may conceive of the jus civile as diflfering from the jus naturale, as the conditions of the conventional life differ from those of the natural, and yet as being just under the actual conditions of human life. We shall see that this is the explanation which the Christian Fathers furnish of the contrast between the primitive or natural conditions of human life and the actual ; and the fact that in this matter Seneca seems to represent a current Stoic tradition encourages us to think that the lawyers, like Ulpian and Florentinus, may have been influenced by some such ideas, even though they were not very clearly conscious of their influence. i

There remains to be considered a sentence of Paulus, a con- temporary of Ulpian. We have already mentioned this phrase, and must now reconsider the passage with relation to the subject we have in hai\d. Paulus says that we may defipe law in diflferent fashions : in one way when we speak of that which "^is always just and good, this is jus naturale; in another way

. when we speak of that which is useful to all or the majority -

in any State, this is jus civile} At first sight we seem here to have a frank recognition of the utilitarian and interested character of civil law, and might feel inclined to think that Paulus must represent that tradition which so much angered Cicero, that law is merely that which is convenient to those who have power in any State. It is of course possible, though not probable, that this may be the case. We do not know that there is any reason to maintain that such opinions were not current at the time when Paulus wrote, and that he might not have been influenced by them. At the same time, in the ab- sence of any other clear trace of such a view in the Digest and Institutes, we feel rather disposed to think that Paulus used these words without any great care, and that we therefore must

^ Dig., i. 1. 11: "Jus pluribus modo, quod omnibus aut pluribus in

modis dicitur, uno modo, cum id quod quaque civitate utUe est, ut est jus

semper sequum ac bonum est jus dici- civile." tur, ut est, jus naturale. Altero






CHAP, v.] THE THEORY OF THE CIVIL LAW, 61

not press their significance to those conclusions which might be drawn from them. We think that he very probably intended nothing more than a contrast between the perpetual principles of justice embodied in, or represented by, what he calls the jus naturcUe, and the temporary and changing application of those principles as adapted to the varying circumstances and varying desires of the members of any State.

We have seen then, that, except so far as there may be some doubt about the position of Paulus, the Eoman Jurists of the second century hold a clear view of the relation of the civil law to the principles of justice; whether these are looked upon as embodied in the Jus naturale or theyt^ gentium. They hold with Cicero that the civil law is organically related to the ultimate law of reason and justice ; that it is not merely the expression of the capricious will of the lawgiver, but con- stantly tends, at least, to embody, to apply to the actual con- ditions of' life, principles which are of perpetual obligation. We have seen that it is possible that the judgment of some of these may have been perplexed by their own distinction between the jus naturale and the jus gentium, that they may have felt that actually existing or universal institutions could not be con- sidered to belong to. the primitive and perpetual principles of life, while they were not prepared to condemn them. This only illustrates a perplexity of mind, which was indeed a natural result of the perpetual ambiguity in the concep- tion ot social justice in relation to the ideal justice, whether this is regarded as belonging to the past or to the future. The regulations of society ought to be just, and yet we are constantly compelled to amend them. Their claim to the obedience of man is founded upon the fact that they represent justice, and yet they never are in the complete sense of the word just. The perplexity with regard to the past found a solution for many centuries in the theory of a change in the condition of human nature, in the judgment that principles of perfect justice which were adapted to a condition of perfect innocence cannot well be adapted to a condition of vice and imperfection. In the eighteenth century, when many thinkers understood very imperfectly the social significance of the






62 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part il.

faultiness of human nature, the difficulty resulted in the revolutionary bias given to the conception of the return to nature. Gradually men have turned back to the conception of perfect justice as belonging to the future, as being the ideal towards which the institutions of society tend, the principle which governs their development ; but the difficulties of the actual condition have not therefore been completely solved. It is a thing worthy, of note how few have recognised the significance of the most resolute modern attempt to suggest a solution, the attempt made by Rousseau in his theory of the "General Will." In England Professor T. H. Green and, recently, Mr Bosanquet are among the very few who have recognised the real importance of that theory.






63


CHAPTEK VL

THE SOURCE OP POLITICAL AUTHORITY.

We have still to consider the theory of the Boman Lawyer® with regard to one very important subject, the source of authority in the State. It will be remembered that we found in Cicero a very interesting tendency towards a conception of liberty, as identified with a share in the control of the State. *^ The Roman Lawyers of the second century and onwards deal briefly indeed, but very distinctly, with the question of the ulti- mate source of authority in the State, and we think that, so far, they do very clearly carry on the tradition represented by Ciceror^ They do not conceive of the Boman citizen as having any direct , share in the actual administration of the Commonwealth, but in their view the Eoman citizens are the sole ultimate source of authority, whether legislative or administrative. The relation of \ their view to that of Cicero is interesting, but much more im- portant is the connexion between their theory and the demo- cratic theory of mediaeval and modern times. The mediaeval theory of the social contract, which, so far as we know, waa first put forward definitely in the end of the eleventh century, may have relations with such ancient forms of the theory as are perhaps suggested by Cidero ^ and had been ^developed by Plato,^ and perhaps by authors whose works have now dis- appeared. We shall see that the mediaeval theory is related primarily to the traditional ideas of the Teutonic races on '. government, and to the course of the history of the Teutonic \ empire and kingdoms. But at the same time, the theory of the Boman Lawyers with respect to the people as the

^ Cicero, De Rep., iii. 13. '^ Plato, Laws, iii, 684.






64 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

sole ultimate source of authority in the State seems to us to be clearly an undeveloped form of the theory of contract. We might call it the theory of consent, which is not the same thing as the theory of contract in any of its forms, but is the germ out of which the theory of contract might very well grow. When we discuss the theories of the mediaeval writers in detail we shall have to consider what traces there are of the direct influence of this aspect of the legal view, we shall certainly recognise that they were acquainted with it. In the meanwhile we consider the Roman Lawyers as expressing one aspect of the theory out of which the mediaeval and modern democratic conception of the State has grown.

Few phrases in the Digest are more familiar than that of Ulpian, " Quod principi placuit, legis habet vigorem " ; ^ some- times at least it has been forgotten that Ulpian continues, " ut- pote cum lege regia, quae de imperio ejus lata est, populus ei et in eum omne suum imperium et potestatem conferat." Few phrases are more remarkable than this almost paradoxical description of an unlimited personal authority founded upon a / purely democratic basis. The Emperor's will is law, but only I because the people choose to have it so. Ulpian's words sum up in a single phrase the universal theory of the lawyers ; so far as we have seen, there is no other view known to the Eoman jurisprudence. From Julianus, in the earlier part of the second century, to Justinian himself in the sixth, the Emperor is the source of law, but only because the people by their own legislative act have made him so. The matter is of such import- ance that we must justify this judgment by an examination of all the writers of the Digest who, so far as we have found, refer to the question.

The earliest discussion, in the Digest, of the authority which lies behind the civil law of Rome is, so far as we have seen, con- tained in a citation from Julianus, a jurist of the period of Hadrian and the Antonines. He is cited to illustrate the place of custom in law, and says that custom has rightly the force of law, inasmuch as law derives its authority from the people, and it is immaterial whether the people declares its will by vote or

1 Dig., i. 4. 1.






CHAP. VI.] THE SOURCE OF POLITICAL AUTHORITY.


65


by custom.^ It is certainly interesting to observe this un- compromising and dogmatic statement of the authority of the people in making and unmaking laws (leges). It might indeed be urged that lex is the distinctive name for the legislation of the popiUvs, and that we must not therefore press the phrases of Julianus to mean that leges are the only forms of law. We shall presently see that Gains, in his cljuisification of law, dis- tinguishes the lex from other forms of law: whether this distinction is here present to the mind of Julianus may perhaps be doubted; but if it is, we shall also probably judge that Julianus, like Gaius, looks upon the lex of the whole people as the original form of law, from which all other forms are descended.

Gaius has furnished us with a general definition of the nature of the civil law in that passage which we have had occasion to quote several times.* We must now examine the words with which he carries out the definition in detail, with regard to the Boman State.^ It might seem at first sight that there are here as many authorities as there are forms of law, but a closer


1 Dig., i. 3. 32: "InveteraU consuetudo pro lege non immerito cus- toditur, et hoc est jus quod dicitur moribus constitutum. Nam cum ipsse legeB nulla alia ex causa nos teneaut, quam quod judicio populi receptee sunt, merito et ea, quae sine uUo scripto populus probavit tenebunt omnes: nam quid interest suffragio populus voluntatem suam declaret an rebus ipsis et factis ? Quare rectissime etiam illud receptum est, ut leges non solum sufiragio legis latoris, sed etiam tacito consensu omnium per desuetudinem abrogentur."

'^ Gaius, Inst., L 1. ; Dig., i. 1. 9 : "Quod quisque populus ipse sibi jus constituit, id ipsius proprium est, voca- turque jus civile, quasi jus proprium civitatis."

'Gaius, Inst., i. 2.-7.: "Constant

autens jura populi Romani ex legLbus,

plebiscitis, senatus - consultis, consti-

tutionibus principum, edictis eorum

VOL. I.


qui jus edicendi habent, responsis prudentium. Lex est quod populus jubet atque constituit. Plebiscitum est quod plebs jubet atque constituit. . . . Unde olim patricii dicebant plebiscitis se non teueri, quae ^ne auctoritati eorum facta essent: sed postea lex Hortensia lata est, qua cautum est ut plebiscita universum populum tenerent ; itaque eo modo legibus exaequata sunt. Senatus-con- sultum est quod senatus jubet atque constituit, idque legis vicem obtinet, quamvis fuerit quaesitum. Constitutio principis est quod imperator decreto, vel edicto, vel epistola constituit, nee ' umquam dubitatum est, quin id legis vicem obtineat, cum ipse imperator per legem imperium accipiat. Jus autem edicendi habent magistratus populi Romani. . . . Responsa prudentium sunt sententise et opiniones eorum quibus permissum est jura condere."


E






66 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

observation shows us that ultimately these come back to the authority of the whole populus. It is they and they alone who

•^ have the power of making a lex, and all other authority is derived from this. Thus the plebisQsiMm, or law made by the plebs alone, without the other classes, only has the force of law because this was decreed by the lex Hortensia. The constitution of the prince, in the same way, has the force of law because the emperor receives his im pemum, per legem . The magistrates have theyjtse<cKcmrfi, but this no doubt is derived from their election. The Bespqma Frudentium, if they all agree, have the force of law, but this is because such an authority is given to the juris- consults. The only form of law of which we cannot definitely conclude, from this statement of Gaius, that its authority can be traced back to the people, is the Senqtus consuUum. Gaius does not define the mode in which this form of law came to be recognised as such. Pomponius suggests that it was due to the growing difficulty of getting together the populus as the Eoman population increased i^ both he and Gaius seem to look upon the legislative authority of the Senate as tacitly recognised, though, as Gaius seems to indicate, at first there was hesitation about it. The same theory of the source of authority is put before us in that very interesting account of the origin and develop- ment of the Roman legal system, by Pomponius, a con- temporary of Gaius, to which we have just referred.* In this we have a succinct history of the Roman law from the time of Romulus down to the organisation of the Imperial system. The most important points in this are as follows. At first there was no certain lex or jtis in the State, and all things were directed by the kings. Romulus first began to propose definite laws {leges) to the people. After the expulsion of the kings these laws went out of use, and for some time the Roman

• people was governed rather by uncertain usages and customs than by definite laws. At last ten men were appointed to pro- cure laws from the Greek cities, that the State might be founded on laws (leges), and they were given supreme authority in the State for a year, to put these into order and to correct them if necessary, and to interpret them with such authority that there

1 Dig., i. 2. 2, 9. 2 Dig., i. 2. 2.






CHAP. VI.] THE SOURCE OP POLITICAL AUTHORITY. 67

should be no appeal from them. These laws, to which the name of the laws of the Twelve Tables was given, were finally adopted. They needed to be interpreted by the great lawyers, and out of this interpretation grew up that form of jus connected with the prudentes, the jvs which is " proprium jus civile, quod sine scripto in sola prudentium interpretatione consistit." Then on the basis of these laws were founded the " legis actiones." Later it came about that there was a dispute between the plebs and the patres, and the plebs made laws for themselves which were called plehiscita} When the plebs had been brought back and much discord had arisen with respect to these plebiscita, it was finally agreed that they should be recognised as legeSy and this was sanctioned by the lex Hortensia.^ Then, the people growing so numerous that it was difficult to gather together the populvs, or even the plebs, the very necessity of the case made it necessary that the Senate should be charged with the care of the State, and the Senate began to issue decrees : this form of law was known as Senattis consultum? At the same time the magistrates who declared the law issued their edicts, that the citizens might know exactly the jvs under which cases would be decided. Finally it became necessary that one man should be charged with the care of the State ; a prince was created, and he was given the authority, that whatever he should ordain should have the force of law.*

It is interesting to observe the laborious care with which Pomponius explains each new development in the legal system. By his presentation of the subject we see again that, with the exception of the Senattcs consultum, every form of law derives

^ Dig., i 2. 2, 8 : " Evenit ut plebs qtiidquid constituisset observabatur,

in discordiam cum patribus perven- idque jus apellabatur seuatus con-

iret et secederet sibique jura constit- sultum." ueret quse jura plebiscita vocantur." * Dig., i. 2. 2, 11 : "Novissime, sicut

^ Dig. , i. 2. 2, 8 : " Pro legibus ad pauciores juris constituendi vias

placuit et ea observari lege Hortensia : transisse ipsis rebus dictantibus vide-

et ita factum est, ut inter plebiscita et batur per partes, evenit, ut necesse

legem species constituendi interesset esset reipublicse per unum consuli

potestas autem eadem esset." (nam senatus non perinde omnes pro-

'Dig., i. 2. 2, 9: "Necessitas ipsa vincias probe gerere poterat) : igitur

curam reipublicse ad senatum deduxit ; constituto principe datum est ei jus

ita coepit senatus se interponere et ut quod constituisset, ratum esset."






68 POLITICAL THEORY OP ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

its authority ultimately from the populvs. This is especially important with respect to the Imperial power, and here indeed Pomponius's phrases are almost apologetic in their anxiety to account for the legislative authority of the Emperor. The historical value of Pomponius's account is of course a very dififerent matter from its interest to us : so far, indeed, as we are concerned, this is quite immaterial ; we are only concerned: with his narrative as illustrating the political theory of the second century, and for that purpose it is invaluable.

Early in the third century we come to Marcianus, whose citations from Demosthenes and Chrysippus we have already examined in another connexion. We must return to the first of these in relation to our present inquiry. His words are as follows: "This is law which all men should obey for many reasons, and especially because every law is a thing found and given by God, a judgment (Soyfia) of wise men, a correction of voluntary and involuntary transgressions, a common agreement of the State, in accordance with which all those who are in the State should live."^ We have already discussed the significance of the first part of this definition: for our present purposes the important phrases are two — that a law is something decreed or advised by wise men, and some- thing adopted by the common agreement of the State. This latter part of the definition is adopted by Papinian, a contem- porary of Marcianus: his definition is, with slight modifica- tion, evidently taken from that of Demosthenes.* In this definition, then, it is clear that the immediate source of the authority of the law of any State is the agreement of the whole State, and we may take it that it governs the short genertd description of the civil law given by Papinian in another place, where he deals with it in very much the same terms as Gkius : * we are entitled to interpret this classification by the definition to which we have just referred.

We have, then, come down to the time of TJlpian, with whose

  • Dig., i. 3. 2. See p. 56, note 1. munis reipublicse sponsio."

2 Dig., i. 3. 1 : "Lex est commune ' Dig., i. 1. 7 : "Jus autem civile

prseceptum, virorum prudentium con- est quod ex legibus, plebis scitis

sultum, delictorum quae sponte vel senatus consultis, decretis principum,

ignorantia contrahuntur coercitio, com- auctoritate prudentium venit. "






CHAP. VI.] THE SOURCE OF POLITICAL AUTHORITY. 69

sentence on the Imperial authority we commenced our inquiry. We are now in a position to recognise that his statement, that the authority of the prince is derived from the fact that the people have by the lex regia conferred on him all their authority, is strictly in harmony with the political theory of all the earlier jurists. But we can trace the same theory down to the time of Justinian himself. In a rescript of Theodosius and Valentinian of the year 429, the relation of the Imperial authority to the law is expressed in very clear and forcible termd. Theodosius and Valentinian say that the prince is bound by the laws, for his authority is drawn from the authority of the law.i Nothing could well be plainer than this statement, nothing could show more clearly that the theory of Ulpian is still the theory of the fifth century. And, finally, in the rescript which is prefixed to the Digest, we find Justinian himself referring in explicit terms to the ancient law by which the Roman people transferred all their authority and power to the Emperor.^

It is true that in Justinian we also find some trace of a con- ception out of which there grew another theory of the author- ity of the ruler. The first words of the rescript we have just quoted are, " Deo auctore nostrum gubemantes imperium, quod nobis a caelesti majestate traditum eat." * In another rescript, also prefixed to the Digest, we read, "quia ideo imperialem fortunam rebus humanis deus prseposuit, ut possit omnia quae noviter contingunt et emendare et componere et modis et regulis competentibus tradere." * In another place still, he speaks of Grod subjecting all laws to the Emperor, whom He has given to men as a living law.^ These phrases may be compared with those of Seneca and Pliny, to which we have already referred,^

^ Codex, i. 14. 4 : " Digna vox majes- Roman! in imperatoriam translata sunt

tate regnantis legibus alligatum le potestatem." principem profiteri i adeo de auctori- ' Cod., i. 17. 1.

tate juris nostra pendet auctoritas. * Cod., i. 17. 2, 18.

Et reveramajusimperioestsubmittere * Novel., cv. 4: TiJarrotv 8c 8^ rSav

legibus principatum. Et oraculo prse- elfrnfUvnv rifiiv ri ficurt\4(as ifyp^aOay

sentis edicti quod nobis licere non ti^x'?* jf 7* **^ ainohs 6 Oths robs v6fiovs^

patimur indicamus." 8ir^6tj<c€ v6fiov avriip tfiy^vxov Kara.

  • Cod., i. 17. 1, 7 : " Cum enim x4fv^af dv$p<&irois.

lege antiqua, quae regia nuncupabatur, * See p. 31.

omne jus omnisque potestas populi






70 POLITICAL THEORY OP ROMAN LAWYERS. [part ii.

and with the patristic conception of the relation between God and the ruler, which we shall presently iave to examine ; but in themselves the words of Justinian can hardly be pressed to mean more than that the providence of God rules even over the matters of the State.

From the second century, then, to the sixth, we have seen

that the Eoman law knows one, and only one, ultimate source of

, political power, and that is the authority of the people. It may of course* be said that this is the merest abstract theory, that during this time the Imperial power was obteined-by every method, but never by that -of popular appointment; that the legislative authority of the people was only a name and a pretence, and it must be noticed that Justinian seems even to speak of the Emperor as the sole^ legis lator, as though, in fact, the legislative action of the Koman popvlus had wholly ceased. But still the theory of the ultimate authority of the people subsisted, and so came down till it touched the new Teutonic theory of law and political authority, a theory which again knew nothing of any legislative authority in the State apart from the whole body of the State.

We think that the legal theory, that all political power is ^ derived from the people, is at least one of the sources from i which the theory of the social contract sprang. It is far from being the same theory, but it seems to us to represent an ele- mentary form of the same conception. The Boman lawyers indeed usually deal with the matter only from the. point of view of the Roman Commonwealth, but this is not always the case. Papinian, and Marcianus in his citation from Demos- thenes,* define law in terms of universal application. And, after all, the Empire was to the Roman much the same as the world. The principles which belonged to it were at lejuit the principles of the civilised world, and their application to the conditions of the world at large was natural and easy.

1 Cod., i. 14. 12, 3 and 4. » See p. 68.






71


CHAPTER VII.

THE POLITIC A.L THEORY OF JUSTINIAN's INSTITUTES.

Wi; have so far examined mainlj the jurists of the second and third centuries, and have endeavoured to make ourselves clear as to the general character of the political theory which they rep- resent. We have observed that their theory is not something fixed, but that we can trace the changes of legal opinion, in the course of these centuries, with regard at least to some subjects. It is for our purpose important that we are able to compare these views with those of the lawyers of the sixth century as embodied in the Institutes of Justinian. From such a comparison we are able to arrive at some conclusions with regard to the permanent tendencies of the legal traditions, to judge, with respect to certain of them, which ultimately tended to predominate. It must at the same time be con- fessed that the compilers of the Institutes were so anxious to express themselves in the phrases of the great lawyers of the second century that it is often diflBcult to be quite certain as to their own opinions. It is difficult to imagine that the com- pilers were not aware that the passages- they quote from dif- ferent writers often represent views inconsistent with each other, and yet they do actually sometimes join together in the same passage citations which are completely out of harmony.

This carelessness of construction is nowhere more noticeable than it is with reference to the theory of the law of nature. We think that the opinion of the authors of the Institutes on the subject is clear and distinct, but it must be admitted that occasionally they embody in their work phrases which belong to another view. Their general position will be sufficiently






72 POLITICAL THEORY OP ROMAN LAWYERS. [part II.

shown by a few sentences: "Dicendum est igitur de jure private, quod est tripertitum ; coUectum est enim ex naturalibus prseceptis aut gentium aut civilibus." ^ This dogmatic statement of the threefold character of law is followed by the definition of the j%is naturale which is cited in the Digest from Ulpian, and then by the definition of thejtcs gentium from Gaius's Institutes, and a description of the jm civile ; ^ they add that account of the JUS gentium which we have had occasion to notice before.*

The fact that the compilers of the Institutes follow Ulpian in distinguishing the Jus gerUium from the jus naturale is cer- tainly clear enough. It is true that the first two passages we have just mentioned are quoted directly from Ulpian, but the last mentioned is not taken from any known source (with the exception of the words, "Jure enim naturali ab initio," &c.) We have already suggested that it may be related to that passage from Hermogenianus * which we have already mentioned, but the explanation of the origin of the in- stitutions is not contained in the passage from Hermogenianus, as we have it in the Digest. At any rate, whether these phrases are wholly borrowed or partly original, they do very clearly show that the compilers of the Institutes distinguished between the jus naturale and the jus gentium, and the last passage gives us some indication of their conception of the nature of the distinction.

Before we discuss the meaning of the jus naturale in the Institutes, we must examine one passage which seems directly to contradict those which we have just considered. This passage is contained in the first title of the Second Book of the Institutes, a title which deals with certain general questions of property.^ This passage is evidently founded upon those words

^ Inst., i. 1. 4. liberi nascebantur. Ex hoc jure gen-

^ Inst.y i 2. tium et omnes paene contractus intro-

^ Inst., i. 2. 2 : ^^ Jus autem gentium ducti sunt, ut emptio venditio, locatio

onini humauo generi commune est. conductio, societas, depositum, mu-

Nam usu exigente et humanis necessi- tuum et alii innumerabiles."

tatibus gentes humanse qusedam sibi * Dig., i. 1. 5. See p. 42, note 1.

constituerunt: beUaetenimortasuntet 'Inst., ii. 1. 11: "Singulorum

captivitates secutae et servitutes, quae autem hominum multis modis res

sunt juri naturali contrariae. Jure fiunt: quarundam enim rerum do-

enim naturali ab initio omnes homines minium nanciscimur jure naturali,






OH. VII.] POLITICAL THEORY OF JUSTINIAN'S INSTITUTES. 73

of Gaius's in the Digest, which we have already several times had occasion to quote,^ but the compilers of the Institutes have made several important changes. In the first place, they have substituted the words "jure naturali, quod sicut diximus appellatur jus gentium" for Gaius's words, "jure gen- tium, quod ratione naturali inter omnes homines perseque ser- vatur." Next, they have wiitten " Palam est autem vetustius esse naturale jus, quod cum ipso genere humano rerum natura prodidit " in place of Gaius's " Et quia antiquius jus gentium cum ipso genere humano rerum natura proditum est"; and finally, they have added the last clause. The two latter points are in- teresting, but the real difficulty is raised by the first sentence.

We have just seen that the authors of the Institutes separate the jii8 ncUurcUe from the jus gentium. It is difficult to under- stand what they can mean by saying that the law of nature is called the jus gentium : they not only say this, but add that they have said it already, while we can find np trace of any such statement in the earlier parts of the Institutes. The form of the statement suggests that we may have here a quotation from some otherwise unknown source. We can only conjecture either that this is the explanation of the phenomenon, or that this is to be found in the fact that the passage forms part of a title which deals with the theory of property, consisting for the most part of citations from Gaius, Marcianus, and other jurists who identify the jus naturale and the jtis gentium, and that the editors have adapted their language to this fact. The statement is certainly perplexing, but it seems impossible to allow this phrase to change the conclusion which we derive from the clear and repeated statements which we have already examined. There can be no doubt that normally the authors of the Institutes did distinguish the jus naturale from the jus gentium.

Their formal definition of the jus naturale ^ is, as we have

quod sicut diximus appellatur jus gen- enim jura tunc coeperunt, cum et civi-

tium, quarundam jure civili. Com- tates condi et magistratus creari et

modius est itaque a vetustiore jure in- leges scribi coeperunt."

cipere. Palam est autem vetustius esse ^ Dig., xli. 1. 1. See p. 37, note 2.

naturale jus, quod cum ipso genere ^ Inst., i. 2.

humano rerum natura prodidit : civilia






74 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part il.

seen, the same as that of Ulpian, — that is, they reproduce that definition which suggests that the jtbs naturale means little more than the instincts common to all animals. But whatever may be the case with Ulpian, this definition does not appear to present at all a complete account of the view of the authors of the Institutes. At the close of the same title they use phrases descriptive of the/wra naturalia which seem to convey quite another conception, the conception of their divine and

J immutable character.^ The matter may be illustrated from other passages. In the Third Book of the Institutes we find a phrase of much significance.^ The "natural laws" here are equivalent to permanent and divine principles of life

- f which are superior to the civil law, and to which the civil law ought to be conformed. In the same title we find the action of the praetor, in admitting emancipated children to a share in the inheritance of their parents, described as being due to the sense of " paturalis sequitas." ^ Again, the same title and the next, in dealing with the changes of the law of succession in relation to females and their representatives, describe certain changes in the civil law as being due to the feeling that the old law was contrary to nature and to the inspiration of a humaner sense.* Natural laws are divine and ought to govern and correct all other forms of law, for they represent the per- manent principles of justice and humanity. This is evidently j quite another view of the jvs naturale from that which may 1 seem to be expressed in the formal definition of Ulpian which the Institutes cite. It would appear, then, that whatever uncertainty we may feel as to the meaning attached to the jm naturale by Ulpian and his contemporaries, by the sixth century the phrase was certainly taking that meaning which

/ ^ Inst., i. 2. 11: "Sed naturalia ' Inst., iii. 1. 9: "Sed praetor natural!

quidem jura, quae apud omnes gentes aequitate motus dat eis bonorum pos-

peraeque servantur, divina quadam pro- sessionem. "

videntia constituta semper firma atque * Inst., iii. 1. 15 : "Divi autem prin-

immutabilia permanent : ea vero, quae cipes non passi sunt talem contra

ipsa sibi quaeque civitas constituit, saepe naturam injuriam sine competent!

mutari Solent vel tacito consensu populi emendatione relinquere." Inst., iii.

vel alia postea lege lata.'* 2. 3a, "humano proposito,*' and 7,

2 Inst, iii. 1. 11 : "Naturalia enim "humanitate suggerente." jura civilis ratio peremere non potest."






CH. VII.] POLITICAL THEORY OF JUSTINIAN's INSTITUTES. 75

it has throughout the Middle Ages and later — that is, that the jv^ naturale means that body of principles of justice and reason which men can rationally apprehend, and which forms the ideal norm or standard of right conduct and of the justice of social institutions.

We do not mean that the authors of the Institutes had arrived at any perfectly clear judgment on the matter, — on the contrary, the fact of their reproducing Ulpian's definition shows us sufficiently clearly that this was not the case, — but we think that the tendency of their thought is clear enough, that they show us the development of a conception which in the second century was still unformed and indistinct. We have seen that the jtts gentium was by Gains conceived as embodying the principles of justice and reason, that indeed the fus gentium in Gains is practically the same thing as they^^s no^wro/e in Cicero. The conception, therefore, of a principle of law, apprehended by reason as lying behind all positive law and embodying the principles of justice and reason, was not new. The new thing was simply the distinction between this ultimate law and the Jus gentium.

We have already considered the question of the causes which led to this distinction. We think that in the main it must have arisen from the judgment that certain institutions, which were actually universal, could not be looked upon as having been primitive or natural in the full sense of the word. It is ronnd the question of slavery that this distinction, as far as our evidence goes, seems to take shape in the legal writings, and this, again, seems to be related to the ques- tion of natural equality. But the conception could be ex- tended easily to other conditions and circumstances of life. The distinction between the jus naturale and the jus gentium seems, then, to be very clearly related to the distinction between the primitive state of nature and the conventional organisation of society. The writers of the Institutes do not deal with this directly and explicitly, but in two passages at least they seem to come a good deal nearer to it than any writer cited in the Digest, with the possible exception of Hermogenianus. We have already quoted these passages, but must do so again. The






76 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [PART II.

first comes after the definition of the tripartite law, and resumes the description of the jvs gentium which had been first given in the words of Gains. This passage, which, as we have already mentioned, is not drawn from any known source, though it reminds us of Hermogenianus, seems quite clearly to imply a contrast between the primitive conditions of human life and the time when the conditions and institutions referred to came into existence.^ The other phrase comes at the end of that passage which we have already mentioned in discussing the relation of the jics ndturale and the jvs gentium,^ In this passage, as we have already seen, the authors of the Institutes have spoken of the jvs naturale and the jvs gentium as being identical, and therefore the primitive condition is not thought of under terms which belong in any exclusive sense to the jvs natv^ale. But the writers of the Institutes do seem clearly to conceive of a time when States did not exist, nor magistrates, nor written laws. That is, they seem to contrast the primitive conditions of human life, in which such institutions as those mentioned did not exist, with the later time when they did.

Tne treatment of slavery in the Institutes is the same as that in Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus ; indeed, with the excep- tion of the words, " bella etenim orta sunt, et captivitates secutse, quae sunt juri naturali contrarise," * they simply reproduce the phrases of Ulpian and Florentinus, "Jure enim naturali ab initio omnes homines liberi nascebantur," * and " Servitus autem est constitutio juris gentium, qua quis dominio alieno contra naturam subjicitur." *

We need not say anything as to the theory of property in the Institutes : it does not seem to differ in any way from that presented in the Digest. The compilers simply put together in shorter form the same views as those which we have seen to

^ Inst., i. 2. 2 : *' Jus autem gen- vetustius esse naturale jus, quod cum

tium omni humano generi commune ipso genere humano rerum natura

est. Nam usu exigente et humanis prodidit : civilia enim jura tunc coeper-

necessitatibus gentes humanse qusedam unt, cum et civitates condi et magis-

sibi constituerunt : beUa etenim orta tratus creari et leges scribi coeperunt."

sunt et captivitates secutsQ et servi- ' Inst. , i. 2. 2.

tutee quae sunt juri naturaU "con- ^ Inst., i. 2. 2. Cf. Dig., i. 1. 4.

trario.*' ' Inst., i. 8. 2. Cf. Dig., i. 5. 4.

2 Inst., ii. 1. 11 : "Palam est autem






CH. VII.] POLITICAL THEORY OF JUSTINIAN's INSTITUTES. 77

be generally held by the jurists of the second and third cen- turies. They throw no further light on that interesting passage from Hermogenianus on which we have commented.

And again we find the same thing to be the case with regard to the theory of the relation of the civil law to the general principles of law : the writers of the Institutes begin their own treatise with Ulpian's definition of justice and of the general character of jurisprudence,^ but they add nothing. And so, again, with regard to the source of the authority of the civil law. They define the varieties of the civil law and the source of their authority mainly in the words of Gains and of Ulpian.* They represent the same tradition which we have seen to be characteristic of all the legal theory of Rome from the second century to Justinian, that the Roman people are the ultimate source of the authority of the civil law of Rome.*

The Institutes then furnish us with valuable information as to the development of the theories of natural law and the natural state between the second century and the sixth, and seem to show us that, with regard to the other subjects into which we have inquired, the legal theory continues during these centuries unchanged.

Looking back now on our examination of the political theory of the Roman lawyers, we feel it in the first place important to observe how very small a place such theory occupies in their work. We have been compelled to take up a considerable space in our discussion of this, but that is simply due to the fact that the subject is obscure, and that there are many points whose interpretation presents some diflBculties. The references of the lawyers to the theory of politics are few in number, and some- what slight, if not superficial, in character. We cannot pretend to think that the lawyers contributed much to the philosophy of the State by their own reflections, but in reproducing the theories current among intelligent men they probably did much to give them a precise and definite character, and the mere fact of the embodiment of such theories in the technical law-books could not but give them a new importance and influence. The

1 Inst., i. 1. 1. Cf. Dig., i. 1. 10. ^ jng^,^ i 2. 3.3. » Inst., I 2. 6.






78 POLITICAL THEORY OF ROMAN LAWYERS. [part ll.

• influence of the lawyers in the development of political theory was probably quite out of proportion to their actual capacity as political thinkers. Their importance for our purpose is obvi- ously very great: the period to which they belong is one in which there seems to have been very little formal writing on political theory, or else the works which may have dealt with this have disappeared. The lawyers furnish us with the best materials for estimating what was the general tendency of political theory during these centuries, apart from the Christian influences. When we turn to the Christian Fathers we shall iind that they provide us with much information on our subject, but if we were to go to them without first examining the views of the lawyers, we should have some difficulty in discriminating between conceptions which belong to the Christiaii tradition and those which were the common property of the Koman world. The influence of the jurists upon mediaeval political thought is very great, certainly very obvious, and while, as we shall see, the relations between mediaeval thought and the Eoman jurisprudence may often be somewhat superficial, yet its influence is so constant, both directly and through the gradu- ally growing and developing body of the Canon Law, that some study of the Koman law is necessary as a preliminary to any complete examination of mediaeval ideas.

If now we consider what are historically the most important

elements in the political theory of the Eoman lawyers, we shall

^ be inclined to say that first in order of significance comes their

contribution to the theory of the natural law and the natural

state. We have seen how these conceptions take shape or are

implied in the writings pf the jurists of the second century, and

are by them transmitted to those of the sixth. We have seen

that these conceptions seem to be related to some judgment,

instinctive perhaps rather than fully reasoned, that some actual

institutions of society cannot be thought of as being strictly in

harmony with the primitive conditions of human life, which are

also conceived of as representing some ideal system of justice.

We have seen that through Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Floren-

tinus the theory of the natural equality and liberty of mankind

, passed into the system of the Eoman law, and it can hardly be






CH. VII.] POLITICAL THEORY OF JUSTINIAN's INSTITUTES. 79

doubted that this fact was not without a powerful influence upon the course of speculation on the theory of human institutions.

Secondl y, we think it is probable that the influence of the lawyers on future times was greater than we might at first j think with respect _to thejheory of Jhe rdatiouiiLiaw.amL-the ultimate p rinciple prjustice. They contributed at lejuit to fix for many centuries in the minds of men the conviction that the civil law of any State represents the practical application of the principles of justice and reason. Cicero and the Stoics indeed had maintained this view with clearness and conviction ; but whether it would have become predominant apart from the influence of the jurists may perhaps be doubted. When we come to discuss the theory of St Augustine, we may have occasion to observe some signs of another view.

And, ^finally, we think that in the conception of the Boman lawyers as to the source of authority in the State we probably have one foundation of the mediaeval and modem theory of democracy. We shall have to study the immediate sources of this in later chapters of this volume, and in the next volume we shall have to examine the mediaeval conception in detail, and shall then be in a position to estimate more precisely the importance of the contribution of the Boman lawyers to the development of modern democratic theory. But in the mean- while it is at least well worth observing that, if the ancient civilisation ended in a system of monarchical though legal ab- solutism, yet t he th eory of government which the jurists of the old world handed down to the new was a theory in which all authority in the State is conceived of as coming from the people.


f










PAET III.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS.


CHAPTEK VIIL i

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE NEW TESTAMENT.

We have so far been engaged upon an inquiry into the political theory of the ancient world, in its last stages indeed, but as un- affected by any of those new conceptions which may have come into it with Judaism and Christianity. W6 have now to con- sider the leading features of the political theory of the West as we find it in the Christian writers of the first six centuries of our era. We have to consider what contributions the new mode of thought actually made to the general stream of political and social ideas, how far it simply coincided with these, how far it may have changed them, and how far, even when it did in the main correspond with them, it may have tended to give these ideas a new form or a new force.

Historians have often spoken in general terms of the far- reaching effects of Christianity in changing men's conceptions with regard to the character, the purpose, and the ruling prin- ciples of human society, and no doubt the influence of Christi- anity upon these has been profound and far-reaching, but we think that we have already said enough to show that if we are to arrive at any just and well-grounded judgment upon this question, we must be at pains to discriminate very carefully

VOL. L F





82 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part hi.

those elements of the theory of Christian writers which are really original to them, and those in which they do but re- produce the opinions already current in the civilised world. There are, no doubt, certain elements of political and social theory which are distinctive of the Christian writers, but we shall have to recognise a little more distinctly than has always been done that very often they are simply drawing from the ' common stock of ideas current in their times.

We must begin by considering the significance and scope of the references to the theory of human nature and society in the New Testament. But behind the New Testament there lies the literature of the Old Testament, whether belonging to the earlier history of Israel or to the period between the Exile and the advent of our Lord. It is especially in the literature, whether canonical or apocryphal, of this later period, that we have to look for the explanation of many of the phenomena of New Testament theory : unhappily the field is as yet but very imperfectly explored. The obscurity of the period indeed corresponds in time and in importance with the parallel obscurity of the period between Aristotle and Cicero, and until more light has been thrown upon these centuries, much in the New Testament will remain difficult to understand, and still more difficult to explain with reference to sources and origins. Among the many obscurities of our subject, perhaps the most obscure and perplexing are the questions which arise as to the contact between Jewish and Hellenic ideas, and the influence which the latter exercised upon the former. The importance of the subject has long been recognised with regard to the interpretation of St Paul's concep'tion of religion and the world, but it may be much more important with regard to the whole of the New Testament than we yet understand.

We find in the New Testament matter of importance with / regard to the theory of natural law, the theory of human equality, the theory of property, and the theory of government. We begin by examining the theory of na tural law.

The references to this theory in tKe^ NevTTTestament are very scanty — ^indeed we have not observed any distinct refer-






CHAP, vin.] POLITICAL THEORY OF NEW TESTAMENT. 83

ence to the subject, except in one passage in St Paul's letter to the Eomans; but this reference is very clear and dis- tinct, and may be taken as presenting a conception which is constantly assumed by St Paul as true and important The passage occurs in a very important and indeed fundamental discussion of the relation to God of the Gentiles who have not received a revealed law from God: "For as many as have^ sinned without law shall also perish without law : and as many ^ as have sinned under law shall be judged by law ; for not the I hearers of a law are just before God, but the doers of a law shall be justified: for when Gentiles which have no law do , by nature the things of the law, these, having no law, are a law '{^. unto themselves ; in that they show the work of the law written in their hearts, their conscience bearing witness therewith." ^

There can be little doubt that St Paul's words imply some } . conception analogous to the " natural law " in Cicero, a law written in men's hearts, recognised by man's reason, a lawj distinct from the positive law of any State, or from what St Paul recognised as the revealed law of God. It is in this sense that St Paul's words are taken by the Fathers of the fourth and fifth centuries like St Hilary of Poitiers, St Ambrose, and St .Augustine,^ and there seems no reason to doubt the correctness , of their interpretation. It would be an interesting question to discuss the source of this conception in St Paul; how far it came to him from the presumably Hellenic culture of his youth at Tarsus, how far from the general stock of ideas current among the more educated Jews. For our purpose it is suffi- cient to observe that we find the conception in the New Testa- ment. We have already considered its character in the writ- c^ ings of Cicero, and the development of the conception among th,e jurists of the second and third centuries. We shall have to consider it again in the Christian Fathers.

We turn to the theory of human nature and equality in the . > New Testament, and first to this as presented in the teaching of

i

1 Roin._ii. 12'l< r et Vita Beata, vi., and Ep. Ixxiii. 2;

^ St Hilary of Poitiers, Comm. on St Augustine, contra Faustum Mani- Ps. cxviii. 119 ; St Ambrose, De Jacob chseum, xix. 2.






84 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

our Lord in the Gospels. Whatever questions may be raised as to the universalist and particularist aspects of the Gospels, it will, we think, now be admitted by all critics that the doctrine of our /A Lord must have contained the germs of that universalism which ultimately predominated in the Christian Church. It is evident that more or less clearly our Lord must have taught the doc- trine of the universal fatherhood of God, that in His eyes the distinctions of Jew and Gentile were not fundamental nor per- manent. The Jewish people are warned that " many shall come

'-y from the east and from the west, and shall sit down in the kingdom of heaven with Abraham, and Isaac, and Jacob," while the children of the kingdom, the people of Israel, are shut out.^ This is only one example of a conception which is continually making itself felt in warnings to the Jews, and in the expression of the universdtl compassion and mercy of God.

The same conception is expressed in set terms by St Paul, "There can be neither Jew nor Greek, there can be neither

y/j bond nor free, there can be no male and female : for ye all are one man in Christ Jesus '*;2 but this aspect of St Paul's teaching is too well known to need any detailed exposition. It is perhaps interesting and worth while to notice that the author of the Acts of the Apostles represents St Paul as ex- pressing the conception of the universal fatherhood of God in the terms of a Stoic philosopher and poet, " For in him we live, y and move, and have our being ; as certain even of your own poets have said. For we are also his offspring." ^ The doctrine of St Paul with regard to the common relation of all mankind to God is the same as that of the later philosophers.

We find, then, as characteristic of the Christian faith, that same conception of the identity of human nature over all the world which we have already considered in Cicero and Seneca. We cannot here enter into the question of the history of this conception in the later Judaism. We can see that among the Palestinian Jews there was still in St Paul's time a strong con- servative party which looked upon these sentiments with sus- picion. Apart from all the critical disputes as to the relation

' Matt. viii. 11, 12. and Col. iii. 11.

2 Gal. iii. 28. Cf. 1 Cor. xii. 13 ; » Acts xvii. 28.






CHAP. VIII.] POLITICAL THEORY OF NEW TESTAMENT. 85

of St Paul to Jewish Christians, there can be little doubt that it was the form of his universalism which, more than any other cause, tended to concentrate upon him the anger of the Jews.

There are indeed traces in Hebrew literature from an early date of a tendency to transcend the national principle in religion. Both in the first and the second parts of Isaiah, in connection with the expectation of the deliverer and restorer, there is expressed, however vaguely, the sense that his work will transcend the limits of the people of Israel, that it will be his work to establish righteousness and equity for all mankind, and to extend the knowledge of God over all the world.^ How far these ideas grew and developed during that most obscure period which followed the return from the great captivity, how far the nationalism of the Jews may have revived under the stress of the resistance to Hellenism under the Maccabees, how far the contact with Hellenism, even when resisted, may have yet actually tended to break down the Judaic isolation, — all this is a subject still obscure and perplexed. That our Lord took up again the tradition of the great prophets, and, translating it into a new form, gave it a profound and perma- nent life, seems clear, as is also the fact that St Paul carries on the doctrine of our Lord. The Christian Church then set out on its history with a conception of human nature which had outgrown the sense of national limitations, a conception which coincided very closely with the conception of the contemporary philosophy.

We shall therefore not be surprised to find that the treat- ment of slavery, and its relation to human nature, in the New Testament, is very closely analogous to that of the writers whom we have hitherto considered. We have a series of interesting passages which deal with the subject in St Paul's writings, and while these leave a good deal obscure, yet they enable us to form a fairly clear conception of the principles which from the first dominate the attitude of the Christian Church towards the institution of slavery.

The earliest reference to the subject by St Paul is contained in that passage which we have already considered,^ in which St

^ Cf. especially Isa. xi. 9-12 and xlii. 1-6. ^ q^^ jji, 28.






86 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

/ Paul speaks of the distinction between slave and freeman as one which has no meaning in relation to God. This evidently does not mean that Christianity has made the institution of slavery unlawful, but simply that it has no significance in God's sight, — that the slave, just as much as the freeman, is capable of the religious life, capable of knowing God and of the life of the child of God. We might translate St Paul's yphrase into other terms, — the slave is possessed of reason and

^ capable of virtue. St Paul would obviously have emphatically repudiated the notion that there is a natural or inherent dis- tinction in human nature, which renders some men capable of the higher life, while others must remain upon a lower level. y The passages in the Corinthian and Colqssian ^ letters to which we referred are strictly parallel, but add nothing further.

In the letter to Philemon we have a practical commentary on - this conception, and we have a further development of St Paul's principles with regard to slavery. St Paul sends a certain Ones- imus back to his master Philemon, from whom he had appar- ently escaped. He had fallen in with Sfc Paul and been converted to Christianity. It is very noteworthy that St Paul felt it right to send Onesimus back to his master, and does not even suggest that Philemon should set him at liberty. On the other hand, St Paul expects Philemon to receive Onesimus not as a mere slave, a runaway to be punished, but as a beloved brother. The epistle seems to illustrate clearly two principles : that slavery is not in St Paul's mind unlawful, but that the

J condition of slavery is only external — that it has no existence in the moral and spiritual life.

We have another reference to the subject in the first letter to the Corinthians, which would be extremely interesting if we could be more confident as to its meaning : " Let each man abide in that calling wherein he was called. Wast thou called being a bond-servant ? care not for it : but if ^ thou canst become ^ free, use it rather. For he that was called in the Lord, being a bond-servant, is the Lord's freedman: likewise he that was called, being free, is Christ's bond-servant. Ye were bought with a price ; become not bond-servants of men. Brethren, let

1 ICor. xil 13; Col, iii. U. ^ Or, "Nay, even if."






CHAP, vm.] POLITICAL THEORY OF NEW TESTAMENT. 87


each man, wherein he was called, therein abide with GodJ One general conclusion can clearly enough be founded upon this passage, namely, that in relation to Christ it is completely indifferent whether a man is a slave or a freeman. But when we ask ourselves. Does St Paul in this passage advise a man to get his freedom if he can, or does he rather urge upon him that the whole thing is so unimportant that it is not worth while taking steps to obtain his freedom ? we find ourselves in much uncertainty, and can hardly express any decided opinion.

Another aspect of St Paul's conception of slavery is presented to us in two passages, obviously parallel to each other, but not identical. We may take first that in the letter to the Ephes- ians : " Bond-servants, be obedient unto them that according to the flesh are your masters, with fear and trembling, in single- 1^ ness of your heart, as unto Christ; not in the way of eye- service, as men-pleasers ; but as bond-servants of Christ, doing the will of God from the heart ; with good will doing service, as unto the Lord, and not unto men. . . . And, ye masters, do the same things unto them, and forbear threatening : knowing that both their Master and yours is in heaven, and there is no respect of persons with Him."* St Paul's phrases are very general in their character, but three conclusions may be drawn y3 from them. First, that he looks upon the performance of his >. work by the slave as a duty in the sight of God. Secondly, that before God the jnaster and the slave are on the same level. (£) Thirdly, it is probably safe to interpret St Paul's injunctions to the masters, " do the same things unto them," as meaning that they are to behave towards their slaves with fairness. Perhaps we may find the best commentary on these words in the parallel passage in the letter to the Colossians : " Bond-servants, obey in all things them that are your masters according to the flesh : not with eye-service, as men-pleasers, but in singleness of heart, fearing the Lord : whatsoever ye do, work heartily, as unto the Lord, and not unto men; knowing that from the Lord ye shall receive the recompense of the inheritance: ye serve the Lord Christ. For he that doeth wrong shall receive again

1 1 Cor. vii. 20-24. = Eph. vi. 6-9.







88 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

for the wrong that he hath done : and there is no respect of ^persons. Masters, render unto your bond-servants that which is just and equal; knowing that ye also have a Master in heaven."^ The first part of this passage is substantially the same as that in the Ephesian letter, but in the last sentence there is a change of phrase of some interest. Instead of " Masters, do the same things unto them," we have, " Masters, render unto your bond-servants that which is just and equal" (to hUaiov Kol Ttjv ta-oTrjTo), The words are a little vague, but at least they seem clearly to express the principle that justice and fairness is a quality which ought to belong to the relation of master and slave, that a man's actions in this relation ought to have the same quality as that which belongs to the other rela- tions of life. We are reminded of Cicero's phrase, " Meminerimus autem etiam adversus infimos justitiam esse servandam. Est autem infima condicio et fortuna servorum."^

St Paul's attitude to the question of slavery is obviously founded upon his conviction that all men are at least morally and spiritually equal in character. To him all men are in God's sight equal, distinctions of condition belong only to the outer man, men are to each other brothers. The conduct of masters towards their slaves must be governed by the sajne principles of equity and fairness as those which govern their relations to other men. We can hardly say that St Paul goes beyond the position of Cicero or Seneca as to the natural similarity and equality of human nature, or beyond Seneca in his judgment that slavery is a condition which only affects the outer character of the man. His theory of human nature is indeed very similar to theirs, and his attitude towards slavery is much the same. Seneca indeed goes somewhat further than St Paul when he recognises that slavery is to all men hateful and ^ burdensome ; ^ as we have seen, St Paul's attitude towards the question of the advantages of emancipation is uncertain. If St Paul's conception of slavery was to have a greater influence on the future of that institution, we must probably conclude that this was due to the fact that St Paul's judgment dominated the

^ C!Qt;Jii ^, iv. 1 . ' Seneca, De Beneficiis, iii. 19.

  • Cicero/De Ufliclis, i. 13. 41.


y-






CHAP. VIII.] POLITICAL THEORY OF NEW TESTAMENT. 89

thought and the practical tendencies of the Church, while Seneca's was but the sentiment of an individual, representa- tive probably of a very general judgment, but not enforced by an organised common judgment.

There are two references to the subject of slavery in the " Pastoral " epistles, but they illustrate not so much the theory of slavery as the relation of the writers of the New Testament to anarchical and disorderly elements in the primitive Church, which were probably of much greater importance than we have hitherto recognised. We shall have to deal with the matter immediately in connection with the theory of government in the New Testament. The passages are in the first letter to Timothy, and in the letter to Titus.^ The writer of the letters exhorts the slaves to honour and obey their masters, and particularly not to despise their masters if they also were Christians. We may probably infer that the writer felt that there was some danger lest the new sense of spiritual dignity, and of spiritual relation between Christians of all conditions, should tend violently to destroy the old social order: he is afraid lest the conduct of Christian men should bring discredit or suspicion upon the religion of Christ.

We turn to the theory of the institution of government, and here we find certain conceptions whose importance in the history of later political thought is very great indeed. The most important passage in the New Testament which is connected with this subject is that in the thirteenth chapter of St PauFs epistle to the Eomans. "Let every soul be in subjection to the higher powers : for there is no power but of God ; and the powers that be are ordained of God. There- fore he that resisteth the power withstandeth the ordinance of God: and they that withstand shall recdve to themselves / judgment. For rulers are not a terror to the good work, ^ but to the evil. And wouldest thou have no fear of the power? do that which is good, and thou shalt have praise from the same: for he is a minister of God to thee for good. / But if thou do that which is evil, be afraid; for he beareth^

1 1 Tim. vi. 1, 2 ; TitUB ii. 9, 10. Cf. 1 Peter ii. 18.


I






90 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.



not the sword in vain : for he is a minister of God, an avenger for wrath to him that doeth evil. Wherefore ye must needs be in subjection, not only because of the wrath, but also for conscience' sake. For for this cause ye pay tribute also; for they are the ministers of God's service, attending continually upon this very thing. Bender to all their dues: tribute to

\ whom tribute is due ; custom to whom custom ; fear to whom

I \ fear; honour to whom honour."^

^ This passage, which is of the greatest importance -throughoat C the whole course of mediaeval political thought, being indeed ^\ constantly quoted from the secoftiLcentjiry onwards, is indeed

^ pregnant and significant in the highest degree. It defines in the profoundest way the Christian theory of the nature of political society, while it furnishes us with the most interesting evidence with regard to the condition of the Christian societies of the apostolic period.


X }


^ St Paul's general meaning is plain and distinct. The order

r" of civil government is of divine institution, a thing deriving its

authority and sanction from God Himself ; to refuse to submit

to it is to refuse to submit to God ; obedience to the State is

not merely a political necessity, but a religious obligation.

But, we may ask, why is this so ? Why are we to take the

civil order of the State to be a divine institution, to which

we must render obedience as to God Himself ? Here also

St Paul's answer is clear and distinct; it is because the end

and purpose of civil government is to repress the^vil jyxd

tcr"TOCourage tlie good. The civil ruler is God's servant for a

vgood purpose "the good man need have no fear of the civil

ruler, but only the evil man. To put this into the more

technical phrases of political theory, St Paul means that we

Cmust obey the civil order, as having a divine authority, be-

iv cause it exists for the maintenance of justice. It is the

^just ^d of the civil State which gives it a sacred character.

There are some other passages of importance which should

be considered along with this one. In the letter to Titus ^

we have an exhortation in general terms to obedience to

authorities, and in the first letter to Timothy Christian men

^ Rom. xiii. 1-7. ^ Ti^ug yj^ \^ 2.






CHAP. Vlil.] POLITICAL THEORY OF NEW TESTAMENT. 91

are exhorted to pray "for kings and all that are in high"? place ; that we may lead a tranquil and quiet life in all V godliness and gravity."^ The position of the ruler is defined clearly, along with the ground of the attitude of Christian men towards him, namely, that it is his function to secure order and peace for society.

In the first letter of St Peter we have a more complete parallel to the phrases of St Paul in the Roman letter. "Be^ subject to every ordinance of man for the Lord's sake : whether ; it be to the king, as supreme ; or unto governors, as sent by him ' for vengeance on evil-doers and for praise to them that do well. For so is the will of God, that by well-doing ye should put to silence the ignorance of foolish men: as free, and not using your freedom for a cloke of wickedness, but as bond-servants of God. Honour all men. Love the brotherhood. Fear God. Honour the king."^ We have here the same conception as that of St Paul, that the authority of the ruler is divine, that obedience is to be rendered to him for the Lord's sake; and the same explanation of this, as resting upon the fact that

  • the function of the ruler is to punish the evil and to reward

the-foed. But the passage is also interesting £is suggesting to us some explanation of the urgency with which St Paul and the writer of this letter deal with the matter : for our purposes it is immaterial whether the author is, as we should judge probable, St Peter, or some other and later writer.

We might very well at first sight wonder what it is that leads St Paul and St Peter to insist upon such an obvious truism as that the honest man should respect and obey the civil power. J - The first explg,Q9.tiQn which offers itself is, that they are anxious^ to counteract some Jewish antipathy to the Koman rule, and > the explanation is consistent with the character of the persons' to whom the letter to the Eomans and the letter of St Peter are addressed. It is fairly clear that the Koman Church, •when St Paul wrote, consisted partly of Jewish, partly of Gentile Christians, and it would seem that the letter of St Peter may be addressed mainly to Jewish Christians.* It is indeed most

1 1 Tim. ii. 2. » Cf. 1 Peter i. 1 : iK\€Kro7s irapein'

2 1 Peter ii. 13-17. 9'fi/iois Siaairopcis,






92 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [part III.

probable that the Christian teachers were compelled at an early ^date to deal with this question of the relation of the Church to the Roman Government. The Jewish religious and political leaders had evidently tried to entangle our Lord in the difficult / questions relating to the Jewish nationality and the Eoman J Empire. There can be no mistake about the purpose of the question with regard to paying tribute to Csesar;^ it was obviously intended to involve our Lord in a charge either of Awrant of patriotism, or of disloyalty to the Eoman Government. The apparent failure of the attempt evidently did not prevent the Jewish authorities from bringing the latter charge ag«dnst our Lord. It is true that only St Luke's gospel actually records the definite form of the charge, " We found this man perverting >^j^ /our nation, and forbidding to give tribute to Csesar, and saying that he himself is Christ a king ; " * but it is clear from all the accounts of the trial before Pilate that some such charge must have been made. The common tradition of all the narratives represents Pilate as asking our Lord whether he claimed to be the King of the Jews,^ and there seems therefore to be nothing 'improbable in St John's statement that it was by pressing the charge of disloyalty that the Jewish leaders were able to coerce Pilate into ordering our Lord's crucifixion.* Our judgment is confirmed by the account of the inscription placed upon the cross.^ There is some evidence that this same charge of dis- loyalty was brought against the Christians in the later part of the first century. According to the author of the Acts of the Apostles, the Jews at Thessalonica tried to embroil the newly founded Christian community in that city with the authorities, by bringing against them a charge closely connected with that brought against our Lord. " These that have turned the world upside down are come hither also ; whom Jason hath received : and these all act contrary to the decrees of Caesar, saying that there is another king, one Jesus." ^ There may be some trace of charges of the same kind in the narrative of the incidents

^ Mark zii. 13-17, and parallels. *' John zix. 12-lS^

'^ Luke xxiii 2. ° Matt, xxvii. 37,^and parallels.

^ Matt, xxvii. 11 ; Mark xv. 2 ; Luke • Acts xvii 6, 7. xxiiL 3 ; John xviii. 33.






CHAP. VIII.] POLITICAL THEORY OF NEW TESTAMENT. 93

at Philippi,^ and in the charges brought against St Paul at Csesarea.^

The Apocalypse also furnishes us with clear evidence that, as a matter of- fact, the Jewish hatred of the Roman Government was at one time, and in some circles, common among Christian men, when Kome first turned from its early indifiFerence and careless protection, and became the violent enemy of the Christ- ian societies. Without entering into any discussion of the in- terpretation of the Apocalypse as a whole, or any criticism of its sources, it is at least obvious that we have in it an ex- 4 pression of the most intense hatred of the Roman oppressor, | which, even if it were Jewish in its original form, has been adopted by a Christian writer. It may of course be urged that this represents the feelings of one section only of the Christian community ; but even if this is so, the fact that such sentiments were current in any section of the Christian societies must be taken into account in considering the position of their leaders.

It is thus very possible that these leaders were compelled at a very early date to deal with the question of the relation of their converts to the Roman Government, and the suggestion is a reasonable one, that we might interpret the passages whose significance we are discussing, as being primarily intended to check any tendency on the part of the members of the Christian communities to adopt the national Jewish attitude towards the Roman Government.

But we do not think that this explanation is really adequate to the interpretation of these passages. They seem to have some more general significance ; there is no trace in them of any special reference to a Jewish attitude towards the Roman Government, such as we might reasonably expect to find were they intended primarily to detach Christian men from a Jewish nationalism. We thint that the full explanation of these phrases must be found in a characteristic of the early Christian societies, of which there are numerous traces in the apostolic letters, and which St Peter seems to indicate in the passage we have quoted : " For so is the will of God, that with well-doing j ye should put to silence the ignorance of foolish men : as free, j

^ Acts xvl 20, 21. 2 Acts xxiv. 5.






94 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part hi.

kf and not using your liberty for a cloke of wickedness, but as bond-servants of God." ^

The freedom of the Christian man is one of the most im- portant of the conceptions of St Paul: "With freedom did Christ set us free : stand fast therefore, and be not entangled again in a yoke of bondage." ^ We have just seen that St ( Peter's epistles also recognise freedom as a true characteristic lof the Christian. Even St James uses the name of freedom, (whatever may be the precise meaning which he attaches to the phrase.^ But it is also evident that the doctrine of the freedom of the Christian man was attended in the primitive Church with the same difficulties as in later times ; indeed we venture to think that it was precisely in primitive times that the difficulties and dangers attending upon the conception made themselves most urgently felt.

It requires only a slight study of the apostolic writings to perceive that if the early Christian teachers had hard work to overcome the traditional legalism of the Jew, they were 1/ confronted with an almost equally dangerous tendency to ^ anarchism, especially no doubt among their Gentile converts. The tendency shows itself first in a disposition to slight the ordinary duties of life, to refuse submission to the discipline of the common life. " We exhort you, brethren," St Paul says in his first letter to the Thessalonians, " that ye abound more and more [in works of love] ; and that ye study to be quiet, and to do your own business, and to work with your own hands, even as we charged you."* And again, "We exhort you, brethren, admonish the disorderly."^ And so again in the second letter, " Now we command you, brethren, in the name of our Lord Jesus Christ, that ye withdraw yourselves from every brother that walketh disorderly, and not after the tradition which they received of us. For yourselves know how ye ought to imitate us: for we behaved not ourselves disorderly among you; neither did we eat bread for nought at any man's hand, but in labour and travail, working night

1 1 Peter ii. 15, 16. * 1 Thess. iv. 10, 11.

2 Gal. V. 1. Cf. 2 Cor. iii. 17. « 1 Thess. v. 14.

3 James i. 26, ii. 12.






CHAP. VIII.] POLITICAL THEOKY OF KEW TESTAMENT. 95

and day, that we might not be a burden to any of you. . . . ^

For even when we were with you, this we commanded you, If '-^^'^ any will not work, neither let him eat. For we hear of some that walk among you disorderly, that work not at all, but are busybodies. Now them that are such we command and exhort in the Lord Jesus Christ, that with quietness they work, and eat their own bread." ^ It would appear that in the Thessalonian church a number of persons had so interpreted the Christian spirit of freedom, and the Christian consciousness

[of the dignity of the spiritual relation of man to God, that they were disinclined to submit to the ordinary duties of life, and to any kind of human authority.

The same tendencies, if under slightly different forms, exhibit themselves in the Corinthian church. It is clear from any examination of the letters to this church that St Paul had a very real difficulty, especially with his own Grentile converts, ta persuade th^ that the liberty of the Christian man did not mean a complete emancipation from all discipline and order in life. It is clear that some at least of the Corinthian Christians were inclined to press the principle of the indifference of external rules and forms to the point of a complete disregard of the principle of that mutual sub- ordination of desires and actions which alone makes social life possible. "All things are lawful"^ seems to have been ^ N the catchword of this tendency. St Paul argues that, while it is quite true that the Christian man is free from the legal principle in life, he must remember that his conduct must be governed^ by the fundamental principles of society, the principles of mutual love and consideration. "All things are ux^ lawful ; but all things are not expedient. All things are lawful ; but all things edify not. Let no man seek his own, but each his neighbour's good." ^ And so with regard to those spiritual gifts which St Paul and the Corinthian Christians firmly believed that they possessed, St Paul tries to persuade them that not the more remarkable and conspicuous, or the more abstractly

^ 2 These, iii. 6-12. (The import- the authorship of the letter.) ance of the passage is independent of ^ 1 Cor. vi. 12, x. 23.

any question that may be raised as to ^1 Cor. x. 23, 24.






J\


96 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

spiritual gifts were the most valuable, but rather the gifts of service and counsel, and that the greatest gift was that of love.^ Even in writing to the Galatian churches, when St Paul was stirred to the very depths of his nature by the

> necessity of counteracting the legal spirit which threatened

> to take possession of them, St Paul warns his converts against the misinterpretation and perversion of the conception of liberty, " For ye, brethren, were called for freedom ; only use not your freedom for an occasion to the flesh, but through love be servants one to another." ^ There can, we think, be little doubt that the early Church was troubled with anarchical tendencies, very similar to those of some of the Anabaptist movements of the sixteenth century, and that these sprang from the same source. The reaction against the legal spirit

I carried men ofif their feet, and St Paul has to take the greatest pains to counteract the possible effects of his own teaching, just as Luther had to do when he wrote his treatise on * The Liberty of the Christian Man.' r"^^ There is indeed no direct evidence in the New Testament, I nor, as far as we have seen, in the early Fathers, of an explicit Hrepudiation of the principle of civil government in the early Y Church, though such a charge^ may have been brought against I the Church; but it is at least very easy to conjecture that r the enthusiastic spirit of the freedom of the sons of God, of the members of the true kingdom of Christ, might easily pass into a contempt for all government, especially when that government was in the hands of unspiritual persons. In a later volume we shall have to consider the significance of Wyclifife's doctrine of civil lordship: it is possible that his view may have been anticipated in primitive times. There are even not wanting some germs out of which such senti- ments might grow, both in the Gospels and in St Paul's own writings. Our Lord had very sharply contrasted the spirit of the Gentiles with the spirit of His kingdom, when he said : "Ye know that tKey which are accouiTEed to rule over the Gentiles lord it over them ; and their great ones exercise authority over them. But it is not so among you : but whoso-

1 1 Cor. xii. and xiii. " Gal. v. 13.






CHAP, vin.] POLITICAL THEOKY OP NEW TESTAMENT. 97

ever would become great among you, shall be your minister: and whosoever would be first among you, shall be servant of all." 1 It is not difficult to understand how such a conception might lead men of a rash and impulsive disposition into a contempt for all secular authority. In St Paul's first letter to the Corinthians we have a reference to the relation of Christians to the law-courts, which might quite possibly be understood as indicating a certain tendency to slight the ordinary machinery of the secular power. ** Dare any of you, having a matter against his neighbour, go to law before the / unrighteous, and not before the saints? Or know ye not V^ that the saints shall judge the world? and if the world is judged by you, are ye unworthy to judge the smallest matters?" 2 ifo doubt St Paul's words are aimed at the contentious unbrotherly spirit which prevailed in the Church, but there is, probably unintentionally and unconsciously, a slightly depreciatory accent in the reference to the secular \ courts, perhaps a slight confusion with regard to the nature of civil justice.

It seems most probable, then, that St Paul's vindication of the authority of the civil ruler, with the parallel expressions of ? St Peter's epistle, were intended to counteract some anarchical tendencies in the early Christian societies, were intended to k preserve the Christian societies from falling into an error which would have destroyed the unity of human life, and would have tended to put them into a ruinous opposition to the general principles of human progress. We shall have occ asion to see how this question is develo ped i n the writings of the Fathers, and we shall then recognise both how important it was that St Paul had so cleayly laid down the true principles of the religious conception of the state, and also how even the clear- ness of his treatment failed to save later Christian thinkers from a perversion of this conception.

When we now consider the relation of this theory of the nature of government to the contemporary philosophical con- ception of the state, we find that it is both old and new. It is

1 Mark x. 42-44. Cf. Matt. xx. 25, 26 ; Luke xxii. 25, 26.

2 1 Cor. vi. 1-8.

VOL. I. G




Godgle


98 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [part III.

I essentially the same theory as that of the Stoics, that man is by nature a social creature,/that government is an institution necessary to the proper development of human liieTj St Paul is translating the philosophical conception into the Christian conception of the divine order, and the translation has its real importance, but fundamentally the conception is the same. It is new in expression but the same in substance, and even the expression is, as we have already seen, to be found in such contemporary writers as Seneca and Pliny.^ We shall have presently to consider the theories that grew up on this translation, but we shall see throughout our work that the translation was necessary if Christian civil- isation was to inherit the philosophical tradition of Aristotle and the Stoics. We must remember that clearly enough the Epicurean tradition was not the same as the Stoic, that the attitude of the philosophers of that school towards the ■ organised State was at least one of indifi'erence, and, as we i have just seen, there were elements in the Christian concep- tions which might have tended towards a similar position. It is therefore a matter of the greatest importance that St Paul should have recognised the gravity of the question, and should have set forth his views with such distinctness and penetration.

We have still to consider the theory of property in the New Testament. A great deal has been said about what has been / called the communism of the early Church, and it has been thought that we see the beginnings of this in the condition of the Church of Jerusalem as described in the first chapters of the Acts. We must begin by examining the exact nature of the accounts of this which are given to us. The first refer- jjnce is at the end of the second chapter ; " And all that believed were together, and had all things common ; and they sold their possessions and goods, and parted them to all, according as any man had need." ^ The next reference is in the fourth chapter: "And the multitude of them that believed were of one heart and soul : and not one of them said that aught of the things

1 See p. 31. a Acts ii. 44, 45.


/






CHAP. VIII.] POLITICAL THEOKY OP NEW TESTAMENT. 99

which he possessed was his own; but they had all things common. . . . For neither was there among them any that lacked : for as many as were possessors of lands or houses sold them, and brought the prices of the things that were sold, and laid them at the apostles' feet : and distribution was made unto each, according as any one had need." ^

There is no doubt that if these words stood alone we should conclude that a complete communistic system was established in *| the Church of Jerusalem, and we might almost conclude that conformity to this was one of the regular tests of membership. But we must look at the general narrative a little more care- fully, and our first impression will then be a good deal modified. One of the most dramatic incidents in the-etory of the primitive Church is the narrative of the falsehood and death of Ananias and Sapphira, and in this narrative we observe phrases which materially aflfect our judgment of the condition of the Church. ^' A certain man named Ananias, with Sapphira his wife, sold a possession, and kept back part of the price, his wife also being privy to it, and brought a certain part, and laid it at the apostles' feet. But Peter said, Ananias, why hath Satan filled ^ thy heart to lie to the Holy Ghost, and to keep back part of the price of the land ? Whiles it remained, did it not remain thine own ? and after it was sold, was it not in thy power ? How is it that thou hast conceived this thing in thy heart ? thou hast not lied unto men, but unto Godl" ^

It is at least clear from this narrative that there was no com- pulsory system of communism in the Church, that submission j to it was not a condition of membership of the Christian society ' in Jerusalem, and we are compelled to reconsider the judgment which we might be inclined to found upon the passages first quoted. It would seem safest to conclude that the first wave of enthusiasm in the Christian society in Jerusalem led to a sudden development of the charitable impulses of the com- munity to such a point that at least for the time the Christian society might well have appeared to be living iuj* a complete community of goods, but that this condition of things was never developed into a complete system, and that

lActaiv. 32-35. 'Acts v. 1-4.






100 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.




) fer^ t the surrender of individual property was never a condition

^ ^^' ' ' of church membership.

~^^ \ \ The narrative of the Acts throws no light upon the continu-

' ance of this state of things in Jerusalem. There are many

traces in the letters of St Paul of great poverty in the Church of Jerusalem, a poverty probably due mainly to the crowds of Jews, many of them doubtless of very small resources, who from time to time made their way to Jerusalem, from all parts of the Empire, to attend the great festivals; and we find St Paul engaged in collecting money in the churches which he visited, for the relief of this poverty, but there is nothing to show us whether the Church in Jerusalem itself continued to be under the same conditions as at first or not.

It may perhaps be said that there are traces in the Gospels, and especially in the Epistle of St James, of a tendency to look upon the rich as being, by the very fact of their riches, evil, and the poor as being, by reason of their poverty, good. It is certainly noteworthy at least that St James represents the true disciple as being poor, and oppressed by the rich, and that he proclaims the coming judgment of God upon t^ rich.^ And in the Gospels there is more than one trace of a tendency to regard the condition of the rich as being, normally at least, full of danger,^ and the condition of the poor as being one of blessed- ness.3 (In St Matthew's gospel this poverty is explained in a spiritual sense.) In one well-known passage our Lord tells /the rich young ruler that for him the way of perfection lies in the renunciation of all his wealth.* It is of course true that the interpretation of the passage has been the subject of much dispute : we shall see presently in what very various fashions the Fathers deal with it, but the general impression which we derive from the Gospels is certainly that wealth is at least a difficulty in the spiritual life.

When we consider the condition of the Christian Church outside of Judsea, we find no trace of any such system of the common life as may have existed in some loose fashion in

^ James ii. 5, 6 ; v. 1-6. * Mark x. 21 ; Matt. xix. 21 ; Luke

2 Mark x. 25 ; Luke xviii. 24. xviii. 22.

8 Luke vi. 20.


J


a

/

V 1]






CHAP. VIII.] POLITICAL THEORY OP NEW TESTAMENT. 101

Judaea. St Paul, in his various letters, constantly exhorts his disciples to liberality, especially towards the poor Christians in Jerusalem,^ but also in more general terms ; ^ but there is little trace of a community of goods in the churches to which he writes, unless we may conjecture that the idle and disorderly life of some of the Christians at Thessalonica may be related to a somewhat indiscriminate system of almsgiving in that com- munity. St Paul's emphatic words, "If any will not work, neither let him eat," * may imply that the benevolence of the brethren was encouraging a certain number of Christians in idle and thriftless ways. We have discussed the traces of certain anarchical tendencies in the primitive Christian societies, and it is quite possible that this spirit was fostered by a charity which may sometimes have been almost reckless. But in all this there is no trace of any strict community of goods, any notion that the ownership of property was something illegitimate.

So far as the New Testament is concerned, we can hardly say that there is any theory of property of a strict kind : the Gospels and St James may tend to represent the sense of the dangerous responsibilities and temptations which wealth brings ; the Acts and the Epistles show us that the Christian societies, from the outset, felt the imperious claims of the brotherhood, and inter- preted them as meaning that it was the duty of a Christian man to see that his brother was not in want.* We shall return to the subject again when we deal with the theory of property as it is presented in the early Fathers.

1 1 Cor. xvi. 1 ; 2 Cor. vUi. Cf. ' 2 Thess. iii. 10. Cf. 1 Theas. iv. Rom. XV. 26 ; Gal. ii. 10. 9-12.

2 1 Tim. vi. 17-19. * 1 John iii. 17.






102


CHAPTER IX.

NATURAL LAW.

When we consider the character of the political theory of the Christian Fathers we find ourselves in face of a considerable difl&culty in arranging our materials. The writings which we have to consider extend over a period of some six centuries, from St Clement of Eome and the 'Teaching of the Twelve Apoatle« ' in the first century to St Isidore of Seville in the beginning of the seventh, and they represent very various standpoint s. *^ome of them are written by men who have nothing of a philosophical h abit of thought; while others represent the more or less reasoned reflections of men who might be good or bad philosophers, but who were at any rate thinkers. Some of them, that is, simply seem to show us what notions were curren t among Christian men, others must be taken also to represent the particular turn given to these by the individual writer s. We are compelled to recognise considerable diversities of opinion among these writers, and we ^ have endeavoured to note these when they occur, and to discuss the relations of the different views to each other : at the same time, we think-that it is true to say that in the main the Fathers represent a jiomogeneous system of thoug ht, and we have, therefore usually arranged our materials under the same general system which we have so far followed, not under the names of the individual writers, while we have usually endeavoured to present their opinions in some roughly chronological order.

We have seen the importance of the development of the ' theory of natural law in the Roman jurists, we have seen how






CHAP. IX.] NATURAL LAW. 103

at the close of the second century the law of nations is dis- tinguished from the law of nature, and how this distinction is fixed with more or less complete definiteness in the sixth cen- tury. We must now consider the treatment of this subject in the Christian writers of these centuries. We have observed the general characteristics of the theory of Cicero w ith respect to the natural law, that there is a law behind all the positiv e ordinances of human society, a law which is written in the hearts of all men, drawing them to good, forbidding them to do evil, a law which is itself the expression of the reason and nature of God Himself, and that from this all the true laws of men are derived. We have also seen that at least in ohe great passage ^ St Paul indicates that he also conceives of such a principle as existing in the heart of every man — that every man does in his heart know the law of God, which forbids man to sin, and commands him to do what is right. Whether St Paul's conception should be traced to the natural development of Jewish thought, or to the influence of that Hellenic culture which had already strongly afifected Judaism, or to the special circumstances of his own education at Tarsus, is, as we have said, difl&cult to determine. For our purpose, indeed, ^e may suppose that it was derived from any or all of these sources. It will be obvious to any one who studies the phenomena, that here is one of the many points where the Christian conception and that of the Western world at large coincided. The theory of natural law became one of the commonplaces of Christian thought.

In Origen's treatise against Celsus there is an interesting sentence which may be taken as characteristic of the attitude of the Christian thinkers. Celsus had urged that " Law is kinp o f all things," and Origen, after expressing a necessary qualification of the phrase as liable to misunderstanding, agrees that that which is law in the proper sense of the word is by nature king of all things, even though there may be some who have like robbers abandoned the law and deny its validity. The Christians, he says, have come to the knowledge of this law which is by nature king of all things, for it is the same as the law of God, and they endeavour to live in accordance with


CjOOQ IC 


104 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [part III.

it.^ This frank admission of the truth of the conception and the identification of the law of nature with the law of God — an identification already made, at least in terms, by Cicero — is representative of the pommon attitude of Christian writer s towards this conception.

Even yertullian. wh o, if any man, represents the extreme opposition to the ideas of the Greek world, uses language which is the same as that of the philosophers. Nature, he says, is our first school: we know God first by nature . Nature As the teacher, the soul the disciple) Whatever nature taught, it was taught by God.^ Lactantigs, with his usual somewhat captious way of dealing with ancient philos- ophy, when discussing Zeno's principle of living according to nature, complains at first that this is too vague: there are many varieties of nature, he says, and the phrase might mean that men are to live like beasts ; but finally he admits that, if the principle means that man, who is born to virtue , is to follow his own nature, it is a good principle. ^ These Fathers, that is, admit that there is a law written by nature in men's hearts which is the true rule of human life and conduct.

The view of the later Fathers isthe same. The writer known as " Ambrosiaster," in his commentary on St Paurs Epistle to

ihe Eomans, gives us an interesting tripartite definition of law, ,nd a statement of the relation of the law of nature to the law •f Moses.* The definition is interesting, but more significant is the conception of the relation of the Mosaic Law to the natural law, as being something intended to supplement as well as to confirm it. The same conception is expressed in a

^ Orfgen, Contra Celsum, v. 40. etc. Haec est ergo lex naturalis, qua8 ^ Tertullian, De Corona, v. and vi. per Moysen partim reformata, partim De Test. An., 6. (From Dr Fairbaim's auctoritate ejus firmata in vitiis

  • Christ in Modern Theology,' p. 96.) cohibendis, cognitum fecit peccatum."

' Lactantius, Div. Inst., iii. 8. We should refer our readers who wish

  • Ambrosiaster, Com. in Ep. ad to know more about this writer and

Rom., iii. 20 : Triplex quidem lex est, his identity with the author of the ita ut prima pars de sacramento div- ** Quaestiones Veteris et Novi Testa- initatis sit Dei : secunda autem qu88 menti," formerly attributed to St congruit legi naturali, quse interdicit Augustine, to an article by Dom. Morin peccatum : tertia vero factorum, id in the ' Bevue d'Histoire et de Lit- est, sabbati, neomenise, circumcisionis, t^rature religieuse,' 1899.






CHAP. IX.]


NATURAL LAW.


105


h letter of Sjb Ambrose : Tfae Mosaic law was given because men !J had failed to obey the natural law.^ Again, St Ambrose says, Law is f;wofold, patural a nd written. Thg natural law is in man's heart; t he written laws in tab les. All men are under the law — that is, under the natural law.^ And again : The law of God is in the heart of the just man. Which law ? Not the written but the natural law, for law is not set for the just, but for the unjust man.^ The natural law, says St Jerome, speaks in our heart, telling us to do what is good and to avoid what is evil ; and, again, he says that the whole world received the natural law, and the Mosaic law was given because the natural law was neglected or destroyed.*

It is interestfng to notice that the Fathers frequently, as we have before said, connect their treatment of the natural law with St Paul's phrases in Eomans. St Ambrose, for instance, says that it is the Apostle who teaches us that the natu ral'^ law is in our hearts^ St Augustine also refers to St Paul's words in a passage in which he divides law into three species ; ® and St Hilary of Poitiers does the same in describing the general scope of the natural law. He defines this as being that a man must not injure his fellow-man, must not take that whicl^ belongs to another, must keep himself from fraud and per-

scribitur, sed innascitur : nee aliqua percipitur lectione, sed profluo quod- am fonte in singulis exprimitur, et humanis ingeniis hausitur." Cf. 'De Jacob et Vita Beata,' vi.

^ St Augustine, ContraFaustumMani- chseum, xix. 2: "Sunt autem legum genera tria : unum quidem Hebraot^ orum, quod peccati et mortis Paulus appellat (Rom. viii. 2). Aliud vero Gentium, quod naturale vocat : * Gtentes enim,' inquit, *naturaliter quae legis sunt faciimt ; et ejusmodi legem non habentes, ipsi sibi sunt lex ; qui ostend- unt opus legis scriptum in cordibus suis' (Rom. ii. 14, 15). Tertium vero genus legis est Veritas, quod perinde significans, apostolus dicit : Lex enim spiritus vitse in Christo Jesu liberavit me a lege peccati et mortis" (Rom. viii. 2).


^ St Ambrose, Ep. Ixxiii. 10 : " Accipe aliud. Non fuit necessaria lex per Moysen. Denique subintravit, quod utique non ordinarium sed velut f urtiv- um significare videtur introitum; eo quod in locum naturalis legis intra- verit. Itaque si iUa suum servasset locum, hsec lex scripta nequaquam esset ingressa."

2 Id., De Fuga Sseculi, iii.

^ Id., Enarr. in Ps. xxxvi. 31.

  • St Jerome, Com. on Gal. iii. 2, and

on Isaiah xxiv. 6.

' St Ambrose, Ep. Ixxiii. 2 : " Esse autem legem naturalem in cordibus nostris etiam apostolus docet, qui scrip- sit quia plerumque * et gentes natural- iter ea, quae Legis sunt, faciunt, et cum Legem non legerint, opus tamen Legis scriptum habent in cordibus suis ' (Rom. ii. 14, 15). Ea igitur lex non






106 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [part in.

jury, must not plot against another man's marriage.^ It is interesting to compare this with the definitions of the natural law by St Ambrose ^ and by St Augustine.^ It is clear that these are derived from Cicero and other ancient writers.

It is unnecessary to multiply quotations. There seems to be no division of opinion among the Fathers upon the subject. Practically they carry on the same conceptions as those of Cicero and the later philosophers, and while they bring these into connection with the suggestion of St Paul, they cannot be said either to modify these inherited conceptions or to carry them any farther.

The treatment of the law of nature in the Fathers is not complete till we come t^ ^. TsidnrA of RAviUfl at the beginning of the seventh century. Then we find that distinction which we have considered in Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Florentinus, and in the Institutes of Justinian, restated with great direct- ness, and defined in a method which is interesting and to some extent novel. The importance of the treatment of the natural law by St Isidore is, however, not only due to the fact that he furnishes us with interesting evidence as to the general prevalence of the theory of law in this form, and shows us that it was adopted by an important Christian writer. His importance in the history of the theory of natural law is much greater than this. His definitions were finally embodied, in the twelfth century, in G r atianfs Decretum^ and so passed into the structure of the Canon Law, and furnished the form of


1 St HUary of Poitiers, Tract, on Ps. cxviii. 119 : " Lex enim veluti naturalis est, injuriam nemini inferre, nil alienum prseripere, fraude ac perjurio abstinere, alieno conjugio non insidi£kri. Novit et banc Apostolus legem, dicens. * Cum < enim nationes, quae legem non babent, naturaliter secundum legem faciunt,' etc."

2 St Ambrose, De OflF., iii. 3 : " Hsec utique lex natures est, quae nos ad omnem astringit bumanitatem, ut alter alteri tanquam unius partes cor- poris invicem deferamus. Nee detra- bendum quidquam putemus, cum


contra naturae legem sit non juvare." St Ambrose, De OflF., iii. 24 : "Nibil- que judicandum utile, nisi quod in commune prosit. . . . Etenim si una lex naturse omnibus, una utique utilitas universorum, ad consulendum utique omnibus naturae lege constring- imur."

^ St Augustine, De Diversis Questioni- bus xxxi. : " Natura jus est quod, non opinio genuit, sed qusedam innata via inseruit, ut religionem, pietatem, gra- tiam, vindicationem, observantiam^ veritatem."






CHAP. IX.] NATURAL LAW. 107

all the mediaeval ecclesiastical treatment of the subject ; and though, no doubt, with the reviving study of the Roman juris- prudence, the same conceptions would probably have appeared, yet the fact that they were already embodied in St Isidore's Etymologies secured the unanimity of mediaeval theory upon the subject.

The position of St Isidore in the development, especially of the political theory of the Middle Ages, is indeed out of all proportion to the intrinsic merits or pretensions of his work. His 'Origins,' or 'Etymologies,' is really the seventh-century equivalent of a modern encyclopaedia. He suggests the deriva- tion of each word with which he deals, and gives a brief account of the thing which it describes. It would be extremely interest- ing, were it not here out of place, to trace the history and origin of such an encyclopaedic work as that of St Isidore. It is evident enough that in most points and in general conception it is not original. It seems to belong to the same class of work as Martianus Capella's *De Nuptiis Philologiae.* How much farther back this encyclopaedic form of literature can be traced we are not competent to say. It will be seen in the course of our inquiries that St Isidore furnishes the model of a variety of works of the same kind in the Middle Ages, of which the nearest is Hrabanus Maurus's ' De Universe,' which belongs! to the ninth century.

St Isidore's work has therefore little of the character of an original production, and indeed makes no claim to this. For our purpose, indeed, this fact rather increases than diminishes its importance. We feel convinced in reading St Isidore's definitions that he is giving us not merely his own judgments but the generally current conceptions of his time. It may of course be urged that St Isidore, writing as he did in Spain, was rather far removed from the centre of the culture of his time, and that we must be prepared to admit the influence of the new barbarian circumstances upon his mode of thought. With regard to some aspects of his political ideas this may be quite true, and indeed may be a fact of some importance. But with regard to the subject which we are at present con- sidering, his treatment of the theory of Natural Law, there







108 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [part III.


seems no reason to think that any such special influences are at work upon him. We should indeed be glad, if it were possible, to trace more clearly the sources of his theories, for much remains, to us at least, very obscure; but we see no reason at all why we should look for these outside of the limits of the Latin culture.

St Isidore of Seville deals with the definition of law in the fdllowing terms :^ "Jus aut naturale est aut civile a ut gen - tium." That is, he begins by laying down the tripartite char- acter of law as Ulpian and the Institutes do. He then defines natural law, " Jus naturale est commune omnium nationum, et quod ubique instinctu naturse, non constitutione aliqua ha beatur ; ut, viri et feminse conjunctio, liberorum successio et educatio, communis omnium possesfsio, et omnium una libertas, acquisitio eorum quae coelo, terra, marique capiuntur. Item depositae rei vel commendatae ^gecuniae restitutio, violentiae per vim repulsio. Nam hoc aut si quid huic simile est, nunquam injustum, sed naturale, aequumque habetur."

It will be evident that the definition is related to that of Ulpian and the Institutes,^ and yet that there are considerable differences between them, and these of some significance. The statement that the jtis riaturale is common to all animals has disappeared, and in its place we read that it is common to all nations, and that men follow it " instinctu naturae non constitu- tione aliqua." We have already had occasion to deal with this change, but we must again point out that it seems to represent the fact that while Ulpian's definition suggests that the jus naturale was something of the nature of the animal instinct, the general tendency of thought was to look upon it as a body of

prmmplpq rafinnnlly flpprftViAnHft/^ It is trUC that St Isidore

says that men follow it "instinctu naturae," but this is con-




1 St Isidore, Etymol., v. 4.

^ Ulpian's definition is : " Jus natu- rale est, quod natura omnia animalia docuit: nam jus istud non humani generis proprium, sed omnium animal- ium, quae in terra, quae in mari nas- cuntur, avium quoque, commune est. Hinc descendit maris atque feminse


conjunctio, quam nos matrimonium appeUamus, hinc liberorum procreatio, hinc educatio : videmus etenim cetera quoque animalia, feras etiam istius juris peritia censeri." (Dig., i. 1. 1. 3.) The definition in Inst., i. 2., is practi- cally the same.






CHAP. IX.] NATURAL LAW. (V^^^"^ 109

trasted, not with reason, but with " constitutio aliguap" a nd it

should be observed that under the definition is included an

ethical habit, such as the " depositae rei vel commendatae pe-

cuniae restitutio. " This has no place in Ulpian's definition. ,^

St Isidore defines the jus gentium in the following terms: \a

  • ' Jus gentium est sedium occupatio, sedificatio, munitio, bella, /V


captivitates, servitutes, postliminia, foedera, paces, inducise, A legatorum non violandorum religio, connubia inter alienigenas prohibita : et inde jus gentium, quod eo jure omnes fere gentes utuntur." ^ We have already compared this definition with a fragment of Hermogenianus contained in the Digest, and with one part of the discussion of this question in the Institutes of Justinian.2 It is difficult to say whether St I8id9re's definition is directly related to these, but there seems to be a general agreement of character between them all. In passing we may point out that there is the same contrast between the natural liberty of all, under the jus naturale, and the slavery which belongs to the jus gentium, in St Isidore and in the Institutes ; but we shall have to return to this point later. Thp. f^^ pimlp. is defined by St Isidore as follows : " Jus civile est, quod quisque populus, vel civitas sibi proprium, humana divinaque causa con- stituit." ^ This is practically the same as the definition of the civil law as distinguished from the jus gentium and the jus naturale in the Institutes of Gains and Justinian.*

St Isidore of Seville has obviously reproduced with certain changes of detail the theory of the tripartite character of law which we have already seen in the works of Ulpian and in the

^ St Isid., Etym., v. 6. captivitates secutae et servitutes, quae

^ Hermog., in Dig., i. 1. 5: "Ex sunt juri naturali contrarise. Jure

hoc jure gentium introducta bella, dis- enim naturali ab initio omnes homines

cretfle gentes, regna condita, dominia liberi nascebantur. Ex hoc jure gen-

distincta, agris termini positi, sedificia tium et omnes psene contractus intro-

coUocata, commercium, emptiones ven- ducti sunt, ut «mptio venditio, locatio

ditiones, locationes conductiones, obli- conductio, societas, depositum, mut-

gationes institutse : exceptis quibusdam uum et alii innumerabiles." quffi jure civiliintroductse sunt." Inst., * St Isid., Etym., v. 5.

i. 2. 2 : " Jus autem gentium omni * Gkiius, i. 1 : " Nam quod quisque

humano generi commxme est. Nam populus ipse sibi jus constituit, id

usu exigente et humanis necessitatibus ipsius proprium est, vocaturque * jus

gentes humanae quaedam sibi constit- civile," quasi jus proprium civitatis."

uerunt : bella etenim orta sunt, et Of. Inst., i. 2. 1.


V







/


110 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [part hi.

Institutes of Justinian. With Tiis work the conception passes into the common stock of mediseval tradition on political theory. The distinction would, however, have had little or no meaning if it had not been closely connected with that theory ^f the natural condition, or state of nature, the state ante- cedent to the conventional institutions of society, which we have already studied in Seneca, and whose influence we have recognised in the lawyers. We must examine this theory as it is exhibited to us in the Fathers, but we shall find it best to approach the subject by considering their theory of human nature and human institutions. We shall find that there is xjontinually implied in this a reference to a condition of life precedent to and other than that which now exists. We shall see that the conception of' the state of nature is in the Fathers ^ identified with the conception of the condition of mankind in i;he unfallen state.






Ill


CHAPTER X.

NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY.

We have seen that in the New Testament writings we find a conception of human nature which is very clear and distinct as to the essential and inherent equality of mankind ; we find that in the teaching of our Lord Himself men are regarded «ts all equally the children of God, and that in St Paul's writings we have the more technical expression of this conception as signi- fying the capacity of all men for the spiritual and moral life. Whether a man is slave or free he is still capable of the same moral and spiritual life, capable of knowing God and serving Him. If he is a slave he must be treated fairly and reasonably by his master, who is no dearer to God than is the slave.

This conception is carried on with eloquence and force in the writings of the early Fathers — is indeed implied in all that they say. We may refer to one or two passages which deal with the matter directly: the first is in the little work known as the ^ Octavius,' written by Minucius Felix. He says that all men, without difference of age, sex, or rank, are begotten with a <japacity and power of reason and feeling, and obtain wisdom, not by fortune, but by nature.^ It is interesting to observe how close these phrases, in spite of certain differences, are to those of Cicero and Seneca ; indeed it might be diflScult to say whether the author derives his method of expression from the New Testament or from the philosophers. Another passage is contained in Lactantius's work, the ' Divine Institutes.' He is • discussing the nature of justice, and after having given the first place in the conception of this to pietas he goes on to urge

^ Octavius, xvi.




poogle


112 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART HI.

that the second part of justice is cequitas — that is, the temper which teaches a man to put himself on an equality with his fellow-men, the quality which Lactantius says Cicero had called ceqtcabilitas. God, who brings forth and inspires men, wished them all to be equal. He made them all for virtue, promised them all immortality. No one, in God's sight, is a slave or a master ; He is the Father of all men, we are all therefore His children. Lactantius finds fault with Eoman and Greek institu- tions as not recognising these principles of equality sufl&ciently, but it does not appear that he is really attacking the institutions so much as what he considers the wrong temper with which men regard these institutions ; for when he considers the objection which some one might make, that the same differences of rank and condition exist also among Christian people, he replies not by denying that the differences exist, nor by condemning their existence, but by urging that Christian people do re^U v recognise each bther as brothers and equals, that they estimate all things by their spiritual and not by their material value.^

Lactantius*s phrases are well-meaning and no doubt sincere, but they scarcely justify his attempt to censure the Greek and Eoman spirit, and his somewhat inexcusable forgetf ulness of the fact that writers like Cicero and Seneca had taken up much the same position towards the inequalities of human condition as his own. Lactantius does not really condemn the existence of the great Inequalities of society, only he wishes them to be corrected by the sense of the fundamental equality of human nature, just as Seneca had done.

In the later Fathers this conception of the intrinsic and primitive equality of human nature is discussed with much ful- ness, but almost always in direct connection with the treatment of the institution of slavery : they assert that this equality is primitive, and also that in some sense it always continues, while they also develop with great clearness a theory which is to account for the existence of this unprimitive and, in one sense, unnatural institution of slavery.

We do not know that any passage in the writings of the Fathers represents "the general character of their theory better

^ Lact., Div. Inst., v. 15 and 16.






CHAP. X.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY.


113


than a discussion of the subject by " Ambrosiaster," in his comAientary on St Paul's Epistle to the Colossians. He begins by warning masters lest they be puffed up with pride and for- get that God made, not slaves and free men, but all men free. Slavery is the consequence of man's sin; man, making war upon his fellow-man, makes captives, and chance determines whether these are to remain slaves or to be redeemed. Before God the sinner is the slave ; Ham is an example of this, and the ancient writers who maintain that the wise were free and the foolish slaves, really recognised this principle. Masters must remember that their lordship extends only over the body ; they have no authority over the soul, Grod only is the master of that : let them remember this, and only exact just service from their slaves, who are still their equals, not to say their brethren.^

It will be noticed that there are really four distinct proposi- tions with regard to human nature and slavery contained in this passage. Fitst, that men as God made them were free; second, that this still continues in some sense, the condi- tion of slavery is very largely one determined by fortune, and this condition does not extend beyond the body ; thirdly, that slavery is the result of man's sin and sinfulness, the true slavery is that of the soul, for the foolish are the true slaves ;

Cui sententise veteres assensere, ita ut


^ Ambrosiaster, Com. on Coloss. iv. 1 : " ' Domini quod justum est et sequum servis prsebete, scientes quod et voe dominum habetis in coelis.' Ne domini temporales superbia extollantur, prse- sumentes de dominatu, mitigat et cohibet animos illorum, ut adhibita consideratione humani generis anim- advertant auctorem Deum non servos etliberos sed omnes ingenuos condidisse. Sed hoc mundi iniquitate factum est, ut dum alterius fines invadit tunc captives ducit ingenuos ; unde et manu capti dicti simt a veteribus inde mancipia. Hie casus et conditio etiam nunc apparet ; alii redimuntur, alii remanent servi ; apud Deum autem hie servus habetur qui peccaverit Denique peccati causa, Cham servus audivit: 'Maledictus puer Chanaam, servus servorum erit fratribus suis.' VOL. I.


definirent omnes prudentes esse liberos, stultos autem omnes ess& servos. . . . Ostendit ergo dominis, quia non vere sunt domini sed quasi per imaginem ; corporum enim non animorum sunt domini. Solus enim dominus, et auctor rerum invisibilis Deus, tam corporibus quam animis dominatur : ut haec con- siderantes justa ab eis ezigant servitia : tfidia utique qualia et a be exigi volunt a Domino communt Nam cum ipsi non ut dignum est, Deo serviant, quem non negant omnium potestatem habere, cujusque quotidiana dona per minis- teria creaturee humanis usibus exhiberi, a paribus suis (ut non dicam fratribus) tam gravia exigunt servitia, ut ferri non possint : non ponentes in animo, quia et ipsi velint nolint, servi sunt ; et viderint cujus meriti."

H






114 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [pART III.

fourthly, that masters must treat their slaves with considera- tion and forbearance. All these points can be amply illustrated from the works of the Fathers. ^

All the Fathers maintain that in their original nature men were free and equal. Salvian speaks of that human nature and condition which makes masters and slaves equal.^ St Augustine, in a very notable passage, to which we shall have to return, lays it down that Grod did not make rational man to lord it over his rational fellows, but only to be master of the irrational creatures, and that no one in that nature in which God first made man is the slave either of man or of sin. In the original order of things men would have been free and equal.^ Gregory the Great insists upon the same conception. Masters are admonished that they should remember that their slaves are of the same nature as themselves, lest they should cease to recognise that those whom they hold in bondage are equal with them, through their share in one common nature.* In a passage in his work on Job, a passage which is fre- quently referred to in mediaeval literature, and some of whose phrases have become almost classical, Gregory admonishes great men to remember that by nature we are all equal, that nature brought forth all men equal, that it is only by a secret dispensation of God that some men are set over or are inferior to others.* St Gregory's phrase, " Omnes namque natura sequales sumus," is strictly parallel to Ulpian's " Quod ad jus naturale attinet, omnes homines sequales sunt." We have just seen how St Isidore of Seville says that under the natural law there is " omnium una libertas." ^

1 Salvian, De Gubematione Dei, iii. semelipBam mens desoendit de vertice 28. ^ culminis, citius planitiem invenit natu-

2 St Aug., De Civ. Dei, xix. 16. - ralis sequalitatia. Nam ut prsefati ^ Gregory the Great, Liber Pastor- sumus, omnes homines natura sequales

alis Curse, Part iii. 5. genuit, sed variante meritorum ordine,

^ Gregory the Great, Expositio alios aliis dispensatio occulta postponit.

Moralis in Beatum Job, xxi. 15: ... Sancti autem viri cum prsesunt,

Potentibus viris magna est virtus non in se potestatem ordinis, sed sequal-

humilitatis, considerata sequalitas con- itatem conditionis attendunt, nee

ditionis. Omnes namque homines prseesse gaudent hominibus, sed pro-


natura sequales sumus, sed accessit

dispensatorio ordine, ut quibusdam ^ St Isidore of Seville, Etym., v. 4»

prselati videamur. ... Si enim apud See p. 108.






CHAP. X.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 115

But, further, this equality is not a thing wholly of the past : the inequalities of condition and life only affect the bo^y, they have no relation to the. mind and soul. The slave, St Ambrose says, may be the superior, in character, of his master ; no condition of life is incapable of virtue, the flesh can be enslaved, the mind is free. The slave may really be more free than the master. It is sin which renders a man truly a slave, innocence is free. He is free under any outward form of slavery who is not governed by the love of the world, by avarice, by fear. The free man is he who can look out with confidence on his actual life and for whom the future has no terrors.^ St Ambrose's words remind us very forcibly of those of Seneca, and indeed so far the theories we are con- sidering do not seem essentially to differ from those i;Wth which we have already de^t. But they are reinforced by the em- phatic assertion that in Christ we are all one. St Ambrose in another treatise puts this very forcibly. Neither family nor rank affect the true position of men. Slaves or freemen, we are all one in Christ ; slavery can take nothing from man's char- acter, nor can freedom add anything to it.^ This is expressed in another and perhaps more technical fashion by the author of one of the sermons attributed to St Augustine, who protests t^ainst the harsh treatment of Christian slaves by Christian

^ St Ambrose, DeJoseph Patriarcha, semper liber, qui mundi amore non

iv. : " Cseterum quod ad moralem capitur, avaritise vinculis non tenetur,

pertinet locum, quia omnes vult salvos metu criminis non alligatur, qui

fieri Dominus Deus noster, dedit per securus spectat prsesentia, quern

Joseph etiam iis qui sunt in servitute futura non terrent." solatium : attribuit magisterium ; ut ^ St Ambrose, Exhortatio Virgini-

discerent etiam in ultima conditione tatis, i. 3 : " Nullum ergo ad com-

posae mores esse superiores, nee uUum mendationem hominis condicio afiert

statum immunem esse virtutis, si impedimentum ; nee dignitas prosapisa

animus se uniuscujusque cognoscat ;. meritum, sed fides affert. Sive servus,

carnem servituti subditam esse, non sive liber, omnes in Christo unum

mentem, multosque servulos esse sumus. . . . Nee servitus derogat nee

dominis liberiores, si in servitute libertas adjuvat. . . . Apud Christum

positi a servilibus putent operibus enim servitus et libertas sequa lance

abstingndum. Servile est omne pec- penduntur, nee uUo discemiculo bonss

catum, libera est innocentia. Unde servitutis et libertatis merita dividun-

et Dominus ait : Omnis qui facit tur : quia nulla major est dignitas quam

peccatum, servus est peccatL . . . servire Christo." Ille vero in quavis conditione servitii






116 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

masters, and upbraids them for not considering that the slave is their brother by grace, has equally with them put on Christ, partakes of the same sacraments, has the same Father, God, and should find in his master a brother.^ These Christian con- llpeptions do not perhaps add anything in strict theory to the ^philosophic conception of the equality of man's nature, but they represent to us a mode of apprehending this which has probably had a very great and continuous influence on the development of the practical consequences of this theory of human nature.

Man, then, as God made him was free and equal. The subjec- tion of man to man is something which belongs not to his original nature but to his present condition; and more than that, this equality and freedom is in one sense indestructible and inalienable: even now, though his body may be in sub- jection, his mind and soul are free, he is still capable of reason and virtue, he may even now be superior to the man to whom he is enslaved, and in his relation to God all differences of condition are meaningless. Men, whether slaves or freemen, are called to one common life in Christ and God, called to know God as the common Father and to hold each other as brethren. We may stay for a moment to notice once again how far we have travelled from the Aristotelian mode of thought, how clearly we are in presence of what we may call the modern conception, the fundamental idea upon which the modern democratic theory of society depends. The Christian Fathers are clearly restating in their own fashion the same conceptions «is those which we already met with in Cicero, in Seneca, and in the lawyers.

But slavery is not, in the judgment of the Christian Fathers, unlawful or improper: they recognise its existence, they ac- quiesce in its presence, and they furnish a complete theory of its iorigin and a new justification of its continuance. Slavery, they say, had no place in the primitive condition of life ; man, as God

^ Pseudo Augustine, Sermones, cxlvi. f rater est. Etenim similiter Christum

3 : " Et quod magis dolendem est, christ- induit, iisdem participat sacramentis,

ianus dominus christiano in his diebus eodem quo et tu, utitur Deo Patre ;

servo nonparcit,minimerespiciens quod cur te non utatur ut fratre?" etsi servus est conditione, gratia tamen






CHAP. X.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 117

created him, was not made to be either the slave or the lord of his fellow-man ; but, they add, man has long ago passed out of that primitive condition, and lives now under other circum- stances. He was once innocent and harmless, now he is vicious and inclined to attack and injure his fellow-man. Under the primitive conditions, he needed no coercive discipline to train him to goodness and to restrain his evil desires; he lived in freedom, and under conditions of equality, for he had no tend- ency to abuse his freedom to the injury of his neighbours, and therefore he did not need to be under the domination of his fellow-man, lest he should do wrong.

The Fathers conceive of the state of man before the Fall much as Seneca conceives of the Golden Age,^ and they account for the disappearance of the primitive conditions of that age by the theory of the Fall. By the Fall man passed out of the state of nature into the state in which the conventional institutions of society are necessary. Slavery did not exist in the state of nature when men were free, and in some very large sense equal. But the Fall brought with it the need of new conditions, of a new discipline, by which the new and evil tendencies of human nature should be corrected. Slavery is a consequence of the coming of sin into the world, and is also a disciplinary system by which the sinful tendencies of man may be corrected.

We have already seen how this conception is stated by " Ambrosiaster." In general terms he puts the universal theory of the Fathers, that slavery came into the world with sin. This conception is drawn out with greater completeness by St Augustine, St Ambrose, and St Isidore of Seville. The passage to which we have already referred in the * De Civitate Dei,' as illustrating the conception of the equality and primitive liberty of mankind, also contains one of the best statements of the patristic theory of the origin and rationale of slavery.*

^ See p. 23. quam hominum constituti sunt, ut

^ De Civ. Dei, zix. 15 : *' Rationalem etiam sic insinuaret Deus quid postulet

factum ad imaginem suam noluit (Deus) ordo creaturarum, quid exigat meritum

nisi irrationabilibusdomiiiari;non horn- peccatorum. Condicio quippe servit-

inem homini, sed hominem pecori. Inde utis jure inteU^tur imposita peccatori.

primi justi pastores pecorum magis Proinde nusquam scripturarum legimus






118 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHEKS. [part m.


Man, who was made in the image of God, and endowed with reason, was made to be the lord of all irrational creatures, but not of his fellow-men. Slavery has been imposed by the just sentence of God upon the sinner: it is a consequence not of man's nature but of man's sinfulness; by nature man is the slave neither of sin nor of his fellow-man. Slavery is intended to preserve the true order of life, which is threatened with destruction by sin. St Augustine looks upon slavery partly as a punishment of sin, but also as a remedy for sin, as one of those institutions, unnatural in one sense, as being contrary to the primitive conditions of human nature, but necessary under the actual circumstances of society. St Ambrose urges more than once that sin and vice and ignorance do in themselves make a man a slave. Sin is always servile, innocence alone is free. " Every one who commits sin is a slave of sin." ^ It is really better for a vicious man to be a slave ; a man who cannot rule himself is better under the authority of a wise man. When Isaac put Esau into subjection to Jacob, he was really conferring upon him a benefit.^ The same conception is drawn out with precision and clearness by St Isidore of Seville. Slavery is a punishment for sin, but a remedial punishment ; it is intended


servum, antequam hoc vocabulo Noe Justus peccatum filii vindicaret. Nomen itaque istud culpa meruit, non natura. . . . Prima ergo servitutis causa pec- catum est, ut homo homini condicionis vinculo Bubderetur ; quod non fit nisi Deo judicante, apud quem non est in- iquitas et novit diversas poeuas meritis distribuere delinquentium. Sicutautem supernus Dominus dicit: 'Omnis qui facit peccatum, servus est peccati.' Ac per hoc multi quidem religiosi dominis iniquis non tamen liberis serviunt : ' A quo enim quis devictus est, huic et servus addictus est' Et utique felicius servitur homini quam libidini, cum Bsevissimo dominatu vastet corda mort- alium, ut alias omittam, libido ipsa dominandi. Hominibus autem illo pacis ordine, quo aUis alii subjecti sunt, sicut prodest humilitas servientibus, ita nocet superbia dominantibus. NuUus autem


natura, in qua prius Deus hominem condidit, servus est hominis aut pec- catL Verum et poenalis servitus ea lege ordinatur, quae naturalem ordiuem conservare jubet, perturbari vetat; quia si contra earn legem non esset factum, nihil esset poanali servitute cohercendum. Ideoque apostolus etiam servos monet subditos esse dominis suis et ex animo eis cum bona voluntate servire ; ut scilicet, si non possunt a dominis liberi fieri, suam servitutem ipsi quodam modo liberam faciant, non timore subdolo, sed fideli dilectione serviendo, donee transeat iniquitas et evacuetur omnis principatus et pot- estas humana et sit Deus omnia in omnibus."

^ St Ambrose, De Joseph Patriarcha, iv. See p. 115, note 1.

' St Ambrose, Ep. xxxvii., and Ep. Ixxvii. 6.






CHAP. X.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 119

to correct the evil tendencies of original sin in human nature. It is necessary that the evil dispositions of some men should be restrained by terror, and yet God is equally careful for men whether they are slaves or free, and it may chance that a good man may be enslaved to an evil master while he is really his superior.^ St Isidore seems to mean that slavery is one of those disciplinary institutions which are necessary under the actual conditions oi human nature, which do, in the general, tend to correct the result of men's depravity, though he is evidently compelled to recognise that the dispensation of Providence is not always adjusted correctly to the individual case.

This theory of the Fathers deserves careful attention. We have seen that they use phrases which illustrate the sincere conviction with which they, like the later philosophers and the lawyers, maintained the natural equality and liberty of man- kind. Clearly they all continue to hold firmly to the view that human nature is fundamentally equal, that there is no reality in such a distinction as that which Aristotle had made between the naturally free man and the man who was naturally a slave. Men are all possessed of reason and capable of virtue ; they are all the children of God. But it is also quite clear that the Christian writers were no more prepared to condemn the actual institution of slavery as unlawful than were the jurists or the philosophers. In the writings of the jurists we have

^ St Isidore of SeviUe, Sententiae, ore suo populoB a malo coercerent, atque iii. 47 : *' Propter peccatum primi ad recte vivendum legibus subderent. hominis humano generi poena divinitus Quantum attinet ad rationem " non est illata est servitutis ita ut quibus aspi- personarum acceptio apud Deum," qui cit non congruere libertatem, his mis- mundi elegit ignobilia et contempti- ericordius irroget servitutem. Et licet bilia, et quae non sunt ut ea quaa sunt peccatum humanae originis per baptismi destrueret : ne glorietur omnis caro, gratiam cunctis fidelibus dimissum sit, hoc est camalis potentia coram illo. tamen sequus Deus ideo discrevit ho- Unus enim Dominus sequaliter et do- minibus vitam, alios servos constituens, minis fert consultum et servis. Melior alios dominos, ut licentia male agendi est subjecta servitus quam elata liber- servorum, potestate dominantium re- tas. Multi enim inveniuntur Deo etringatur. Nam si omnes sine metu libere servientes sub dominis constituti fuissent, quis esset qui a malis quern- flagitiosis, qui et si subjecti sunt illis quam prohibeat. Inde et in gentibus corpore, prselati tamen sunt mente." principes regesque electi sunt, ut terr-






120 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.

the apparent contradiction stated, without explanation, that slavery is contrary to nature and yet that it exists. Seneca, at least, among the philosophers, suggests an explanation of the apparent contradiction. Institutions which were not necessary in the age of innocence became necessary as men's vices in- creased. The Fathers, bringing to their consideration of society a dogmatic theory of the Fall, are able to apply the same considerations as those which Seneca urges, with completeness and coherence. Had Adam not sinned and brought sin into human nature such an institution as slavery would have been unnecessary ; but the Fall, in^^inemg corruption into the world, made necessary institutions which should correct and control the sinfulness of human nature.

Here we have the explana^on of what at first sight seems a paradoxical contradiction between the principles of the natural law and the actual conditions of human life. The later Eoman jurists had looked upon the natural law as divine and un- changeable,^ and, almost in the same breath, had spoken of slavery as an institution actually existing and yet contrary to the natural law. Directly at least they suggest no explanation of the apparent contradiction. Seneca had suggested, and the Fathers developed completely, an explanation which was in its own way profound and philosophical. The law of nature in its completeness is only adapted to the state of nature. In the condition of innocence and simplicity men needed no coercion to make them obey the principles of this law. But once this innocence had disappeared man needed discipline and coercion to make him obey even the more general principles of justice and right, and hence much which is contrary to nature in the primitive condition is necessary in the actual condition of human life.

Slavery is then, in the view of the Fathers, a lawful institu- tion, and they constantly urge upon the slave the duty of obedience and submission. St Ambrose, after admonishing masters to remember that they are of the same nature as their slaves, bids the slaves serve their masters with good will; a man must patiently accept the condition in which he is born,

1 Inst., i. 2. 11.






CHAP. X.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. .121

and must obey harsh as well as good masters.^ St Augustine, in one interesting passage which is also of some importance in connection with the theory of government, argues that Christ makes good slaves of bad ones ; that, when they turn to Him, He teaches them, not that it is improper that the righteous should serve the wicked, but mther that slaves should follow His example in rendering service.^ In another place, with still greater emphasis, he repudiates the notion that the precedent of the liberation of the Hebrew slaves in every seventh year might be applied to the case of'the Christian slave : the apostle, he says, had admonished slaves to obey their masters, lest | Christian slaves should demand such a manumission.' The author of one of the sermons attributed to St Augustine puts the matter very forcibly when he bids the slaves love and obey their masters from the heart, because it is God who has made these to be masters and the others to be their servants.** But perhaps the most emphatic assertion of the propriety of slavery is to be found in one of the canons of the Council of Gangrae, held in the year 362. In the third canon the anathema of the Church is laid upon any one who under the pretence of godli- ness should teach a slave to despise his master, or to withdraw himself from his service.^

The Church, then, so far from repudiating the institution of slavery, accepted the fact, and framed its own canonical regulations in accordance with it. The history of the canonical

^ ^ St Ambrose, Ep. Ixiii. 112 : apostolica auctoritas jubet servos

Domini servis imperate non quasi dominis suis esse subditos, ne nomen

conditione subditis, sed ita ut naturae Dei et doctrina blasphemetur." ejusdem cujus vos estis, consortes eis ^ Pseudo Augustine, Sermone, cxvii,

esse memineritis. Servi quoque dominis 12 : " Obedite (servi) dominis vestris,

Bervite cum voluntate ; etenim unus- diligite ex corde, non ad oculum servi-

quisque quod natus est, patienter debet entes, sed ministerium ex amore

suBcipere : nee solum bonis, sed etiam facientes ; quia et illos Deus constituit

asperis obedite dominis. ut vobis dominentur, et vos ut

^ St Aug., Enarr. in Ps. cxxiv. serviatis." 3. ' Concilium Gangrense, Canon iii. :

' St Aug., Qusestionum in Hept. ii. Ef rts BovKov irpo<pd<T€i dcoacfieias

77 : " Quae de servo Hebrsao praeci- 9i9d<rKoi KartuppoveTp Setrirdrov, Ktd ctvax-

piuntur, ut sex annos serviat, et capeTv riis imjpetrlas koI u^ fi§r* §{ftfoias

dimittatur liber gratis, ne servi Chris- Koi irdtnis rifirjs ry iavrov HeinrSry

tiani hoc flagitarent a dominis suis, i^vmjpsreTffOaif dvd$€fia l(rra;>






122 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHEKS. [PART ni.

and secular legislation with regard to the slave who entered a monastery, or procured ordination, is long and intricate, and it is not necessary here to deal with it in detail; still some points in this should be observed. At an early date it had become the Church rule that a slave could not be ordained unless he were first set at liberty. St Leo expressly prohibits this,^ and a little later the matter is treated with considerable detail by Pope Gelasius I. In one of his letters he orders a certain bishop to restore a slave, who had been made a "clericus," to his mistress; but with regard to another slave who had been ordained to the priesthood he orders that he should be sent back to his mistress, not as a slave but as a priest at the church on her estates.^ In another letter he forbids the reception of any slave into a monastery without the permission of his master.^ This does not, however, rep- resent the universal character of Christian legislation on the subject. In Justinian's fifth Novel the question of the entrance of slaves into monasteries is handled in a somewhat different spirit. Justinian prefaces his judgment on the subject by the recognition of the fact that the divine grace makes no distinction with regard to hun^^n conditions; that in the worship of God all distinctions of male or female, slave or free, disappear ; and he goes on to lay it down that every one, whether free or a slave, must undergo a probation of three years before being accepted as a monk. If within that time a master come to reclaim his slave, ^and can prove that the slave had stolen somethhig, or hjR committed a crime of

^ St Leo, Ep. iv. Of. Canones Apost., nostra auctoritate depvtamus : et omni

81, and Concil. Tolet., iv. 19, 73, 74. veritate discussa, si revera objectam sibi

^ St Gelasius I., £p. xxi. : "Nuper maculam ^ justitisB refragationis non

etenim actores illustris feminse Placidiae potuerit ratione diluere, Leontium

petitorii oblatione conquesti sunt, clericum, quern gradus praefinitus legi-

SabinumMarceUianensissiveOasilinatis bus non defendit, ad sequendam cog-

urbis Antiochum servum juris patronse nationis suae necessitatem modis omni- .

8U89, absentis dominae occasione captata, bus redhibete. Antiochum vero, quia *

ad presbyterii honorem usque produc- propter sacerdotium non jam potest

turn, ejusque fratrem Leontium cleri- retolli, si in suam eccleeiam in hoc, in

calia officii privilegio decorasse. Et ideo, quo est, honore desiderat coUocare, non

fratres carissimi, inter supradictos veluti redditum sibi, sed habeat pro

actores et eos, qui conditionis extremes mysteriorum celebratioue susceptum.^'

repetuntur, objectam cognitionem vobis * St Gelasius I., Ep. xiv. 4.






CHAP. X.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 123

some kind, and had therefore fle^ to the monastery, the slave is to be restored to him, on the promise that he will not injure him. But if he cannot prove the charge, the slave is not to be surrendered to him, even if the master's demand is made within the three years: after that, no demand can be made even on the ground of any crime committed by the slave before his coming to the monastery. Only, if the slave leave the monastery to return to the secular life, then the master can reclaim him.^ We shall have to recur to this question of the position of the slave or serf with respect to ordination or en- tering a monastery in later chapters. We here refer to the matter only as illustrating the fact that the Christian Church acquiesced in the institution of slavery, and even formed its own internal regulations in accordance .with the fact

Slavery, then, in the judgment of the Fathers, is a legitimate and useful institution. But the Fathers are very careful to urge upon the masters that they must show their slaves con- sideration and kindness, and even that they are responsible for the spiritual welfare of their slaves. St Augustine urges upon the masters of slaves that while with respect to temporal matters they may well distinguish between their children and their slaves, with regard to the worship of God they should take equal thought for both : the true Pater familias will try to bring up his whole household in the service of God.^ St Gregory the Great, in a letter addressed to the nobles and proprietors of Sardinia, warns them that they will have to give account to God for all those -who are in subjection to them ; it is true that these are to serve the temporal interests of their lords, but the lords are responsible for their eternal wellbeing.*

We must not be understood to be discussing the question of the complete influence of Christianity on ancient slavery: our work here is concerned with the theory of the subject. So far as we should venture an opinion on this .matter, we should say that Christianity was one of the many influences which were gradually tending to bring the slavery of the ancient world to an end. It would appear evident that the

^ Novel V. 2. 2 De q^^^ p^j^ xix. 16. ^ St Gregory the Great, Ep. iv. 23.






124 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

influence of Christianity tended to promote the mitigation of the hardships of slavery, not only by its exhortations to the master to remember that the slave was his brother, but also by promoting legislation for the protection of the slave and by actually encouraging manumission. The laws of the Christian Emperors carry on from the older legislation, and seem to develop further, regulations for the protection of slave women and children from prostitution ^ and exposure,^ and it is very noticeable that one of the earliest laws en- acted by Constantine after his conversion was that by which it was permitted to perform the ceremony of manu- mission in the Christian Churches.^ The theory of the Church may have looked upon slavery as legitimate, but it is clear enough that the practical influence of the Church was in fav(;)UTof mamiDpiission. In later centuries we find references to the manumission of slaves which imply that this was con- sidered to be a pious work, likely to profit the souls ot the persons who perform it.* We do not doubt that the general • influeuce of the Church tended towards the mitigation of the .' hardships of slavery, and even towards the disappearance of ^the institution. But the more clearly we may recognise this the more necessary is it to recognise also that the theo^of the Church is somewhat different : we think that^it must be admitted that the influence of the theory may have had con- siderable effect both in defending the actually existing slavery \^ of the ancient world, and in assisting in its revival in the fifteenth century when Europeans came into contact with the negro races.

1 Cod. i. 4. 12, 14, vi. 4. 4. 2. Africanse, 64 and 82.

2 Cod. i. 4. 24. * Cf. the "Formulae" of Marculfus, 2 Cod. i. 13. 1 and 2. Cf. Cod. Eccl. xxxii. and xxxiv.


LjOOQIC 


125


CHAPTEK XL

NATURAL EQUALITY AND GOVERNMENT.

In dealing with the question of slavery we have anticipated a good deal of what we have to say about the relation of the theory of natural equality to the theory of organised society I and government. That natural equality which is, in the judg- ment of the Fathers, contrary to slavery, is also contrary to the subjection of n\gn to man m government.

The Fathers maintain that man is made for society, that he is by nature sociable and inclined to love his fellow-men. Lactantius, in commenting on a passage from Cicero's De ^ Eepublica, which we have already discussed, denies that they were ever apart.^ It is indeed possible that Lactantius is a little confused in his judgment of human nature. In another place he seems to mean that man does indeed desire society, but it is on account of the weakness of his body, which makes him incapable of defending himself in solitude.^ Still, even so, he maintains that men are by nature driven to the social life. A^ clearer conception is very forcibly stated by St Augustine in several passages. Human nature is, he says, _ sociable, and men are held together by the bond of kinship.* He approves of the conception that the life of the wise man is a social life.* Man, he says, "is driven by the very laws of his nature to enter into society and to make peace with

^ Lact., Div. Inst., vi 10. naturale bonum, vim quoque amicitise ;

  • Lact., De Opificio Dei, iv. ob hoc ex uno Deus voliiit omnes

^ St Aug., De Bono Conjugali, i. : homines condere, ut in sua societate

" Quoniam unusquisque homo humani non sola similitudine generis, sed

generis pars est, et sociale quiddam est etiam cognationis vinculo tenerentur."

humana natura, magnumque habet et ^ St Aug., De Civ., xix. 5. •






Vi


126 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [pART III.

men.^ It is of some importance to observe this judgment, for, as we have already said, it must be remembered that ancient philosophy had spoken with a twofold voice on the matter. The Epicurean had plainly tended to think of political life as at the most a necessity, perhaps an unfortunate necessity, «lrising*from the infirmities of human nature, while the con- ception of the obligation of political life even for the wise man had been carried on by the Stoics, although, as we have already seen, it requires a little care to recognise how emphatically they held this. Lactantius may perhaps waver between two opinions, perhaps scarcely recognising the significance of the question ; but St Augustine, at least, is clear in his judgment, and he is, as far as we see, the representative of the normal type of thought of Christian writers.

Man is by nature made for society. But it is not by nature that man is the lord of man, it is not by nature jthat ma^ is in subjection to man. We must recur again to that most important treatment of the question by St Augustine, to which we have already referred in dealing with slavery. God made rational beings in His own image, not to be lords over each other, but to be lords of the ir- rational creatures; the primitive good men were rather shepherds of their flocks than kings of men.^ The govern- ment of man by man is not part of the natural order of the world. In another place St Augustine speaks in the severest terms of the desire of domination, and treats it as arising from an intolerable pride which forgets that men are each other's equals.* Gregory the Great represents precisely the

^ St Aug.jDeCiv., xix. 12 : "Quanto quid postulet ordo creaturarum, quid

magis homo fertur quodam modo exigat meritum peccatorum." naturae suae legibus ad ineundam ^ St Aug., De Doctr. Christ., i. 23 :

societatem pacemque cum hominibus, "Magnum autem aliquid adeptum se

quantum in ipso est, omnibus ob- putat, si etiam sociis, id est aliis

tenendum." hominibus, dominari potuerit. Inest

^ StAug., DeCiv.,xix. 15 : "Ration- enim vitioeo animo id magis appetere,

alem factum ad imaginem suam noluit et sibi tanquam debitum vindicare,

nisi irrationalibus dominari : non hom- quod uni proprie debetur Deo. . . .

inem homini, sed hominem pecori. Cum vero etiam eis qui sibi naturaliter

Inde primi justi pastores pecorum pares simt, hoc est, hominibus, domin-

magis quam reges hominum constituti ari appetat, intolerabilis animi superbia

sunt, ut etiam sic insinuaret Deus, est."






CHAP. XI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND GOVERNMENT. 127

same attitude towards the primitive order of human life. In the passage already quoted in relation to slavery, he points out the immense profit that great men will cferive from the consideration of the equality of human nature, the great benefit they will gain if they will recollect that in the beginning man was set over the other animals, nit over his fellow-man.^ It is probable that Gregory the Great is here following St Augustine, but the general source of the theory can hardly be mistaken : it is that same Stoic theory of a primitive state in which the conventional institutions of society did not yet exist, of which we have already spoken so of^n. The primitive state of man was to these Fathers, as it had been to the Stoics like Posidonius and Seneca, a state without any coercive government : in the state of nature men did not need this.

It must be noticed that, at least in St Gregory the Great, this does not mean that in the state of innocence there Vas no order of society or distinction of authority. In a letter ad- dressed to the bishops of the kingdom of Childebert, in ratifying the authority of Virgilius, the Bishop of Aries, as represent- ing the Soman See, St Gregory urges that some system of authority is necessary in every society — that even the angels,^ although they are free from sin, are yet ordered in a hierarchy of greater and less.^ St Gregory's conception is very similar

^ St Gregory the Great, Exp. Mor. in ent, una concordise fieret ex diversitate

Job, xxi. 16 : " Sancti autem viri cum contextio et recte officiorum gerer-

prsesunt, non in se potestatem ordinis etur administratio singulorum. Neque

sed sequalitatem conditionis attendunt, enim uniyersitas alia poterat ratione

nee prseesse gaudent hominibus sed subsistere, nisi hujusmodi magnus earn

prodesse. Sciunt enim quod antiqui differentiao ordo servaret. Quia vero

patres nostri non tam reges hominum creatura in una eademque aequalitate

quam pastores peoorum memorantur. gubemari vel vivere non potest, cseles-

. . . Homo quippe animalibus irra- tium militiarum exemplar nos instruit,.

tionabilibus, non autem ceteris bom- quia dum sunt angeli, et sunt arch-

inibus natura prselatus est." Of. xxiv. angeli, liquet, quia non sequales sunt,

25. sed in potestate et ordine, sicut nostris,

2 St Gregory the Great, Ep. v. 69 : differt alter ab altero. Si ergo inter hos

'^ Ad hoc dispensationis divinse provisio qui sine peccato sunt ista constat esse

gradus diversos et ordines constituit distinctio, quis hominum abnuat huic

esse distinctod, ut, dum reverentiam se libenter dispositioni submittere, cui

minores potioribus exhiberent et poti- novit etiam angelos obedire ? " ores minoribus dilectionem impender-






128 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

to that of Seneca and Posidonius, who, while they think that there was no organised coercive government in the primitive age, think that in that time men freely obeyed the wise.

To return, it seems clear that both St Augustine and St Oregory look upon the institution of coercive government as not belonging to the primitive state of man ; they do not think that government of this kijid is a natural institution ; but this does not mean that the Fathers look upon the ordered govern- ment of society among men as they actually are, as a thing improper or illegitimate. We have already, in considering their attitude to the institution of slavery, recognised that they <5onceive of the conditions proper to human life as having been -completely altered by the entrance of sin into the world. Slavery was contrary to the natural law of the primitive condition of human innocence, but is proper and even useful under the actual conditions of human nature. It is the same with the institution of government. Coercive government has been made necessary through sin, and is a divinely appointed remedy for -sin.

It is interesting to find this conception developed by the -Christian writers from a very early date. We have already considered St Paul's treatment of the institution of government cgid the sanctity which belongs to it. He affirms its sanctity and explains this as arising from the fact that its purpose is to repress the evil and to reward the good. St Clement of Rome, in the great liturgical prayer which forms a concluding part ^f his letter, does not go beyond St PauFs conception of the sanctity of government: he prays to God for the rulers of

yinankind, as those to Whom God has given authority and

/glory, that God will give them wisdom.^

Towards the end of the second century we have in the writings of St Irenseus a detailed discussion of the origin of government, of the circumstances which have made it neces- sary, and of the purpose whiph it is intended to serve. The passage occurs with that apparent irrelevance which is so characteristic of the writings of the 'Fathers, in a discussion of the mendacity of the devil. Irenseus begins by asserting

^ St Clement of Rome, 61.






CHAP. XI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND GOVERNMENT. 129

that the devil was, as always, a liar, when in the temptation he said to our Lord that all the kingdoms of the earth were his, to give to whom he would. It is not the devil at all, Irenseus says, who has appointed the kingdoms of the world, but God, and he establishes this by a reference to the passage in the Proverbs, " By me kings reign and princes administer justice," and the saying of St Paul, already discussed (Rom. xiii. 1, &c.) Author- ity came from God, not from the devil. So far we have nothing new; but Irenaeus then proceeds to discuss the causes which made government necegjary, and urges that this is due to the fact that men departed from God and hated their fellow-men, and fell into confusion and disorder of every kind, and so God set men over each other, imposing the fear of man upon men, and subjecting men to the authority of men, that by this means they might be compelled to some measure of righteousness and just dealing.! We have here an explicit statement that the

/ institution of government has been made necessary by sin

\ and is a divinely appointed remedy for sin.

The Christian writers of the same period as Irenseus do not indeed draw out the relation of government to the existence of evil, as Irenseus has done, but they agree with him in asserting its divine origin. Justin Martyr lays great stress upon the fact that Christians had been taught by Christ Himself to pay taxes to the ruler, to " render to Csesar the things which are Csesar's," and urges that, while Christians can only worship God, in all other ways they gladly serve their rulers.^ Theophilus of Antioch, another writer of the second century, while also refusing to worship the king, says that he should be honourecl and obeyed, for at least in some sense it may be said of him that he has received his authority from God.* No doubt these emphatic assertions of the divine authority of the ruler, while they may have been partly intended to allay any suspicions of I disloyalty, were also intended to counteract those tendencies to anarchy in the Christian societies, to whose existence the New Testament bears witness. The Christian writers of the second century, then, clearly carry on the tradition of the New Testa-

^ Irenseus, Adv. Hser., v. 24. ' Theophilus of Antioch, Ad Auto-

  • -* Justin Martyr, First Apology, 17. lycum, i. 11.

VOL. I. I






130 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.


ment that the principle of authority is a divine principle, while in the case of Irenseus at least we see that this means that government is a divinely instituted remedy for the sin and wickedness of men.

The great writers of the fourth, fifth, and sixth centuries carry on precisely the same conceptions. Most of them indeed only deal with the divine character of government, but St Ambrose, St Augustine, St Gregory the Great, and St Isidore develop the conception of St Irenaeus that government is the necessary divine remedy for sin. St Ambrose speaks of the authority of rulers as being imposed upon foolish peoples, to compel men even though unwillingly to obey the wise.^ St Augustine, as we have already seen, looks upon the government of men by men as being contrary to the primitive condition of human nature, but as being a necessary and divinely appointed consequence of and remedy for sin.^ We give below another passage from his writings in which his conception of government is very clearly drawn out.^

St Gregory the Great echoes the sentiments of St Augustine : we^need only refer the reader to the passage which we have already quoted in part, but we may draw attention to some phrases in this which were not specially germane to the subject


0^ Sfc Ambrose, Ep. xxxvii. 8.

•2 St Aug., De. Civ. Dei, xix. 15. ^ St Aug., Quar. Prop, ex Ep. ad Rom., 72 : " Quod autem ait. Omnia anima potestatibus sublimioribus sub- dita sit : non est enim potestas nisi a Deo, rectissime jam monet ne quis ex eo quod a Domino suo in libertatem vocatus est, factusque Christianus, ex- tollatur in superbiam, et non arbitretur in hujus vitse itinere servandum esse ordinem suum, et potestatibus sub- limioribus, quibus pro tempore rerum temporalium gubematio tradita est, putet non se esse subdendum. Cum enim constemus ex anima et corpore, et quamdiu in hac vita temporali sumus, etiam rebus temporalibus ad subsidium degendse hujus vitae utamur; oportet nos ex ea parte, quae ad banc vitam pertinet, subditos esse potestatibus, id


est, hominibus res humanas cum aliquo honore administrantibus. Ex ilia vero parte qua credimus Deo, et in regnum ejus vocamur, non nos oportet esse sub- ditos cuiquam homini, idipsum in nobis evertere cupienti, quod Deus ad vitam seternam donare dignatus est. Si <}uis ergo putat quoniam Christianus est, non sibi esse vectigal reddendum aut tributum, aut non esse exhibendum honorem debitum eis quee hsec cui*ant potestatibus ; in magno errore versatur. Item si quis se putat esse subdendum, ut etiam in suam Mem habere potes- tatem arbitretur eum qui tempondibus administrandis aliqua sublimitate pr83- oellit; in majorem errorem labitur. Sed modus iste servandus est quam Dominus ipse prsescribit, ut reddamus Csesari quae Cs&saris sunt, et Deo quse Dei sunt."






€HAP. XI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND GOVERNMENT. 131


(»:


which we were then dealing with. Men, he says, are indeed by nature equal, but they are different in condition as a conse- quence of sin : as all men do not live equally well, one man must be ruled by another ; there is a bestial tendency in the human race which can .only be kept down by fear.^

St Isidore of Seville, in the same passage in which he deals ith slavery as a consequence of and a remedy for sin, also deals with government in the same fashion. The just God, he says, has so ordered life, in making some men slaves and someV men lords, that the tendency to evil may be restrained by the \ fear of punishment ; and to the same end princes and kings are J appointed, that by fear of them and by their laws the people/ may be restrained from evil and encouraged to good.^ /

It is unnecessary to multiply quotations from the Fathers to show that they all accept the theory of St Paul, that Governr men^j ia divi nr inn tituti nn We shall have to recur to the matter again when we discuss their conception of the character of the authority of Government, the question of its absolute or limited nature, and the propriety or impropriety of resistance to it. So jar w e are only concerned to make it clear how ^ is t hat We^ d^Jhg^:at.hp^a»at4Uiia. iiitn^ ^XasS^1^^3mn\^^Ji^^ Oovernment i^ jipt natural an4-ffHmrivftj and. :f%t that .it is A. divme institution. Wfr-i^ave tried to make it clear that this apparently self-contradictory position is really a perfectly \ intelligible, and, on its own terms, rational one. For man is \ not now in the condition in which God made him : once he j was innocent and harmless, now his nature is depraved and / corrupted, and conditions which would have been wholly/ contrary to his primitive nature are now necessary ana useful.


^ St Gregory the Great, Exp. Mor., in Job xxi. 16 : ** Nam ut prsefati sumus, omnes homines natura sequales genuit, sed variante meritorum ordine, alios aliis dispensatio occtdta postponit. Ipsa autem diversitas, quse accessit ex vitio recte est divinis judiciis ordinata, ut quia omnis homo iter vitae seque non graditur, alter ab altero regatur. . . . Nequaquam ergo prsepositi ex hoc


qusesito timore superbiant, in quo non suam gloriam, sed subditorum juatitiam quaerunt. In eo enim quod metus sibi a perverse viventibus exigunt, quasi a non hominibus, sed brutis animalibus domi- nantur, quia videlicet ex qua parte bestiales sunt subditi, ex ea etiam de- bent formidine jacere substrati."

2 St Isidore of Seville, Sen tent., iiL 47. See p. 119.






132


CHAPTER XII.

THE THEORY OF PROPERTY.

We must turn to the theory of property in the Christian writers. We have already seen that the New Testament does not seem to contain any definite theory of property : it may contain traces of a theory that the perfect man has little to do with wealth, but the general tendency of the New Testa- ment writers seems to be to assume the existence of the insti- tution, while they enjoin upon Christian men the duty of using their property especially for the benefit of all the members of the Christian societies.

The earliest Fathers carry on these conceptions very much as we find them in the New Testament : on the one hand they do not seem to have any dogmatic theory of the community of Christian men's goods ; on the other hand they continue to insist that the Christian man is bound to use his property to relieve the wants of his fellow-man, and especially of his fellow- Christian. The 'Teaching of the Twelve Apostles' and the so-called Epistle of Barnabas reproduce from some common source very emphatic exhortations to liberality in giving, which in one phrase echo the words of the Acts of the Apostles : " Thou shalt not turn away from him that hath need, but shalt share all things with thy brother, and shalt not say that they are thine own : for if ye are sharers in that which is immortal, how much more in those things which are mortal."^ The phrase, "Thou shalt not say that thgy are thine own" {ovk ipei^ tSca elvai), is very near the phrase of the Acts, " No one of them said that ought of the things which he possessed was his

1 * Teaching of the Twelve Apostles,' iv. 8. Cf . Ep. of Barnabas, xix. 8.






CHAP. XII.] THE THEORY OP PROPERTY. 133

own " (ovSe eh tl t£v v'7rap')(pvT(ov avr& eXeyev iBcov elvac, aW Tjv aifToh airavra kocvo).

The same conception is represented by Justin Martyr in the second century. In his first 'Apology' he contrasts the eovetousness and greed of the ordinary man with the liberality of the Christian. He says of the Christians, that they brought what they possessed into a common stock and shared with every one in need.^ Justin Martyr again suggests the phrase of the' Acts. In the third century St Cyprian quotes the narra- tive of the Acts, and commenting on it says, that such conduct is that of the true sons of God, the imitators of God. God's gifts are given to all mankind, the day enlightens all, th^sun shines upon all, the rain falls and the wind blows upon all, to all men comes sleep, the splendour of the stars and the moon are common to all. Man is truly an imitator of God when he follows the equal beneficence of God by imparting to all the brotherhood the good things which he possesses.^ Cyprian does ' not say that the Christian man must share his goods with all the brethren, but clearly he looks on this as the most perfect way. This gradually became the common view of many Christian writers.

But before considering the later Fathers we must observe that other early Christian writers present us with a somewhat different view of the subject. One of the short treatises of Clement of Alexandria discusses the Gospel story of the rich young ruler,^ and it is both interesting and important to observe that Clement treats our Lord's injunction to the young man to go and sell all that he had and to give to the poor as being a metaphorical saying, and as really referring to the pas- sions of the soul. He maintains that there is no advantage in poverty unless it is incurred for some special object.* Desti- tution is distracting and harassing, and it is much better to have such a competence as will suffice for oneself and enable a man to help those who are in need.^ Kiches, therefore, are

^ Justin Martyr, First Apol., xiv. ^ St Cyprian, De Op. et Eleem., 26.

Cf. Ixvii., and TertuUm^^^ApfiL^JSO, * Clem, of Alex., Quis Dives Sal vetur,

I owe the last two references to an 5-14. article by Dr Cobb in the * Economic * Id., 11.

Review ' for April 1895. 5 j^j,^ 13,






134 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

things which may, if rightly used, be serviceable to the posses- sor and to others, and are not to be thrown away.^ Clement's interpretation of our Lord's words is not, so far as we know, a common one, biit it is of considerable importance.

The same general conception is very strongly held by Lac- tantius. He discusses Plato's theory of community of property, and very emphatically repudiates it as impossible and unjust, and urges that justice is not a matter of external condition but of the soul.2 j|j jg j^q^ property that must be abolished, but pridfe and insolence. If the rich would lay these aside it would make no difference though one man were rich and another poor.^ In another passage he discusses the poetical conception of the Golden or Saturnian Age. He looks upon this as no poetical fiction, but a condition of things which really existed and out of which men passed by reason of sin and the loss of the true religion. Lactantius, that is, formally accepts that theory of the state of nature which we have already considered ; but it is very noticeable that he refuses to accept the poetical concep- tion of a complete" community of goods in that age. He main- tains that we must take this as a poetical metaphor. He cannot think that even in that age there was no such thing as private property, but only that men were so generous and kindly that no one was in want.*

What are we to conclude as to the position of the earlier Fathers with respect to the institution of property ? We must first observe that their whole thought is dominated by the sense of the claims of the brotherhood. Whatever may be the further significance of the narrative of the Acts and the phrases of * Barnabas ' and the ' Teaching of the Twelve Apostles,' this at least is clear, that the Christian societies recognised that every member had a claim upon the others for that which was necessary for his maintenance. Behind this, however, there lies a question more difficult to answer. Did the first Christian teachers and societies, or any of them, think that property was in itself unlawful or improper for the true Christian? It should, perhaps, be observed here that the very important phrases of 'Barnabas' and the 'Teaching' are drawn from a

1 Clem, of Alex., 14. 2 La^t., Div. Inst., iii. 21. » Id., iii. 22. * Id., v. 5.






CHAP. XII.] THE THEORY OF PKOPERTY. 135

common source, to which the name of * Two Ways ' has been given, and that it has been argued that this work was a Jewish manual of moral discipline. The phrases in the Acts have a very similar ring. It may be suggested, then, that the notion that the perfect life was that of a society in which all shared equally with their brethren all that they had, was one which belonged to some form of the later Judaism,^ and so passed into the Church.

It is just possible that there m^y have existed within the Church a tendency to think that among Christian men there should be no private . property. But what we know of the historical conditions of the early Christian societies compels us also to recognise that this conception was not carried out into practice, so far as we know, in any community, not even in the community at Jerusalem. It would, however, seem as though there may very early'have grown up in the Christian societies a theory that, while it was perfectly lawful for the Christian man to hold property, to give all that one had to the common funds of the society was the more perfect way. This is not, in- deed, a view which was universally held. Clement of Alexandria and Lactantius, as we have seen, exhibit no special inclination towards it, but it seems to underlie the phrases of St Cyprian, it was developed by two of the most influential of Western Christian writers, St Jerome^ and St Augustine,^ commenting on our Lord's words to the rich young ruler, and it formed part of that theory of the ascetic life as the more perfect way wliich ' dominates so much of Western thought in the Middle Ages.

When we turn to the later Fathers we find that their theory of property is closely connected with the same general philo- sophical system as that which governs the rest of their political theories. In the first place, it seems quite clear that they recog- nise that private property is in no way evil if it is rightly used. St Augustine maintains this dogmatically against the Mani- chseans. Who does not understand, he says, that it is not blame- worthy to have such things (i.e., property of various kinds), but only to love them, to put one's hope in them, to prefer

^ It may be conjectured that this was ^ St Jerome, Ep. cxxx. 14.

connected with Essene principles. ^ St Augustine, Ep. clvii. iv.






136 xrfte NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.

them to, or even to compare them with truth, justice, wisdom, faith, a good conscience, with love to God and our neighbours.^ The same view could be illustrated from the other Christian writers, as being the normal judgment of the Christian Church.^ Whatever doubt may be entertained as to some primitive Chris- tians, there is no doubt about the formal judgment of the de- veloped society. But when we have recognised this fact, we must also observe that this merely means that the Church accepted the* institution of property as being in accordance with the actual conditions of life, just as it accepted the in- stitution of slavery or coercive government : it does not mean that the Church considered private property to belong to the natural or primitive condition of human life. It is true that the Fathers deal with this question in the most incidental and partial manner, and that it is therefore difficult to express our- selves very dogmatically about the theory which lies behind their references, but we think that the best interpretation of these is that, they thought that in the primitive state all things were common, — that it is not the law of God but that of the State which directly gives this thing to one man and that to another. This view is more clearly expressed by St Ambrose than by any other writer. We may first consider a very interesting and well-known passage in his treatise 'De Officiis.' St Ambrose roundly says that private property is not by nature ; nature only produced a common right, use and habit produced private right; nature gave all things to all men.^ We must

^ St Augustine, Contra Adimantum communia, id est, publica pro publicis

Manichaei Discipulum, xx. 2 : " Quia habeat, privata pro suis. Ne hoc

hie uon inteUigat non esse culpabile quidem secundum naturam, natura

habere ista, sed amare et spem in eis enim omnia omnibus in commune

ponere,eteapr8eferreautetiamconferre profudib. Sic enim Deus generari

veritati, justitiae, sapientise, fidei, bonae jussit omnia ut pastus omnibus com-

conscientiee, charitati Dei et proximi, munis esset, et terra foret omnium

quibus omnibus anima pia dives est quaedam possessio. Natura igitur jus

in secretis suis coram oculis Dei." commune geueravit, usurpatio jus fecit

  • Cf. St Hilary of Poitiers, Com. privatum. Quo in loco aiunt placuisse

on Matt. xix. 9 ; St Ambrose, Ep. Ixiii. Stoicis, quae in terris gignantur, omnia 92 ; Salvian, Ad Ecclesiam, i. 7 ; St ad usus hominum creari ; homines Aug., De Moribus Eccl. Cath., i. 35. autem hominum causa esse generates,

  • St Ambrose, De Off., i. 28, " Deinde ut ipsi inter se aliis prodesse possint.

formam justitiae putaverunt, ut quis g






CHAP. XII.] THE THEORY OF PROPERTY. 137

not understand this as meaning that property is unlawful, but only that it is not a natural or primitive institution. St Am- brose here, as throughout his treatise, is largely dependent on Cicero's treatise of the same name, and we may be fairly certain that Cicero's words, " Sun^; autem privata nulla natura," ^ are the text which he is amplifying. It is not very easy to give any very definite meaning to Cicero's phrase : that of St Ambrose is a good deal easier, for, as we have seen, by his time the theory of the state of nature as contrasted with the state of conven- tional institutions had become a commonplace of Christian political theory.

Another passage from St Ambrose will perhaps make the matter clearer. God meant, he says, the world to be the common possession of all men, and to produce its fruits for all ; it was avarice which produced the rights of property. It is only just, therefore, that a man should support the poor with some share of that which was meant for all mankind.^ St Ambrose here comes very near indeed to the form of Seneca's state- ment of the origin of property, namely, that it arose from avarice,^ and we feel that we can hardly be wrong in looking upon the foundation of St Ambrose's theory of property as being the same as that of Seneca. With St Ambrose's view may be very well compared that of Ambrosiaster. In one passage he treats charity as St Ambrose does, as being an act of justice, — for God, he says, gives all things in common to all men.*

1 Cicero, De Off., i. 7. » Sen., Ep. xiv. 2. See p. 24.

^ St Amb., Com. on Ps. cxviii. 8. * Ambrosiaster, Com. on 2 Cor. ix.

22 : " Cum prsesertim Dominus Deus 9, &c. : " Misericordia ergo hsec {i.e.,

noster terram banc possessionem almsgiving to the f)oor), justitia ap-

omnium hominum voluit esse com- pellata est ; quia sciens qui largitur,

munem, et fructus omnibus minis- omnia Deum communiter omnibus

trare ; sed avaritia possessionum jura dare, quia sol enim oritur, et pluit

distribuit. Justum est igitur ut si omnibus; et terram omnibus dedit;

aJiquid tibi privatum vindicas, quod idcirco dividit cum eis, qui copiam

generi humano, immo omnibus ani- terras non habent; ne beneficiis Dei

mantibus in commime collatum est, privati videantur. Justus ergo est,

saltem aliquid inde pauperibus as- qui sibi soli non detinet, quod scit

pergas ; ut quibus juris tui consor- omnibus datum ; et Justus non solum

tium debes, his alimenta non deneges." hoc in tempore, sed et in setemum ;

Cf. also St Amb., De Off., i. 11. xjuia in seculo futuro banc habebit






138 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

Bt Zeiio of Verona, a writer of the latter part of the fourth century, might perhaps be taken to illustrate an almost dogmatic theory of the propriety of some system of communism: he is, indeed, speaking mainly of a community of goods among Christians, founding this upon the passage in the Acts which we have already examined, but it must be observed that the latter words of the passage extend his conception to mankind at large.^ We think, however, that St Zeno is speaking prim- arily in a practical sense — that he wishes to put in the strongest possible way the obligation of charity and active benevolence : he certainly puts the matter in a very strong way, for he continues, after the passage we have quoted in the note, to say that the obligation to give to those who need is not to be limited even by the duty of providing for a man's own family.

With these views we must compare those of St Gregory the Great. In one passage he deals with private property in much the same spirit as St Ambrose and Ambrosiaster. He treats the earth and its products as the gifts of God to all toen, and therefore regards almsgiving as an act of justice, not of charity. It is evident that he does not regard private property itself as wrong, but, on the other hand, he does not seem to regard it as an absolute right. On the contrary, if a man uses it only for himself, he regards his action as unjust.^

eecum in perpetuum. . . . Omnia 32), nee fuit inter iUos discrimen ullum,

Dei sunt, et semina et nascentia Dei • ' nee quidquam suum ex bonis putabant,

nutu crescunt, et multiplicantur ad quae eis erant ; sed erant illis omnia

USU8 hominum ; Deus ergo qui hsec dat, communia,' sicut dies, sol, nox, pluvia,

ipse et jubet de his communicari eis nascendi atque moriendi conditio ; quae

qui indigent. . . . Hsec est justitia, humano generi, sine personarum aliqua

ut quia Deus dat, retribuat ex eo et exceptione, sequabiliter justitia est div-

homo ei, cui deest." ina largita. Cum hsec ita sint, procul

^ St Zeno of Verona, Tractatus, i. dubio non est a Tyranno dissimilis, qui

3. 6 : " Sed, inquies, justuni est, ut solus habet, quod potest prodesse com-

mea servem, aliena non quseram. Hoc modis plurimorum."

etiam Gentes dicere consueverunt. Gae- ^ St Gregory the Great, Liber

terum apud Deum quam sit injustum, Regulse Pastoralis, iii. 21 : * Admon-

mox videbimus. Nunc primo omnium, endi simt qui nee aliena appetimt, nee

optime Christiane, scire cupio, quae sunt sua largiuntur, ut sciant sollicite quod

tua cum sint timentibus Deum uni- ea de qua sumti sunt, cunctis hominibus

versa communia, sicut scriptum est : terra communis est, et idcirco alimenta

  • Turba autem eorum, qui crediderant, quoque omnibus communiter profert.

animo ac mente una agebant ' (Acts iv. Incai^sum ergo se innocentes putant,






CHAP. XII.] THE THEORY OF PROPERTY. 139


We should suggest that in this conception we have the beginnings of a distinction which became very important in the Middle Ages, and is very carefully drawn out by St Thomas Aquinas — the distinction between property as a right of distri- bution, and property as a right of personal use. St Thomas holds that private property is not an institution of natural but of positive law, and that the right of property only extends to the acquisition and distribution of things : so far as their use is concerned, men are bound to treat them as things pertaining to all. A man has the right to use what he needs, and St Thomas does not take this in any narrow sense, but beyond this a man only holds his property for the common use.^ We should suggest that the passages of the Fathers which we have just examined show us the germs out of which this theory grew. Property is not primitive but conventional ; it is not therefore illegitimate, but, on the other hand, it is not an unrestricted right: the circumstances of the world and of human nature may make it necessary that men should take things to them- selves from the common stock, but they do this subject to the responsibility of using all that they do not themselves need, for the common benefit.

St Augustine does not deal directly with the question of the primitive conditions with regard to property. But he furnishes us with a number of very important observations on the immediate source of this right. His theory of property is for the most part developed somewhat incidentally in his defence

qui commune Dei muAUs sibi privatum dicit : * Dispersit dedit pauperibus, jus-

vindicant; qui cum accepta non tribu- titia ejus manet in setemum.* Cum

unt, in proximorum nece grassantur ; enim largitatem impensam pauperibua

quia tot pene quotidie perimunt, quot prsemisisset, non banc vocare miseri-

morientium pauperum apud se sub- cordiam sed justitiam maluit ; quia

sidia abscondunt. Nam cum quselibet quod a communi Domino tribuitur,

necessaria indigentibus ministramus, justum profecto est, ut quicunque

sua illis reddimus, non nostra larg- accipiunt, eocommuniterutantur. Huic

imur ; justitiee debitum potius solvi- etiam Salomon ait, * Qui Justus est,

mus, quam misericordise opera im- tribuet et non cessabit.' "

plemus. Unde et ipsa Veritas cum de ^ Cf. Notes in Econ. Review, Janu-

misericordiacauteexhibendaloqueretur, ary 1894, by R. W. Cariyle, "Some

ait, 'Attendite ne justitiam vestram Economic Doctrines of St Thomas

faciatis coram hominibus.' Cuiquoque Aquinas." sententiae etiam Psalmista concinnens






140 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.


of the confiscation of the churches and other possessions of the Donatists in Africa by the Imperial Government. It would seem, from his allusions to their complaints, that they protested that these confiscations were unjust, and perhaps even that they were outside the powers of the Government. His reply to their contentions is founded upon the following arguments. Property, he says, may be considered as an insti- tution of the divine lawr or of the human law. By the divine law property is either all in the hands of God, for " the earth is the Lord's and the fulness thereof," or else all things belong to the righteous, and the Donatists are not righteous. By human law property belongs to this or that individual, but what human law has given human law can take away. St Augustine also maintains that the right of property is limited by the use to which it is put : the man who does not use his property rightly has no real claim to it.^


^ St Augustine, Epist., xciii. xi. : ** Et quamvis res qusaque terrena non recta a quoquam possideri possit, nisi vel jure divino, quo cuncta justorum sunt, vel jure humane, quod in potestate regum est terrae; ideoque res vestras falso>ip- pelletis, quas nee justi possidetis, et secundum leges regum terrenorum amittere jussi estis, frustraque dicatis

  • nos eis congregandis laboravimus,' cum

scriptum leguatis, * Labores impiorum justi edent * " (Prov. xiii. 22).

Tract, vi. in Joannis Evangelium, 25 1

    • Ecce sunt villae : quo jure defendis

villas ? divino an humano ? Respon- deant : Divinum jus in Scripturis habemus, humanum jus in legibus regum. Unde quisque possidet quod possidet ? Nonne jure humano ? Nam jure divino, Domini est terra et pleni- tude ejus : pauperes et divites Deus de uno limo fecit, et pauperes et divites una terra supportat. Jure tamen humano dicit, Hsec villa mea est, heec domus mea, hie servus mens est. Jure ergo humano, jure imperatorum. Quare ? Quia ipsa jura humana per imperatores et reges sseculi Deus distribuit generi humano.


• Vultis legamus leges imperatorum, et secundum ipsas agamus de villis. Si jure humano vultis possidere, recitemus leges imperatorum : videamus si volue- runt aliquid ab hsereticis possideri. Sed quid mihi est imperator ? Secun- dum jus ipsius possides terram. Aut toUe jura imperatorum, et quis audet dicere : mea est ilia villa, aut mens est ille servus, aut domus hsec mea est ? Si autem ut teneantur ista ab homin- ibus, jura acceperunt regum, vultis recitemus leges, ut gaudeatis quia vel unum hortum habetis, et non impute tis nisi mansuetudini columbsa, quia vel ibi vobis permittitur permanere? Leguntur enim leges manifestae, ubl praeceperunt imperatores, eos qui prse- ter Ecclesise Catholicae communionem usurpant sibi nomen Christianum, nee volunt in pace colere pacis auctorem, nihil nomine Ecclesiso audeant po^- dere.

26 : " Sed quid nobis et imperatori ? Sed jam dixi, de jure humano ^i^tur. Et tamen Apostolus voluit serviri reg- ibus, voluit honorari reges, et dixit

  • Regem reveremini.' Noli dicere :

Quid mihi et regi? Quid tibi ergo






CHAP.


XII.]


THE THEORY OP PROPERTY.


141


It is clear from these statements that St Augustine regards property as normally an institution of human and positive law. His distinction between the jtLs divinum and the jvs hunianum is not indeed the same as that between the jtcs naturcUe and the jm civile, but at least it is parallel to it, and it suggests to us very strongly that St Augustine recognises no proper right in things except that which is given by the State. This view is by no means on the saIa^ lines as that of the lawyers, who re- garded some form of private property as being by natural law : he does not indeed contradict the legal theory of " occupation "^ and the right which can be acquired in the res nullius by him who " occupies " it,^ but his phrases suggest that this theory is not at all in his mind. Incidentally it is interesting to observe in the passage first quoted that the Donatists are represented as urging an argument very analogous to that on which Locke founds his theory of property, namely, that they had acquired their property by labour. St Augustine brushes this aside unsympathetically by an appeal to the Scripture, which says that the just shall devour the labour of the wicked.


et pcwBBessioni ? Per jura regum pos- sidentur possessiones. Dixisti, quid mihi et regi? Noli dicere posses- siones tuas ; quia ad ipsa jura hu- mana renuntiasti, quibus possiden- tur possessiones. Sed de divino jure ago, ait. Ergo Evangelium recitemus : videamus quo usque Ecclesia Catholica Christi est, super quern venit columba quae docuit : ' Hie est qui baptizat.' Quomodo ergo jure divino possideat qui dicit, Ego baptizo : cum dicat columba

  • Hic est qui baptizat,' cum dicat

Scriptura 'Una est columba mea, una est matri suae.' Quare, laniasti colum- bam ? Imo laniastis viscera vestra : nam vobis laniatis, columba Integra perseverat. Ergo fratres mei, si ubique non habeut quod dicant, ego dico quod faciani: veniant ad- Catholicam, et ^obiscum habebunt non solum terram, sed etiam ilium qui fecit ccelum et terram."

Epist., cliii. 6: "Jamvero si pru-


detfter intueamur quid scriptum est. 'Fidelis hominis totus mundus diviti- arum est, infidelis autem nee obolus ; ' nam omnes qui sibi videntur gaudere licite conquisitis, eisque uti nesciunt,. aliena possidere convincimus ? Hoc enim certe alienum non est, quod jure possidetur ; hoc autem jure quod juste, et hoc juste quod bene. Omne igitur quod male possidetur, alienum est; male autem possidet qui male utitur. (Of. St Isid. of Seville, Etym., v. 25.)

Sermo, L. c. 2. ; "Aurum ejus pro- prium est, qui illo bene utitur, adeoque verius est Dei. Illius est ergo aurum et argentum, qui novit uti auro et argento. Nam etiam inter ipsos homi- nes, tunc quisque habere aliquid dicen- dus est, quando bene utitur. Nam quod juste non tractat, jure non tenet. Quod autem jure non tenet, si suum esse dicerit, non erit vox justi possessoris, sed impudentis incubatoris improbitas."

1 Cf. Digest, xli. 1. 3, &c. See p. 52.






142 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [pART III.

We think that when we consider St Augustine's treatment of property alongside of that especially of St Ambrose, we may feel fairly confident that they represei;it a tradition which differs materially from that of the jurists, a tradition probably derived from the same sources as the view of Seneca — that is, that they would, with Seneca, have classed the institution of property as one of those which belong to the conventions of organised society, and not to the primitive conditions of the human race.

At the same time, it must be observed that St Augustine's views on the limitation of the rights of property, by the use to which it is put, finds a parallel in a phrase of Gains, treating of the limitation of the rights of masters over their slaves : " Male enim nostro jure uti non debemus," ^ — a phrase repeated in slightly different terms by the compilers of Jus- tinian's Institutes : " Expedit enim reipublicse, ne quis re sua male utatur."^ St Augustine's phrases, however, are much wider in scope, and indicate a much more developed theory, than those of the lawyers. We think that this is to be con- nected with the theory of St Ambrose and other Fathers, that the things of the world do not cease to be held for the common good, because it is now lawful for particular persons to hold them as their own private property, and that this conception finally takes a definite form in the distinction between the right of property as an authority in distribution and the right of property as one of unlimited use.

We are now in a position to examine the meaning and signif- icance of the references to the theory of property in St Isidore of Seville. We have already discussed his definition of the jus naturals ; we must now recall the words of this : " Jus naturale est commune omnium nationum, et quod ubique instinctu naturae, non constitutione aliqua habeatur, ut : viri et feminse conjunctio, liberorum susceptio et educatio, comnftinis omnium possessio, et omnium una libertas, acquisitio eorum quae ccelo terra marique capiuntur. Item depositee rei vel commendatae pecuniae restitutio, violentiae per vim repulsio. Nam hoc aut si quid huic simile est, nunquam injustum, sed naturale aequum- que habetur."^ .What does St Isidore mean by "communis

^ Qaius, Inst., i. 63. ^ jugt^^ i. 8. 2. * St Isidore of SeviUe, Etym., v. 4.






CHAP. XII.] THE THEORY OF PROPERTY. 143

omnium possessio"? In the Middle Ages he was no doubt taken as meaning the common possession of all things ; ^ and if that interpretation is correct, St Isidore sets forth in technical language the theory that by natural law all things were common, and there was no private property. But it is not quite certain whether this is the correct interpretation of the phrase. The words can be taken to mean simply that by the law of nature there is a form of property common to all men. This would not necessarily exclude forms of property belonging to groups of men or to individuals.

It is not very easy to determine which interpretation is the correct one. The nearest parallels to St Isidore's phrase are to be found in the Digest and the Institutes; in the former we have Marcianus's phrase : " Quaedam naturali jure communia sunt omnium, quaedam universitatis, qusedam nuUius, pleraque singulorum." ^ Here the phrase itself makes it clear that the genitive om^fdum is possessive ; certain things are common to all. In the Institutes ^ we have Marcianus's phrase repeated with a few variations, and throughout the discussion of property we find the genitive case used in the same sense — e.^., "Communia sunt omnium hsec " ; " Singulorum autem hominum multis modis res fiunt." As far, then, as the grammatical construction is concerned, the precedents in legal phraseology seem to point to the genitive case in St Isidore's phrase as being possessive. Itr must be observed, however, that the legal phrases are not absolutely parallel : communis ii not connected with possessio. But, further, St Isidore goes on to mention certain methods of acquiring property, "Acquisitio eorum quae coelo, terra, marique, capiuntur,"* and certain moral rules which only exist in a condition of things where private property exists, "Depositae rei vel commendatae pecuniae restitutio," and all, it must be noticed, as belonging to the jvs naturcUe. It is difl&cult to understand this, if St Isidore means to say that by natural law all property is common to all : at the most, it may

i.^Xjt. Qratian, Decretum, Dist. i. and 2 Digest, i. 8. 2.

viii., and Alexander of Hales, Summa, ^ Inst., ii. 1.

part iii. Quaest. xxvi. ; Memb. iii., * Of. St Isidore on " Possessiones,"

Art. 2. Et^., XV. 13.






144 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part ni.

be suggested that St Isidore is inconsistent with himself, and that it is idle to expect a thorough and completely thought- out explanation of the subjecc from him. It must also be observed that St Isidore in his definition of the jus gentium does not indicate that private property belongs to it, as he does, for instance, with regard to slavery, and that there is no reference to property in his definition of the/i^s civile}

It seems to us that for the present we must take it as uncer- tain whether St Isidore follows the tradition of the Fathers and the Stoics in thinking that private property is not an insti- tution of the natural law, or the general tradition of the lawyers that even by the natural law some things belonged to indi- viduals. The general tendency of the Fathers is, we think, clear, and in the history of political theory this is the important point, for we are thus able to discover the origin of the dog- matic and developed mediaeval theory.

We can now look back over certain general characteristics of patristic political theory, and we think it has become plain that this turns upon the distinction between the primitive or natural state, with its natural law and institutions, and the actual s£ate, with its conventional institutions adapted to the new characteristics and circumstances of human nature and life.

With regard to the theory of human equality and the insti- tution of slavery, the theory of coercive government, and the theory of property, we have seen that the patristic view turns upon this distinction between the natiiral and primitive, and the conventional and actual. Neither slavery, nor government, nor property are institutions of the natural law, and they did not exist in the natural state. There was a time when men were in- nocent — when, therefore, these institutions did not exist, when they were not needed. Out of those conditions men passed through sin, their nature was changed and corrupted, avarice, hatred, and the lust of domination possessed them. New insti- tutions, founded in some measure upon these vices, were needed to correct these same vices. Slavery and government and

^ St Isidore of Seville, Etym., v. 6 and 5.






CHAP. XII.] THE THEORY OP PROPERTY. 145

private property are institutions arising from the vicious tend- encies of human nature, as it is, but they are also the in- struments by which these vices are corrected. The state and condition of nature is b y the F athers identified with the state and condition of unfallen man.

It is evident, we think, that under sime difiference of phraseology the Fathers are really carrying on the same theory as that of the Stoics as represented by Seneca. The relation of this to the political theory of the lawyers is more complex, but it is clear that they are related, and that, in some measure at least, it is justifiable to explain the two sys- tems by comparing them with each other. We think that the fact that the entire patristic theory turns upon the distinction between the natural and the conventional state, expressed inn deed under the terms of the theological conception of the Fall, but obviously reflecting, not any exclusively Christian concep- tion, but rather some widespread assumption of popular philos- ophy, encourages us in thinking that the same type of thought lies behind the obscurer references of the lawyers.

It appears to us that it is correct to say that in considering the meaning of justice in human life these thinkers found themselves compelled to recognise that there was an apparent inconsistency between some of the great institutions of society and that natural or essential equality of human nature which they had learned from their experience of the universal empires. Slavery, therefore, which Aristotle could explain by a theory which was at least in many respects reasonable, to them was a real difficulty, and what they thought of slavery would naturally extend itself to government. On the other hand, they recognised instinctively, if we may use such a phrase, that human life, as it actually is, needs discipline, needs an order enforced by coercion. And thus they came to make a distinction between an ideal, which they think of as also the primitive condition of man, and the actual. Ideally, man, following his truest nature, obeying the laws of reason and justice, which he always, in some measure, recognises, would have needed no such coercive discipline. But, being what he is, a creature whose- true instincts and nature are constantly

VOL. I. K


CjOOQ IC 


146 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

overpowered by his lower nature, it is only by means of a hard discipline that he can be kept from an anarchy and disorder in which all men would be reduced to an equal level of misery and degradation. Their theory is properly a justification of coercive government, but, naturally enough, the institution of slavery being actually in existence, and appearing, as it must naturally have done to them, to be essential to the whole fabric of civil- ised life, they interpreted it . as another form of discipline. Private property also, with its enormous inequalities, they could not accept as a primitive and natural institution. In a primitive or natural state the rights of property could have been nothing more than the right to use that which a man required. But again, in face of the actual condition of human nature, in view of the avaricious and covetous tendencies of human nature as it actually is, they found that a formal regula- tion of the exercise of the right to use was necessary. Private property is really another disciplinary institution intended to check and counteract the vicious dispositions of men.

The thinkers of this philosophical tendency, then, find a just meaning in the great institutions of human society, human nature being what it actually is, but they conceive of these institutions as being dominated bv the fend which they serve. They are intended to correct the vicious dispositions of men. They are only justified as far as they actually do this. The equality of human nature still dominates all just order. All institutions must be reconciled with this in some sense. Government is intended to correct the evil tendencies of man, but should respect his true qualities. Slavery is jus- tifiable as a necessary discipline of human life, but the man continues in the slave. The institution of private property is necessary to reduce the contradictory claims of men to some order, but the good things of the world are still intended for the use of all. The theory of Natural Law and the Natural State is then partly a theory of the origin of human life and in^itutions, but it is also a theory of the principles of justice, by which all the actual institutions of life are to be tested and corrected.






147


CHAPTER XIII.

THE SACRED AUTHORITY OF THE RULER.

We have now to consider the theory of the nature and imme- diate source of authority in the Christian writers. We have seen that in their view the institution of Government is not primitive, but is made necessary by the vices of human nature. , But Government is a divine institution, a divine remedy for man's sin, and the ruler is the representative of God, and must be obeyed in the name of God. It will be easily understood that the conception was capable of a development which should make the king or ruler the absolute and irresponsible representa- tive of God, who derives his authority directly from God, and is accountable to God alone for his actions. This conception, which in later times became^ the formal theory of the Divine i Eight of the monarch, was, as we think, first drawn out and ^ stated by some of the Fathers, notably by St Gregory the Great. It must at the same time be observed that such a conclusion was not necessary, nor was it at first actually de- veloped. The actual tendencies of the patristic theories are very complex ; we can very clearly see how the theory of the Divine Eight arose out of the general theory of the sacred character gf the civil order, but there are many other tenden- cies in the political theory of the Fathers, and some of their phrases and theories became in later times of the greatest importance in counteracting the arguments of the absolutist thinkers.

We begin by examining the development in the Christian writers of the theory of the authority of the civil ruler, as the representative of God. We have already mentioned i8ome of






148 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.

the strong phrases used by the early Christian writers, to express their sense of the duty of obed ience to the civil ruler.

\ We referred to the words of Theophilus of Antioch, in which,

■while repudiating the worship of the king, he acknowledges that Government is in some sense committed to him by God,

- and that Christian men will therefor^ honour and obey him.^ We should observe that Irenaeus, with whose discussion of the origin and object of Government we dealt fully, makes a state- ment with regard to civil rulers which is of great importance in relation to certain developments of the later theory. He has pointed out that God has given men rulers as a remedy for man's sin and vice, but he adds that often God gives men evil rulers to punish their wickedness.^ The ruler is not only .

/ the minister of God's remedy for sin, but the instrument of His

J punishments. We may doubt whether Irenseus had in his mind the conclusions which might be and ultimately were connected with this view, but it is at least important to observe

, its appearance thus early in Christian theory. St Optatus of Milevis, in his treatise on the Donatist schism in North Africa, expresses the conception, that the ruler is the representative of God, in a still more explicit fashion. It appears froni a passage in this treatise that when the Imperial authority interfered on behalf of the Catholic party, the leader of the Donatists indignantly protested that the Emperor had no concern with Church affairs. St Optatus replies by urging St PauFs commands to Christian men, that they should offer up prayers for kings and those in authority, and asserts that the Empire is not in the Church, but the Church in the

^ Empire, and that there is no one over the Emperor but God only, who made him Emperor.^

  • i^ Theophilus of Antioch, Ad Aut., . . . Jam tunc meditabatur, contra

i. 11. prsBcepta apostoli Pauli, potestatibus et

v3 Irenseus, Adv. Haer., v. 24. regibus injuriam facere, pro quibus, si

^ St Optatus of Milevis, * De Schisma apostolum audiret, quotidie rogare de-

Donatistarum,* iii. 3 : " Qui cum ad buerat. Sic enim docet beatus aposto-

Donatum, patrem tuum, venirent, et lus Paulus : * Rogate pro regibus et

quare venerant indicarent, iUo solito potestatibus, ut quietam et tranquillam

• rurore succensus, in haec verba prorupit : vitam cum ipsis agamus.' Non enim

  • Quid est imperatori cum' ecclesia ? ' respublica est in Ecclesia, sed Ecclesia






CHAP. XIII.] THE SACRED AUTHORITY OP THE RULER. 149


J This theory of the ruler as the representative of God is most cTearly expressed in a phrase used for the first time, as far as we have been able to see, by Ambyosia^er. if we may assume the correctness of the identification of the author of the * (^uaestiones Veteris et Novi Testamenti,' once attributed to St Augustine, with the author of the commentaries on St Paul's Epistles, once attributed to St Ambrose.^ In one passage he says that the king'^ is reverenced on earth as the " Vicar afJGcod," and in another passage he draws out his conception^in^-» very curious dis- tinction. The king has " the image of God as the Bishop has that of Christ." * We shall find this distinction again in Cathul- f us in the ninth century : * it is very interesting and curious, but we do not pretend to be able to interpret it. The title of (, " Vicar of God " is important, as summing up the conception that the authority of the ruler is derived from God Him self.] In the Middle Ages it might mean much more than this, but it would be improper to read later conceptions into a writer of the fourth


in republica est, id est, in imperio Ro- mano ; quod Libanum appellat Christus in Canticis Canticorum, cum dicit :

  • Veni, sponsa mea, inventa de Libano/

id est, de imperio Romano : ubi et saoerdotia sancta sunt, et pudicitia, et virginitas, quae in barbaris gentibus non sunt ; et si essent, tuta esse non possent. . . .

" Carthaginis principatum se tenuisse crediderat : et cum super imperatorem non sit nisi solus deus, qui fecit im- peratorem, dum se Do'natus super imperatorem extollit, jam quasi homi- num excesserat metas, ut prope, se Deum, non hominem eestimaret, non reverendo eum, qui post Deum ab hominibus timebatur."

^ See p. 104, note 4.

^^i£geudqAugustu^, Quaestiones Vet- eris et Novi Testamenti, xci. : " Rex enim adoratur in terns quasi vicskrius Dei. Christus autem post vicariam impletam dispensationem adoratur in coelis et in terra."

xxxv. : " Qua ratione David Saul, postquam Deus abeo recessit, Christum


Domini vocat, et honorem defert ei? Non nesciens David divinam esse trtidi- tionem in officio ordinis regalis, idcirco Saul in eadem adhuc traditione posi- tum honorificat, ne Deo injuriam facere videretur, qui his ordinibus honorem decrevit. Dei enim imaginem habet rex, sicut et episcopus Christi. Quam- diu ergo in ea traditione est, honoran- dus est, si non propter se, vel propter ordinem. Unde Apostolus inquit, ^ Potestatibus sublimioribus subditi es- tote. Non est potestas, nisi a Deo : quse enim sunt, a Deo ordinatas sunt.* Hinc est utGtentilem, in potestate tamen positum, honorificemus, licet ipse in- dignus sit, qui Dei ordinem tenens gratias agit diabolo. Potestas enim exigit, quia meretur honorem. Nam ideo Pharaoni futuram famis somnium revelatum est : et Nabuchodonosor, aliis secum assistentibus, solus filium Dei vidit in camino ignis, non utique merito suo, qui in idolo se adorari vol^it, sed merito ordinis regalis."

  • Cathulfus in M. G. H. Epist.^vol.

iv. ; Ep. var. Car. Regn. Script., T.


A ^*






150 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART in.


century. In the last passage he also discusses the question of the conduct of David towards Saul, and there is considerable signif- icance in his discussion. He evidently thinks that the divine character of the office of kingship cannot be lost owing to any misconduct of the ruler. The sanctity of the office gives sanc- tity to any ruler, even though an idolater. It is clear that the writer is much influenced by the Jewish conception of kingship, but of this we shall have more to say presently.

We must, however, observe that in another of these " Quest- ions " the author seems to take up a somewhat different position. He evidently believes that there may be a wholly evil form of authority which is not from God, but it is extremely difficult to say what he understands this to be, and what is the test of its character. It does not appear to consist in its unjust character or actions, for the writer says expressly that a man sitting on the throne or chair of God may oppress the innocent ; and that we must then say that the judgment, but not the throne, is un- just.^ The phrases are very obscure, but may tend in some measure to qualify the judgment which we might have founded on the preceding passages. ' "VB^have then a theory that the ruler is the representative of


^ Pseudo Augustine, Qusest. Vet. et Novi Test., ex. : " Hanc dicimus cathedram pestilentise quae extra Dei ordiuationem est, ad hoc utique in- venta, ut iniqua exeant judicia: prse- terea pestilentise cathedra dicta est, quia est corruptio quae parit mor- tem, sicut et iniquitas danmationem. Non est ergo a Deo quae est cathedra mortis. Nam Moyses accepit cath- edram vitae. Ad hoc enim data est, ut auctoritas in ea sit juste judicis vel creatoris Del Unde dicit Dominus, ' Super cathedram Moysi sedunt Scribse et Phariseei ' : et Apostolus, ' non est ' inquit ' potestas nisi a Deo : quae enim sunt, a Deo ordinatso sunt." Unde dicit ad principem plebis : ' Tu quidem sedes iudicans secundum legem et contra legem jubes me percuti.' Quod dicit, * secundum l^em,' justam et salutarem cathedrae auctoritatem


significavit. Illud autem quod ait, ' contra legem jubes me percuti ' ilium ipsum injustum judicem ostendit, ut in Dei cathedra sedens judicaret in- juste. Hinc est unde et Daniel ' Dei est' ait 'regnum, et cui vult dabit illud.' Sicut enim terreni impera- toris auctoritas sic currit per onmes, ut in omnibus ejus sit reverentia; ita Deus instituit, ut ab ipso rege Dei auctoritas incipiat, et currat per cunctos : quamvis frequenter mundus hoc non intelligat, et aliis se subjiciat in potestate positis quam debet, tamen institutio est ut unus sit qui timeatur. Ubi ergo haec institutio non est, ibi cathedra pestilentiae reperitur. . . .

" Itaque si in Dei cathedra sedentes, innocentes opprimant, injustum erit indicium non cathedra. Ubi enim cathedra pestilentise est, non potest indicium non esse iniquum."






CHAP. XIII.] THE SACRED AUTHOEITY OF THE RULER. 151

God, and that whatever his conduct may be, he does not cease in some sense to have this character. St Augustine expresses ,, the same conception with a certain added emphasis. He men-^ tions Nero as an example of the worst type of ruler, but adds that even such rulers receive their power through the providence , of God, when he judges that any nation may require such governors.^ St Isidore of Seville expresses the same view, and even thinks it necessary to explain away a passage of Scripture which, as it appeared to him, might be interpreted as contradict- ing the theory. The prophet Hosea, as he quotes him, had said of certain kings that they reigned, but not by the appointment of God. St Isidore explains that this means that God had given them te their people in His anger. He quotes the same prophet as saying, " I shall give them a king in my wrath," and * concludes that a wicked ruler is appointed by God just as much as a good ruler. The character of the ruler is adapted to the character of the people : if they are good, God will give them a good ruler ; if they are evil, He will set an evil ruler over them.% How far St Augustine and St Isidore foresaw the conclusions that might be founded upon such statements it is difficult to say. St Augustine does not, so far as we have seen, discuss the question in detail; and St Isidore, as we shall see presently,


1 St Aug., De Civ. Dei, v. 19 : " Etiam talibufr tamen dominandi potesias non datur nisi summi Dei providentia, quando res humanas judicat talibus dominis dignas. Aperta de hac re vox divina est loquente Dei sapientia : ' Per me reges regnant et tyranni per me tenent terram.' Sed ne tyranni non pessimi atque improbi reges, sed vetere nomine fortes dicti existi- mentur (unde ait Virgilius: *Pars mihi pacis erit dextram tetigisse tyr- anni'), apertissime alio loco de Deo dictum est : * Qui regnare facit homi- nem hypocritam propter perversitatem pojmlL* Cf. De Civ., v. 21.

^>8t Isidore of Seville, Sententise, iii. 48 : " Dum Apostolus dicat ; non est potestas nisi a Deo,' quo modo Dominus per Prophetam de quibusdam


potestatibus dicit : * Ipsi regnaverunt, sed non ex me.' Quasi diceret, non me propitio sed etiam summe irato. Unde et inferius per eumdem prophetam ad- didit: 'Dabo,' inquit, 'tibi regem in furore meo.' Quo manifestius elucet bonam malamque potestatem a Deo ordinari; sed bonam propitio, malam irato. Reges, quando boni sunt, mun- eris est Dei, quando vero mali, sceleris est populL Secundum enim meritum plebium disponitur vita rectorum, test- ante Job, ' Qui regnare facit hypocritam propter peccatum populi.' Irascente enim Deo, talem rectorem populi sus- cipiunt, qualem pro peccato merentur. Nonnunquam pro malitia plebium etiam reges mutantur, et qui ante videbantur esse boni, accepto regno fiunt mali."






152 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.


evidently held, along with this view, others which have a some- what diflferent tendency.

The conclusions, however, which are not drawn out by St

Augustine and St Isidore are drawn out and stated with the

greatest emphasis by f^ frracnry thr frrrftt ^® ^^7 notice

first that he treats the relation of the evil ruler to God

in the same manner as St Augustine and St Isidore, and

fargues like them that a good ruler is God's reward to a good

/people, an evil ruler God's punishment on an evil people.

Whether, therefore, the ruler is good or evil, he must be rever-

^enced as one who derives his authority from God.^ But

Gregory the Great goes much further than this. Commenting

upon the conduct of David towards Saul, he points out how

David is said to have refused to lay his hand on the Lord's

/ anointed, and even to have repented that he cut off the hem of

I his garment. He takes Saul to stand for an evil ruler, and

I David for a good subject, and he interprets David's attitude as

signifying that good subjects will not even criticise rashly or

X violently the conduct even of bad rulers : for to resist or

^ offend against a ruler is to offend against God, who has set him

over men.* And lest we should take this to be an isolated


(3>t


^^^t Gregory the Great, Libri Mecalium in Job, xxv. 16.

wSt Gregory the Great, Regulso Pas- toralis, iii. 4 i " Admonendi sunt sub- diti, ne preepositorum suoruin vitam temere iudicent, si quid eos fortasse agere reprehensibiliter vident : ne unde mala recte redarguunt, inde per elationis impulsum in profundiora mergantur. Admonendi sunt, ne cum culpas prse- positorum considerant, contra eis au- daciores fiant, sed sic si qua valde sunt eorum prava, apud semetipsos dijudi- cant, ut tamen divino timore con- stricti ferre sub eis iugum reverentiae non recusent. Quod melius osten- dimus, si David factum ad medium deducamus (1 Sam. xxiv.) . . . Quid enim per Saul, nisi mali rectores : quid per David, nisi boni subditi desig- nanturt . . . Quern tamen David ferire metuit, quia pise subditorum mentes


ab omni se peste obtrectationis absti- nentes, prsepositorum vitam nuUo lin- guae gladio percutiunt, etiam cum de imperfectione reprehendunt. Qui etsi quando pro infirmitate sese ab- stinere vix possunt, ut extrema quae- damatqueexteriora praepositorum mala, sed tamen humiliter loquantur, quasi Oram chlamidis silenter incidunt : quia videlicet dum prselatae dignitati sal- tem innoxie et latenter derogant, quasi regis superpositi vestem foedant; sed tamen ad semetipsos redeunt, seque ve- hementissime vel de tenuissima verbi laceratione reprehendunt, Unde bene et illic scriptum est : " Post haec David percussit cor suum, eo quod abscidisset oram chlamidis Saul." Facta quippe praepositorum oris gladio ferienda non sunt, etiam cum recte reprehendenda iu- dicantur. Si quando vero contra eos vel in minimis lingua labitur, necesse est ut






CHAP. XIII.] THE SACRED AUTHORITY OP THE RULER. 15S

phrase, it is well to observe that he recurs to the matter in his treatise on the Book of Job.^ and restates the same view with an equal, perhaps even with slightly greater, emphasis.

There can be no doubt that we have here the doctrine of the sanctity and Divine a uthority of the ruler in a very t^trong form; even the seventeenth-cen tury apologists of_the Divine Eight hardly go further in preaching the necessity of obedience and the wickedness of resistance. It is from the doctrine of^ St Gregory the Great that the religious theory of the absolute and irresponsible authority of the ruler continually drew its strongest arguments, both in the Middle Ages and later. Other elements, no doubt, both of theory and of actual cir- cumstance, go to produce the later theory, but the authority of St Gregory the Great was a continual protection to those who maintained it.

It may be asked whether the conception of St Gregory the Great was an entirely abstract one, or whether it actually governed his conduct. We think that its influence can be traced, in some degree at least, in his actual relations with the Emperors. Knowing as we do the great force and capacity of Gregory the Great as an administrator, and the energy with which he defended and pushed forward what he considered to be the rights and authority of the Eoman See,

per afflictionem pcenitentiso cor prema- subjacent, facile judicare audeant facta

tur ; quatenus ad semetipsum redeat, rectorum, atque per hoc quod de his

et cum prsepositae potestati deliquerit, qui sibi prselati sunt murmurant, non

ejus contra se judicium a quo sibi prae- humano, sed ei qui cuncta disponit

lata est, perhorrescat. Nam cum divino ordini contradicant. Rlis nam-

preepositis delinquimus, ejus ordinationi que dicitur : ' Oves mese his quae con-

qui eos nobis prsetulit obviamus. Unde culcata pedibus vestris fuerant pasce-

Moyses quoque cum contra se et Aaron bantur, et quae pedes vestri turbaverant,

conqueri populum cognovisset, ait : haec bibebant.* Oves enim turbata

" Nos enim quid sumus ? Nee contra pedibus bibunt, cum subjecti ea ad

nos murmur vestrum, sed contra Do- exemplum vivendi appetunt quae prse-

mwum." lati quique pravo opere pervertunt. At

G/St Gregory the Great, Libri contra a prselatis hi audiunt : 'Nos

Moralium in Job, xxii. 24 : " Qua in enim, quid sumus ? Nee contra nos

re semper sollicita consideratione pen- est murmur vestrum, sed contra Do-

sandum est, ne aut hi qui praesunt minum.' Qui enim contra superposi-

exempla mali operis subjectis prsebeant, tam sibi potestatem murmurat, liquet

eorumque vitam suae gladio pravitatis quod ilium redarguit, qui eamdem

exstinguant: aut hi qui alieno regimini homini potestatem dedit."






^


154 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part m.

we cannot but be in some measure astonished at the ex- tremely deferential, sometimes almost servile, tone which we find, at least occasionally, in his letters to the Emperors. We may take as an example a letter addressed to, Aaatglins, the representative of the Eoman Church at Constantinople, with regard to the wish of the Emperor that John the Bishop of Prima Justiniana should be deposed on account of his bad health. Gregory protests against such action as being wholly contrary to the canons, and unjust, and says therefore that as far as he is concerned he can take no part in such action. But, he concludes, it is in the power of the Emperor to do what he pleases, — ^he must act according to his judgment: what the Emperor does, if it is canonical, Gregory will follow; if not canonical, he will, so far as he can. do so without sin, endure.^ The tone of the letter is not undignified, but it is a little strange to find Gregory even appearing to acquiesce in an open breach of canonical rule by the Emperor, especially when we remember that there was quite another tradition in the Western Church than this, as we shall presently see. Another example will be found in a letter written to the Emperor Maurice with regard to a law issued by him, for- bidding the reception in monasteries of soldiers and other persons who were responsible to discharge various public duties. Gregory is much distressed about the law, and begs \ Maurice to consider what emperor ever issued such a regu- J iation. (It appears from Ep. 64 in the same book that J Gregory believed that this had been done by Julian.) He urges that for some men salvation is only possible if they leave the world and give themselves wholly to religion, and he warns Maurice that Christ will in the last day demand

(J-' St Gregory the Great, Epist., Lib. Quod si hoc petere iUe noluerit quod

xi. 29, " Gregorius Anatolio Diacono piissimo domno placet, quicquid jubet

Constantinopolim :"... Et quidem facere, in ejus potestate est. Sicut

nusquam canones praecipiunt, ut pr86 novit, ipse provideat; nos tantum-

eegritudine episcopo succedatur, et modo in depositione talis viri non

omnino injustum est, ut si molestia faciat permisceri. Quod yero ipse

corporis inruit, honore suo privetur fecerit, si canonicum est, sequimur;

aegrotus. Atque ideo hoc per nos fieri si vero canonicum non est, in quan- ,

nullatenus potest, ne peccatum in mea turn sine peccato nostro portamus." ' anima ex ejus depositione veniat. . . .


%






CHAP. XIII.] THE SACRED AUTHORITY OP THE RULER. 155


from him an account of his conduct in having withdrawn 1 men from the service of Christ. And yet he concludes the letter by saying that, in obedience to the Emperor's com- mands, he has caused the law to be sent on to various regions. He has obeyed the Emperor, and has delivered his( soul by protesting.^ It is certainly strange to find Gregory, who feels so strongly the impiety of such a law, still acting as an agent for its promulgation, instead of refusing to do this in the name of the Christian law and his own ecclesiastical posi- tion. It is true that we must balance the tone of these letters with that of a later one addressed to,,gonifggp, the representative of the Eoman see at Constantinople, with reference to a question


^ St Gregory the Great, Epist., Lib. iii. 61, " Gregorius Mauri tio Augusto :" " LoDgino Tiro clarissimo stratore veni- ente, dominorum legem suscepi, ad quam fatigatuB tunc egritudine cor- poris, respondere ml Talui. In qua dominorum pietas sanxit, ut quisquis publicis administrationibuB fuerit im- plicatus, ei ad Ecclesiasticum officium venire non liceat. Quod valde laudavi, evidentissime sciens quia qui secul- arem habitum deserens, ad Ecdesias- tica officia venire festinat, mutare vu]t seculum, non relinquere. Quod vero in eadem lege dicitur, ut ei in monasterio converti non liceat, omnino miratus sum : ... In qua lege subiunctum est, ut nuUi qui in manu signatus est, converti Uceat. Quam constitutionem ego, fateor dom- inis meis, vehementer expavi. Quia per eam coelorum via multis clanditur, et quod nuncusque licuit, ne liceat prohibetur. Multi enim sunt, qui possunt religiosam vitam etiam cum sseculari habitu ducere. Et plerique sunt, qui nisi omnia reliquerint, salvari apud Deum nuUatenus possunt. Ego vero hsec dominis meis loquens, quid sum nisi pulvis et vermis ? Sed tamen quia contra auctorem omnium Deum banc intendere constitutionem sentio, dominis tacere non possum. Ad hoc enim potestas super omnes homines,


pietati dominorum meorum cselitus data est, ut qui bona appetunt ad- juventur ; ut ccelorum via largus pateat, ut terrestre regnum coelesti regno famuletur. Et ecce aperta voce dicitur, ut ei, qui semel in terrena militia signatus fuerit, nisi aut expleta militia, aut pro debilitate corporis re- pulsus, Christo militcure non liceat.

Ad hsec ecce per me servum ultimum suum et vestrum respondit Christus, dicens : ** Ego te de notario comitem ezcubitorum, de comite ezcubitorum csesarem, de csesare imperatorem : nee solum hoc, sed etiam patrem imperatorum feci. Sacerdotes meis tu88 manui commisi, et tu a meo servitio milites tuos subtrahis." Re- sponde rogo piissime domine, servo tuo, quid venienti et hsec dicenti re- sponsurus es in judicio Domino tuo? . . . Requirat rogo dominus mens, quis prior imperator talem legem dederit, et subtilius sestimet, si debuit dan. . . . Ego quidem jussioni subjectus eandem legem per diversas terrarum partes feci transmitti, et quia lex ipsa omnipotenti Deo minime concordet, ecce per suggestionis mesa paginam serenissimis dominis nuntiavi. Utro- bique ergo quae debui exolvi, qui et imperatori obedientiam prsebui, et pro Deo quod sensi minime tacui."






156 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [pART III.


of the jurisdiction of the Bishop of Corcyra. It appears from

this that the Emperor Maujice had given some decision upon

the subject, and Gregory speaks of this as wholly void, as being

'* contra leges et sacras canones!* The Bishop of Nicopolis, the

Metropolitan of Corcyra, had given a different judgment, to

which Gregory says he had given his approbation. But Gregory

adds that, as the Emperor Maurice had given a decision, he had

abstained from publishing his own decision lest he should appear

to act contrary to the imperial command and in contempt of jt

/He therefore instructs Boniface to do what he can to persuade

"^the Emperor to issue an order confirming the judgment of

jOregory.i Gregory's tone is very emphatic about the illegality

jind invalidity of the action of Maurice, but it must be observed

Cthat he carefully refrains from publicly denounciug it, and


^ St Gregory the Great, Epist., Lib. xiv. 8 : ". . . Hoc tamen breviter indicamus, quia dum Mauricio quondam imperatori esset in preejudicio Ec- clesiae Corcyritanae subreptum, nee jus- sio ejus, quippe quae contra leges et sac- ros canones data fuerat, habuisset effec- tum, et indecisa inter partes contentio remansisset : aliam illam ad Andream quondam fratrem nostrum tunc Nico- politanum metropolitam jussionem de- disse, ut, quoniam utraque pars ejus erat jurisdictioni subjecta, ipse banc causam coguoscere et finire canonice debuisset. Qui metropolita, cognita causa, prolataque sententia, cujus tibi ezemplaria misimus, prsedictum Cassiopi castrum sub potestate ac jurisdictione Corcyritani Episcopi cujus et semper fuit dioecesis, esse distinxit. Quam nos sententiam comprobantes, apostolicse Sedis auctoritate prsevidimus confirman- dum. . . . Sed quia inter ipsa prim- ordia serenissimo domno imperatori subreptum est, atque contra judicatum Nicopolitani metropolitse quod ecclesi- astica rectitudine et canonica ratione suffultum est, episcopo Euriae, quod nee sine dolore audire vel loqui sine gemitu possumus, cum majori injuria episcopi Corcyritan atque clericorum


ejus antefatum Cassiopi castrum tradi- tum memoratur, ut amota, quod dici grave est, jurisdictione Corcyritanse Ec- clesiae, ipse ilKc omnem tamquam prin- cipalem habeat potestatem, sententianl nostram nullidare praevidimus, ne contra jussionem clementissimi domni impera- toris vel, quod absit in despectu ip- sius aliquid facere videremur. Itaque dilectio tua pietati ejus cuncta diligen- ter insinuet, atque constanter astruat hoc omnino pravum, omnino injustum, omnino inlicitum, et sacris esse valde canonibus inimicum : et ideo hujusmodi peccatum temporibus suis introduci in Ecclesiae prsejudicium non permittat, sed quid de hoc negotio judicatum antefati quondam metropolitse con- tineat, vel qualiter a nobis ea quae ab illo decreta sunt, confirmata fuerint, sug- gerat, atque id agere studeat, ut cum ejus jussione nostra illic sententia trans- mittatur, quatenus et serenitati ipsius^ sicut dignum est, reservasse et rational- ibiter correxisse quae male praesumpta sunt videamur. Qua in re onmino opera danda est ut, si fieri potest, etiam ipse jussionem tribuat, in qua ea quae a nobis definita sunt servari prsecipiat."






CHAP. XIII.] THE SACRED AUTHORITY OP THE RULER. 157

setting his own judgment, or that of the MetropoKtan, against / it; and hopes to gain his point by persuading the Emperor \ to agree with his judgment and to issue an order expressing this.

In Gregory the Great, then, we find this theory of the sacred character of government so developed as to make the ruler in^ «  all his actions the representative of God, not merely the repre- sentative of God as embodying the sacred ends for which the government of society exists. The conception is, so far as we have seen, almost peculiar to some Christian writers. We have not observed anything which is really parallel to the conception in the legal writers, and even in Seneca and Pliny we have only indications of an attitude of mind which might be capable of development in this direction. The theory is a somewhat irregular and illogical development of the Christian conception of the divine character of the civil order.

It will naturally be asked, What were the circumstances under which this theory grew up. We think that we can trace the development of this conception to three causes : first, the ^^ need of correcting that anarchical tendency in the primitive - Church to which we have already referred ; secondly, the relation between the Christian Church and the Emperor after the conversion of Constantine; and, thirdly, the influence of the Old Testament conception of the position of the King of • Israel. J

We think that the necessity for counteracting the anarchical tendencies in the primitive Christian societies was probably a very real cause of the tendency to exaggerate or misstate the J divine authority of the ruler. We think that the great emphasis laid upon the sacred character of the civil order in the New Testament — an emphasis which is maintained by writers like Clement of Eome and Irenseus — is a very real indication of a danger which menaced the Church, and led naturally to just the same kind of exaggeration as did the parallel phenomena in the sixteenth century. If we add to this the imperious need which lay on the Christian societies to disarm the hostility of the Empire, we shall, it seems to us, find one reasonable explana-






158 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [pART in.

tion of the tendency to overstate the sanctity of authority in the earliest ages of the Church.

With the conversion of the Empire to Christianity no doubt these conditions were greatly altered. But while, as we shall see presently, many of the Christian writers from the fourth to the seventh centuries illustrate conceptions of quite another kind from those which we have just discussed, yet in this period, too, there were continually in operation circumstances which tended to make the attitude of the Church towards the Emperors one of a somewhat servile deference. We may find an extremely good illustration of the influence of these circumstances in that pass- age from St Optatus ^ which we have already considered. In the

O case of the Donatist dispute the Empire at last exercised its authority to put down what it considered a schismatical faction. I And it is easy to see from the tone of St Optatus that this in- tervention was unhappily as welcome to many Churchmen as it was distasteful to the Donatists.^ Donatus urged that the Emperor had nothing to do with Church afiairs ; St Optatus bids him remember that the Church is within the Empire, and that

' Hhe Einperor has no superior save God. The truth is, that with the conversion of Constantine the Emperor became the patron ^and protector of the Church, and it would be easy enough to trace in many cases the effect of this protectorate on the course of Church disputes. Churchmen would resist the Emperor when he happened to be opposed to their view ; but when he agreed with them, they were only too apt to fall into the habit of regarding his action against their enemies as that of a truly sacred authority. The emancipation of the political theory of the Church from such conceptions as those of Gregory the Great must be traced in large measure to the actual contests between the Church and the Empire.

It is, however, possible that these influences would not alone have been sufficient to produce so rigorous a theory as that of Gregory the Great, had they not been reinforced and confirmed by traditions which the Christian Church inherited from the

^ See p. 148. property of the Donatists, which we

2 Cf. the temper of St Augustine have already considered. See pp. 140, as illustrated in the passages on the 141.






CHAP. XIII.] THE SACRED AUTHORITY OF THE RULER. 15&

religion of Israel. We can hardly doubt that, directly, the theories of St Augustine and St Isidore on the Divine appoint- ment of even wicked rulers, and St Gregory's theory of the duty I of submission even to such rulers, are drawn from the Oldj Testament conception of the position of the king of Israel J According to the tradition of the first Book of Samuel, the monarchy was indeed instituted against the advice of the prophet, who is taken as speaking in the name of God; but the narrative of the same book and of the other historical books makes it very plain that the king, when once appointed, was looked upon as the anointed of the Lord, — that his person and his authority were sacred. There may, indeed, be traces in the Old Testament of other views than this, but this is the normal view of the monarchy in Israel, a view which possessed no doubt a special force with regard to the monarchy of the house of David. Such conceptions with regard to the sanctity of monarchy were probably in no way peculiar to Israel, buti belonged to many oriental nations ; but it was largely through) the Christian Fathers that they came into the West. The', passages to which we have referred will make it suflficiently plain that it is in relation to the Old Testament that these views are developed by the Fathers. We may at least reason- ably say that the tradition of Israel provided the centre round whigh such opinions took definite shape and form. fin St Gregory the Great, then, we find in definite and systematic form a theory of the source of authority in Govern- ment which is very sharply contrasted with that which we have i seen to be characteristic of the Iggal^riter^. They trace the source of all authority in the State to its fountainhead in the people. St Gregory traces the authority of rulers directly to God. The history of mediaeval political theory is very largely the history of the struggle between these two views, in which^ however, for many centuries, the combatants change places. For, at least from the eleventh to the fourteenth century, it is the Imperialist party which defends the theory of the Divine authority of the ruler, it is the ecclesiastical which maintains that his authority is derived from the peo ple. } We have to consider how it was that this change took place, and to do






160 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.

this we shall have to examine in detail the history of the political ideas especially of the ninth century.

But before we proceed to do this we have still to examine some other tendencies of thought in the Christian Fathers. We shall see that besides that tradition which we have so far been examining, there are others which, as we think, greatly influenced the political theory of the ninth century.






161


CHAPTEK XIV.

AUTHORITY AKD JUSTICE.

So far we have endeavoured to disentangle the history and significance of a political conception, which, as it appears to us, was first, in Western thought, developed by the Christian \ Fathers, — the conception of the Divine authority of the ruler, \ the doctrine that the ruler is absolute relatively to his subjects, \ responsible only to God. It would, however, be a great mistake ' to suppose that this theory represents the whole contribution of the Christian Fathers to this portion of political theory. There are many other elements in their conception of the nature of authority in the State ; one or two of the great Fathers, indeed, seem to tend in quite another direction, and with regard to them all it must be recognised that the elements of their theory on this matter are highly complex, perha ps a littl e confused-.. We must consider some general aspects of their thought, arranging them as well as we can.

While the Christian Fathers as a rule think that the institu- tion of coercive Government is not primitive or natural, in that aense, they look upon the institution as being good, inasmuch as it is a remedy for the confusions and disorder which sin has brought into the world. It is true, as we have seen, that they sometimes think of it as being a punishment as well as a remedy for sin ; but, normally, they think of the State as an instrument for securing and preserving justice, and they • regard it as the chief duty of the king as ruler to benefit his people by maintaining justice. We have already observed that i St Paul's assertion of the Divine character of the authority of the State rests upon the assumption that the State rewards

VOL. I. L






162 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART m.

the good and punishes the evil, — that is, that it maintains justice.^

In the second century we find Irenseus in very plain terms threatening unjust rulers with the judgment of God, assur- ing them that God will certainly visit their wickedness upon them;^ and if we turn to the Alexandrian Fathers, we find Clement defining a king as one who rules according to law, and who is willingly obeyed by his subjects,^ — that is, if we may so interpret Clement's meaning, a king is one who follows not merely his own caprice or desire, but governs according to those rules of public action which are designed for the attainment and preservation of justice, and whom his subjects willingly obey as representing their own just desires.

When we pass to St Ambrose in the latter part of the fourth century, we find all these conceptions drawn out and developed very clearly and fully. To St Ambrose justice and beneficence form the " ratio " of the State : * justice is that which builds up the State, while injustice destroys it^ This conception is very significant, especially when we compare it, as we shall have to

V do presently, with St Augustine's attempt to define the State ;

1 and it finds its proper development in the discussion of the relation of the unjust person who discharges an office of Govern- ment, to the sacred character of the institution of Government itself. St Ambrose seems to mean that he only is properly the

I minister of God who uses his authority well:^ the passage is, indeed, somewhat obscure, but that seems to be his meaning.

^ Rom. xiii. 1, &c. '* Claret ergo quoniam et aequitas im-

^ Irenseus, Adv. Hser., v. 24. peria confirmet, et injustitia dissolvat.

' Clement of Alexandria, Stromata, ^ St Ambrose, Exp. Ev. S. Lucse iv.

i. 24 : " fittff i\ths rolwy i<rr\y 6 Apx^f 5 ; " Denique eo usque a Deo ordinatio

Karh p6fiovs, 6 t^k tow ipx^"' Mvtmw poteetatis ; ut Dei minister sit, qui bene

hrurrtitinv Ix*"'*" utitur potestate. *Dei* inquit, *min-

  • St Ambrose, De Offidis, i. 28: ister est tibi in bonum.' Non ergo

" Justitia ergo ad societatem generis muneris aliqua culpa est, sed miniatri ;

humani, et ad communitatem refertur. nee Dei potest ordinatio displicere, sed

Sodetatis enim ratio dividitur in duas administrantis actio. Nam ut de

partes, justitiam et beneficentiam, coelestibus ad terrena derivemus ex-

quam eamdem liberalitatem et benig- emplimi, dat honorem imperator, et

nitatem yocant ; justitia mihi excelsior habet laudem. Quod si quia male

videtur, liberalitas gratior." honore usus fuerit, non imperatoris est

' St Ambrose, De Off., ii 19 ; culpa, sed judicis."






CHAP. XIV.] AUTHORITY AND JUSTICE. 163

• But this is not all that is worth observing in St Ambrose's theory of the institution of Qovernment. It is interesting to notice that h^ lays some stress upon the attitude of the ruler towards liberty. In a letter to Theodosius, on the subject of certain demands which had been made upon the Church, and against which St Ambrose protests, he urges the importance of the permission of freedom of speech and remonstrance; / and while, no doubt, he is thinking primarily ot the freedom of ecclesiastics in relation to the civil power, he shows some sense of the significance of the conception of liberty in the political order: good rulers, he says, love liberty, while bad 1 rulers love slavery.^ It would of course be very foolish to lay too much stress on such phrases ; but they are at least worth noting, especially as similar phrases are used both by Cassio- dorus and by Gregory the Great. Cassiodorus, writing in the name of Athalaric to a certain Ambrose who had just been ap- pointed to the qusestorship, recalls a saying of Trajan, in which he had expressed his wish that his counsellors should freely advise him, rebuking him if necessary.^ Gregory the Great, in a letter not perhaps very creditable to him, in which he expressed to the Emperor Phocas his joy that he had taken the place of Maurice, hails his accession as promising to restore liberty to the people in his dominions, adding that this is the great difference between the emperors of the Commonwealth and the kings of the nations, that the former are the lords of free men, the latter of slaves,*

In later times St Ambrose was frequently quoted as

  • St Ambrose, Ep. xL 2 : " Sed neque ^ Cassiodorus, Varia, viu. 13 : "Re-

imperiale est libertatem dicendi dene- novamus oerte dictum illud celeberrimi

gare, neque sacerdotale quod sentias Trajani ; sume dictationem, si bonus

non dicere. Nihil enim in vobis imper- f uero, pro republica et me, si malus,

tatoribus tam popularis et tam amabilis pro republica in me."

•est, quam libertatem etiam in iis dili- ^ St Greg, the Great, Ep. xiii. 34 ;

gere, qui obsequio militise vobis subditi " Reformetur jam singulis sub jugo

43unt. Siquidem hoc interest inter pii imperii libertas sua. Hoc namque

bonos et malos principes, quod boni inter reges gentium et reipublicas im-

libertatem amant, servitutem im- peratores distat, quod reges gentium

probL Nihil etiam in sacerdote tam domini servorum simt, imperatores vero

periculosum apud Deum, tam turpe reipublicse, domini liberorum." The

Apud homines, quam quod seutiat, non same phrase occurs in Ep. xi. 4 : per-

libere denuntiare." haps it is a quotation.






164 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.


maintaining that the king or ruler is bound by the laws ; and, indeed, there is more than one passage which would seem to have this meaning. In one of his letters he seems to \ argue that the emperor who makes the laws is also bound to obey them ; ^ and in one of his treatises he seems to express an opinion of the same kind.^ It mu^t, however, be obsetved that in other places he uses the ordinary legal phrase, that the emperor is legibus solutus.^ It is worth observing that St Augustine also deals with the relation of the ruler to the law in terms analogous* to those of St Ambrose, and, in later times, is much quoted with St Ambrose. St Isidore of Seville also urges very strongly upon the prince the propriety of his respe cting his own laws. Subjects will learn obedience when they see their rulers ob se rving the laws.^

With some parts of St Augustine's theory of the State we have already dealt; but St Augustine's theory has a certain completeness which we do not find in that of the other Fathers, and, at the risk of a little repetition, we think it well to try to consider briefly his theory of law and the State as a whole. We have already seen that in St Augustine's view men were


1 St Ambrose, Ep. xxL 9 : ** Ubi iUud constituimus, imperator, quod jam ipse tuum judicium declarasti ; immo etiam dedisti leges, nee cui esset liberum aliud judicare? Quod cum prescripsisti aliis, prescripsisti et tibi. Leges enim imperator fert, quas primus ipse custodiat;"

2 St Ambrose, Apol. Alt. Proph. Daniel, iii. : " Quem mihi hujuscemodi reperias virum qui in potestate con- stitutus non magis peccata sua diligat . . . qui se legibus obstringat suis, et quod per justitiam non licet, nee per potestatem licere agnoscat ? Non enim solvit potestas justitiam, sed justitia potestatem; nee legibus rex solutus est, sed leges suo soMt exemplo. An fieri potest, ut qui de aliis judicat, suo ipse sit liber judicio, et in se suscipiat, in quo et alios astringat ? "

  • St Ambrose, Apol. Prophet Daniel,

xvi : * * Quamvis rex legibus absolutus" ;


and in the same work, x. : ** Sequitur, 'Tibi soli peccavi,' Rex utique erat, nullis ipse legibus tenebatur, quia liberi simt reges a vinculis delictorum ; neque enim ullis ad poenam vocantur legibus, tuti sub imperii potestate."

  • St Aug., De Vera Religione, 31 :

Sicut in istis temporalibus legibus, quanquam de his homines iudicent, cum eas instituunt, tamen cum fuer- int institutse atque firmatse, non licebit judici de ipsis judicare sed secundum ip^s."

OlSk Isidore of Seville, Sent. iii. 61 : "Justum est principem legibus ob- temperare suis. Tunc enim jura sua ab omnibus custodienda existimet, quando et ipse illis reverentiam prsebet. Prin- cipea legibus tenere suis, neque in se posse damnare jura quae in subjectis constituunt. Justa est enim vocia eorum auctoritas, si quod populis prohibent, sibi licere non patiantur."






<?HAP. XIV.] , AUTHORITY AND JUSTICE. 165

originally equal, and that the institutions of slavery and govern-'N ment, in which one man is the superior of another, are conse-^ quences of man's sin.. The subjection of man to man is a punishment and a remedy for sin. It must be remembered, however, that this does not mean that men were by nature solitary. On the contrary, as we have already pointed out, St Augustine definitely maintains that by his own nature man is driven to seek the society of his fellow-men ; society is natural and primitive. It is the organised society of the State, with its coercive government and its authority of man over his fellow- men, which is a conventional institution, and it may be regarded partly as punitive, partly as remedial.^

It is important, therefore, to consider how St Augustine defines the State and what is its relation to justice. In the second book of the * De Civitate Dei ' he gives an account of the discussion of the nature of the State in Cicero's * De Republica,* and quotes the definition of Scipio: Popjilum autem non omnem coetum multitudinis, sed ccetum juris consensu et utilit- atis communione sociatum esse determinat," ^ but postpones the discussion of the definition. We find this discussion in the nineteenth book. Here, after restating Cicero's definition, he explains that this means that there can be no true State without justice : when there is not justice there can be no , jus. But, he objects, how can you speak of justice among men who do not serve God? What sort of justice is this to take men from the service of God and to subject them to demons ? There is no justice in men who do such things, and there can therefore be no justice in a society lormed of such men.^ This definition, then, will not work, and he proceeds to

^ St Aug., De Civ. Dei, zix. 12 and est esse. Quod enim jure fit, pro-

15. See pp. 125, 126. fecto juste fit ; quod autem fit injuste,

2 St Aug., De Civ. Dei, ii. 21. nee jure fieri potest. Non enim jura

  • St Aug., De Civ. Dei, xix. 21 : dicenda sunt vel putanda iniqua

Populum enim esse definivit coetum hominum constituta, cum iUud etiam

multitudinis juris consensu et utilitatis ipsi jus esse dicant, quod de justitiae

communione sociatum. Quid autem f onte manaverit, falsumque esse, quod

dicat juris consensum, disputando ex- a quibusdam non recte sentientibus

plicat, per hoc ostendens geri sine jus- dici solet, id esse jus, quod ei, qui

titia non posse rem publicam ; ubi plus potest, utile est. Quocirca ubi

ergo justitia vera non est> nee jus pot- non est vera justitia, juris consensu






166 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART ni.


/


search for some other definition which may make it possible to admit that Bome had been a true State. This is given in a later chapter of the same book, and is as follows : " Populus est coetus multitudinis rationalis rernm quas diligit concordi com- munione sociatus." A State may be more or less corrupt, but so long as it consists of a multitude of rational beings associated together in the harmonious enjoyment of that which they love, St Augustine thinks it may be regarded as a State or Commonwealth.^ This is practically Cicero's definition, but with the elements of law and justice left out. No more fun- damental difference could very well be imagined, although St Augustine seems to take the matter lightly ; for Cicero's whole conception of the State turns upon this principle, that it is a means for attaining and preserving justice.


Bociatus coetus homiDum non potest esse, et ideo nee populus juxta, illam Scipionis vel Ciceronis definitionem ; et si non populus, nee res populi, sed qualiscumque multitudinis, quae populi nomine non digna est. Ac per hoc, si res publica res est populi, et popu- lus non est, qui consensu non sociatus est juris, non est autem jus, ubi nulla justitia : procul dubio colligitur, ubi jusUtia non est, non esse rem pub- licam. Justitia porro ea virtus est, quse sua cuique distribuit. Quae igitur justitia est hominis, quse ipsum homi- nem Deo vero tollit et immundis dsemonibus subdit? Hocine est sua cuique distribuere. . . . Qua propter ubi homo Deum non serrit, quid in eo putandus est esse justitise ? Quando quidem Deo non serviens nuUo modo potest juste animus corpori aut humana ratio Titiis imperare. Et si in homine tali non est uUa justitia, procul dubio nee in hominum coetu, qui ex homi- nibus talibus constat. Non est hie ergo juris iUe consensus, qui hominum multitudinem populum facit, cujus res dicitur esse respublica." Cf. St Aug., De Civ. Dei, ii 21, conclusion.

' St Aug., De Civ. Dei, xix. 24 : " Si autem populus non isto, sed alio defini-


atur modo, velut si dicatur : * Populus est coetus multitudinis rationalis rerum quas diligit concordi communione soci- atus,' profecto, ut videatur qualis quis- que populus sit, ilia sunt intuenda quae diligit. Qusecumque tamen diligat, si coetus est multitudinis non pecorum, sed rationalium creaturarum et eorum quse diligit concordi communione sociatus est, non absurde populus nuncupatur ; tanto utique melior, quanto in melior- ibus, tantoque deterior, quanto est in deterioribus concors. Secundum istam definitionem nostram Romanus populus populus est et res ejus sine dubitatione respublica. Quid autem primis tem- poribus suis quidve sequentibus popu- lus iUe dilexerit et quibus moribus ad cruentissimas seditiones atque inde ad socialia atque civilia bella perveni* ens ipsam concordiam, quse salus est quodam modo populi, ruperit atque corruperit, testatur historia ; de qua in prsecedentibus libris multa posuimus. Nee ideo tamen vel ipsum non esse populum vel ejus rem dixerimus non esse rem publicam, quamdiu manet qualiscumque rationalis multitudinis coetus, rerum quas diligit concordi communione sociatus."






CHAP. XIV.] AUTHORITY AND JUSTICE. 167

This definition does not seem to represent a casual or isolated judgment of St Augustine, corrected perhaps at other times. He does not, indeed, so far as we have seen, formally set out to define the nature of the State in any other place, but he alludes to the matter more than once, and always in the same sense. In one letter he says : "What is a State (civitas) but a multitude of men, brought together into some bond of agreement ? " ^ and again, in another letter, " A State is nothing else but a harmoni- ous multitude of men " ; ^ and again, in one of his treatises, he ui^es that every one must recognise the importance of the order of the State, which coerces even sinnete into the bond of some earthly peace.* These phrases would not, if they stood alone, be sufficient to make clear St Augustine's conception of the State; but when taken with the definition which we have just considered, they seem to indicate that his omissions from Cicero's definition are not accidental, but more or less delib- erate and considered. ^

It must at the same time be recognised that once at least St Augustine uses a phrase which would seem to point in another direction. In the 'De Civitate,' after discussing the comparative advantages of great dominions, and of living in peace and goodwill with one's neighbours, he draws out a comparison between a band of robbers or pirates and a kingdom, and seems to mean that the only ^oint of distinction is that the latter has the quality of justice.* Here at least St Augustine expresses himself in the terms of Cicero's conception of the State. And with this passage we may compare a definition which is obviously closely related to that of Cicero,— npthing can be properly called Jtts which is unjust ;* and an interesting

1 St Aug., £p. cxxxviii. 2 : " Quid est paucis recte laudabiliterque vivatur ; autem civitas, nisi multitudo hominum quantumque valeat ordo reipublicse, in in quoddam vinculum redactum con- cujusdam pacis terrense vinculum cordise?" coercens etiam peccatores."

2 Id., Ep. dv. 3 : " Cum aliudcivitas * Id., De Civ. Dei, iv. 4 : "Remota non sit, quam concors hominum midti- itaque justitia quid sunt regna nisi tudo." magna latrocinia? quia et latrocinia

3 Id., De Genesi ad Litteram, ix. iz : quid sunt nisi parva regna ? "

" An vero ita quis csecus est mente, ut ^ Id., Enarr. in Ps. cxlv. 15 : " Jus

non oemat quanto terris omamento et injuria contraria sunt. Jus enim sit genus humanum, etiam cum a est quod justum est. Neque enim






168 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part im

passage, in which St Augustine describes the characteristics of justice in language taken, in the main, from Cicero's treatise, " De Inventione," but which in part also suggests the definitions of Ulpian.^ These definitions of justice, however, only show that St Augustine follows the general tradition of the relations of law and justice, and the nature of civil justice.

The first mentioned phrase is, as far as we have seen, isolated, and can hardly be cited in correction of the deliberate and con* sidered omission of the quality of justice in his formal definition of the State. It must, at the same time, be recognised that St Augustine is compelled to abstract the quality of justice from the definition of the State, not by any course of reflec- tion upon the nature of the State, but by his theological con* ception of justice, — a conception which might be regarded as true upon his premisses, but which can only be understood as related to those premisses.

We cannot express a decided judgment upon the very inter-


omne quod jus dicitur, jus est. Quid si aliquis condat jus iniquum ? Nee jus dicendum est, si injustum est. lUud ergo verum jus, quod etiam justum est. Vide quid feceris, non quid patiaris. Si jus fecisti, injuriam patens : si injuriam fecisti jus pateris."

— Cf. with Cicero in De Civ. Dei,

xix. 21.

^ De Div. .'Quaest., xxxi: Justitia est habitus animi, communi utili- tate conservata, suam cuique tribuens dignitatem. Ejus initium est ab natura profectum : deinde qusedam in consuetudinem ex utilitatis ratione venerunt : postea res et ab natura profectas et a consuetudine probatas, legum metus et religio sanxit. Natura jus est, quod non opinio genuit. Bed qusedam innata vis inseruit, ut religionem, pietatem, gratiam, vindica- tionem, observantiam, veritatem. Re- ligio est quae superioris cujusdam naturae, quam divinam yocant, curam ceremoniamque afifert. Pietas, per quam sanguine conjunctis patriaeque benevoleos officium, et diligens tribui-


tur cultus. Gratia, in qua amicitiarum et oflBciorum, alterius memoria, et alter- ius remunerandi voluntas continetur. Vindicatio, per quam vis aut injuria, et omnino omne quod obfuturum est, defendendo et ulciscendo propulsatur. Observantia, per quam homines aliqua dignitate antecellentes, cultu quodam et honore dignamur. Veritas per quam immutata ea quae sunt aut fuerunt aut futura sunt dicimtur. Consuetudine autem jus est quod aut leviter a natura tractum aluit, et majus fecit usus, ut religionem ; et si quid eorum quae ante diximus a natura profectum, majus factum propter con- suetudinem videmus : aut quod in morem vetustas vulgi approbatione perduxit. Quod genus pactum est, par, lex, judicatum. Pactum est quod inter aliquos convenit. Par, quod in omnes aequale est. Judicatum, de quo alicujus aut aliquorum jam sententiis constitutum est. Lege jus est, quod in eo Bcripto, quod populo expositum est ut observet, continetur."






CHAP. XIV.] AUTHORITY AND JUSTICE* 169

esting question whether St Augustine's definition of the State exercised any great influence upon the course of political specu- lation. We have not found that this part of his work is often cited ; indeed, we have not come across any instance of this in the earlier Middle Ages at all. But it is hardly possible to escape the impression that, however indirectly, this attitude of St Augustine towards the conception of justice in society is related to that conception of the unrestricted authority of the ruler, which, as we have already seen, takes shape about this period, and was drawn out so sharply by St Gregory the Great As we have already seen, the tendency to confuse between the Divine authority of the institution of government, and the Divine authority of the individual ruler, can be traced back to very early Christian writers, but in St Augustine this tendency is very much developed. We have already quoted one passage from his writings which illustrates this point,^ but it will be useful to cite some other passages in which he draws out in detail his view that the worst, just as much as the best, kings draw their authority from God Himself.^ We have already seen that it is out of this judgment that there grows the dogmatic conception of Gregory the Great, that the ruler must not under any circumstances be resisted. The references to the subject in St Augustine are too scanty to enable us to form a very complete theory of the matter; but, so far as they go, we should be inclined to suggest that there is some real connec-

^ Seep. 151. chaeos, 32: "*A Deo esse et ipsam 2 St Aug., De Civ. Dei, v. 21 : " Quae nocendi potestatem.* Item quia etiam cum ita sint, non tribuamus dandi regni nocentium potestas non est nisi a Deo, atque imperii potestatem nisi Deo vero, sic scriptum est, loquente sapientia : qui dat felicitatem in regno ccelorum * Per me reges regnant, et tyranni per solis piis ; regnum vero terrarum et me tenent terram.' Dicit et apofe- piis et impiis, sicut ei placet, cui nihil tolus : ^ Non est potestas nisi a Deo.' injuste placet. . . . Sic etiam homini- Digne autem fieri, in libro Job scrip- bus, qui Mario ipse Qaio Csesari ; qui turn est : ' qui regnare facit ' inquit Augusix), ipse et Neroni ; qui Vespasia- * hominem hypocritam, propter perver- nis, vel patri vel filio, suavissimis sitatem populi.' £t de populo Israel imperatoribus, ipse et Domitiano dicat Deus. *Dedi eis regem in ira crudelissimo ; et ne per singulos ire mea.' Injustum enim non est ut im- necesse sit, qui Constantino Christiano, probis accipientibus nocendi potes- ipse apostatso Juliano." tatem, et bonorum patientia probetur^ Id., De Katura Boni contra Mani- et malorum iniquitas puniatur."






170 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.

i tion between a theory of the State which deliberately omits the characteristic of justice, and the theory that the ruler, whether just or unjust, must in all cases be looked on as holding God's authority. It would appear, then, that the political theory of St Augustine is materially different in several respects from that of St Ambrose and other Fathers, who represent the ancient tradition that justice is the essential

I quality, as it is also the end, of the State.

We have still to consider two Christian writers of the fifth and seventh centuries who seem to represent the more normal conception of the subject. The first of these writers, gasaiodorus, does not indeed furnish us with any detailed definition of the nature of the State, and he uses phrases which are sometimes ambiguous, but he does in the main seem to present the same judgment as that of St Ambrose, on the importance of justice in the State. He defines justice very much in the terms of

( Ulpian, as that habit of mind which renders his own to every man;^ he recognises that it is this which truly magnifies the ruler, and causes the State to prosper ;2 and he exhorts the ministers of State to just conduct, as that which alone renders them worthy of the name of judge.^ Law is the true instru^ ment of social progress, the true method of human happiness, and this because law represents justice.* He quotes the great passage from St Paul on the authority of the ruler, with an interesting comment, pointing out that the ruler is God's minister to secure justice;^ and, as we have seen, he describes the character of the good prince as that of one who is always ready to hear those who speak in the name of justice, and who delights in a counsellor who will always speak for the State, even when he has to criticise the ruler to

^ Cassiodorus, De Anima, 5. a Deo datur, et Deo videtur velle

^ Cass., Varia, iv. 12, and iii. 34. resistere qui ordinationi judiciarise

' Cass., Varia, iiL 27. nititur obviare, dicens ab eo propter

^ Cass., Varia, iii. 17, iv. 33, v. 39. conscientiam rationabiliter formidari,

  • Cass., * Complexiones, in Epist, qui in aliquo facinore probatur involvi ;

Apost.,' Rom. xiiL 1 : " Omnibus ideo enim et tributa solvimus, quia

potestatibus sublimioribus subditi nos principibus subjectos esse sentimus ;

estote"; et reliqua. Omnibus potes- ministri enim Dei sunt, cum crimina

tatibus justitiam praecipientibus dixit commissa distringunt.

esse debere subjectos, quoniam potestas






CHAP.


XIV.]


AUTHORITY AND JUSTICE.


171


his face.^ The true king is one who can govern and control himself.2

On the other hand, Cassiodorus seems to regard the king not only as the source of law, but as one who normally stands above it : the king feels himself bound by his own pietas when he is not bound by anything else;^ and further, the king is only accountable to God — he may transgress against Him, but cannot be said to sin against others, for there is none who can judge him.* It is, however, possible to interpret this last passage as merely representing the legal theory as to the ruler being legihis solutus and the constitutional conditions which provided no court of justice to which the king was accountable. These phrases of Cassiodorus are interesting, but do not add much to what we have already seen in other Christian writers.

St Isidore of Seville presents us with some of the same am^ biguities as Cassiodorus, but his treatment of the subject of the nature of Government is on the whole clear. He gives us very briefly a statement of the beginnings of social life among men.


^ Cass., Varia, viii 13. *Ambrosio, v. i., qusestori Atbalaricus Rex' : '*Ecce iterum ad qusesturam eminens evenit ingenio. Redde nunc Plinium et sume Trajanum. Habes magna quse dicas, si et tu simili oratione resplendeas. Fama temporum de legitima atque eloquent! jussione generatur. Omnia si quidem bona cumulat lingua diserta et quod a nobis prsecipitur, gratia dictantis omatur. Esto nobis ad bona suggerenda promptissimus et adversum improbitatem male prsesumentium constanter erectus. Die etiam auribus nostris quod est omnino pro nobis. Bonus princeps ille est, cui licet pro justitia loqui, et contra tyrannicsD feri- tatis indicium audire nolle constituta Teterum sanctionum. Renovamus cei*te dictum illud celeberrimum Trajani : sume dictationem, si bonus fuero, pro republica et me, si malus, pro re- publica in me. Sed vide quid a te quseramus, quando nee nobis aliquid injustum licere permittimus. Decreta ergo nostra priscorum resonent consti-


tuta, qu8Q tantam suavitatem laudis inveniunt, quantum saporem vetus- tatis assumimt. Prsejudicia, quae nos horremus, in aliis non amamus. Obligamus te certe generalitati, dum absolute prsecipimus jura servare. . . . Nam quid tibi conveniat, vides. Vox legum diceris, dum nos jura con- damns."

^ Cass., Exp. in Psalt., Ps. cxxxviL 5.

' Cass., Varia, x. 16 : " Imperiosa nimium res est, patres conscripti, pietas nostra, quando propria voluntate Tincimur, qui alienis condicionibus non tenemur. Nam cum deo prses- tante possimus omnia, sola nobis credimus licere laudanda."

4 Cass., Exp. in Psalt., Ps. 1. 5 : "Nunc ad exponenda verba redeamus. De populo si quia erraverit, et Deo peccat, et regi. Nam quando rex delinquit, soli Deo reus est, quia hominem non habet qui ejus facta dijudicet. Merito ergo rex Deo tantum se dixit peccasse, quia solus erat qui ejus potuisset admissa discutere.'*






172 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [pa^t im

« 

In his definition of oppidum he says that men were originally naked and unarmed, defenceless against the inclemency of heat and cold, and the attacks of wild beasts and of other men. At last they learned to make for themselves huts in which they might be sheltered and safe, and these were graduaUy collected in towns.^ But much more important than this is his definition of the nature of the State. He defines dvitas as a multitude of men joined together by the bond of soc iety : ^ this is ambiguous, and he might be following St Augustine; but his definition of popidvs makes his meaning plain. Popvlu s he defines as a multitude of men joined together in society by an agreement of law , and harmonious fellowship .^ It is both interesting and important to see that St Isidore, whether in^ tentionally or not, goes back from the position of St Augustine to that of Cicero, and makes justice an essential part of th e nature of the State.

St Isidore carries out a conception of the same kind in h is definition of the true king and the sharp contrast he draws .bet ween him and the ty rant ^ejking^jie^says^ derives his name from his function of ruling, and to rule means to correct r ii the king does what is right he will keepjiis namejif Jie does evil he will lose i t. St Isidore quotes an old proverb which i5ajs, "Thou shalt be king if thou d()_rightj_ if not, thou shalt not be king," and he defines the chief virtues of a king as J us tice and Fietas. ^ With this definition is sharply con-

^ St Isidore of Seville, Etym., xv. 2 : Haec est origo oppidorum, quae quod

  • ' Oppidum quidam ab oppositione opem darent, idcirco oppida nominata

murorum dixerunt: alii ab opibus dixerunt."

recondendis, eo quod sit munitum : ^ g^^ Isidore of Seville, Etym., xv,

alii quod sibi in eo couventus habi- ^ : " Civitas est hominum multitude

tantium opem det mutuam contra societatis vinculo adunata."

hostem. Nam primum homines tam- ^ St Isidore of Seville, Etym., ix. 4 :

quam nudi et inermes, nee contra "Populus est coetus humanse multi-

beUuas praesidia babebant, nee recep- tudinis, juris consensu, et concord!

tacula frigoris et caloris, nee ipsi inter communione sociatus."

se homines ab hominibus satis erant * St Isidore of Seville, Etym., ix. 3 :

tuti. Tandem naturali solertia spelun- ^' Reges a regendo vocati : sicut enim

cis, sylvestribusque tegumentis tuguria sacerdos a sanctificando, ita et rex a

sibi et casas virgultis aruudinibusque regendo : non autem regit qui non cor-

contexuerunt, quo esset vita tutior, ne rigit. Recte igitur faciendo regis nomen

iis qui nocere possent, aditus esset. tenetur, peccando amittitur. Unde






CHAP. XIV.] AUTHORITY AND JUSTICE. l73

trasted that of the tyrant, the wicked r uler who cruelly, o ppresses his people .^ He carries out the same conception of kingship in greater detail in his ' Sentences.' In one place he again says that kings are so called from ruling, and lose the . name if they transgress. ^ In another passage, which we have already quoted, he explains that t he object for which kings and princes were appointed was that the people should be restrained from evil and directed to good. ^ The duty of the rul er is therefo re to set forward justice in truth and reality;* and he will be guilty of a very grea t cr ime if he appoint unjust judges.^ And finally, in a chapter already cited, which is often referred to in later times, having been embodied by Gratian in the Decretum, he maintains t hat it is a ju st thing that a prince should obey his own la ws.^

It is true that along with these judgments he also maintains with St Augustine that evil kings are sent by God as a judgmen t upon evil peoples .*^ We have already quoted his words, and have seen that this notion pro bably assisted^ in the de velop - ment of the the ory that the ruler was in such a sense the repre - sentative of God that he could in no case be resisted. But St Is idore himsel f does not draw this conclusion ; rather he seems in the m ain to hold that the legitimacy of Government is de- termined by its character, — that it is only as far as the ruler

et apud veteres, tale erat proverbium. cupiditatem, et crudelissimam domina-

  • Rex eris si recte facies, si non facias, tionem in populis exercentes." ,

non eris.' ^ St Isidore of Seville, Sententise, iii,

"Regise virtutes prsecipuse duse, 48. justitia et pietas : plus autem in * Id., id., ilL 47. See p. 119.

regibus laudatur pietas ; nam justitia ^ Id., id., iii. 49.

per se severa est." " Id., id., iii. 52.

^ St Isidore of Seville, Etym. ix. 3 : • Id., id., iii. 51 : " Justum est prin-

" Tyranni Qrseci dicuntur iidem Latine dpem legibus obtemperare suis. Tunc

et reges : nam apud veteres inter regem enim jura sua ab omnibus custodienda

et tyrannum nulla discretio erat : ut, existimet, quando et ipse illis reveren-

  • Pars mihi pacis erit, dextram tetigisse tiam praebet. Principem legibus teneri

tyranni.' Fortes enim reges tyranni sms, neque in se posse damnare jura, Yocabantur: nam Hyro' fortis; de quae in subjectis constituimt. Justa quibus Dominus loquitur : * Per me est enim vocis eorum auctoritas, si, reges regnant, et tyranni per me quod populis prohibent, sibi licere non tenent terram.' Jam postea in usum patiantur." Cf. Qratian, Decretum, accidit, tyrannos vocari pessimos atque Dist. ix. 2.

improbos reges luxuriosse dominationis "^ Id., id., iii 48. See p. 151.






174 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part m,

p romotes justice that he is to be looked upon as a true rule r at all

We have endeavoured in this chapter to put together the judgments of the Fathers upon the place of justice in society. We have 6een that, with the exception of St Augustine, they seem to show the persistence of the conception that the end of the State is the attainment of justice, and that the quality of justice is essential to the legitimacy of any organisation of society. We think it is important to observe this, for in some measure it seems to counteract that tendency of some of the Christian Fathers towards the theory of the absolute Divine authority of the monarch, and^ the consequent obligation of unlimited obedience. The truth is, probably, that the Christian Fathers had no clearly and completely developed conception of the nature of civil authority. One or two principles with respect to this were firmly fixed in their minds, but the conclusions which might be more or less legitimately derived from these principles were undefined, and not generally thought out, still less brought into logical coherence with each other. They were convinced of the Divine nature of the authority of the State, they were convinced that disobedience to that authority was in normal cases an offence against God. Some of them drew from this the conclusion that all authority, under all circum- stances, was from God, and that even an unjust and oppressive command of the ruler must be obeyed. On the other hand, they were for the most part equally clear that the foundation and end of civil authority was the attainment of justice, and some of them more or less distinctly apprehended, as a con- sequence of this principle, that an unjust authority was no authority at all. The great principles which they held were of the profoundest and most permanent significance; but they had not drawn out from them a complete and coherent theory of the nature of authority in society.






175


CHAPTER XV.

THE THEORY OF THE RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE.

We have endeavoured to recognise something of the complexity of the patristic conceptions with regard to the nature of authority in the State. We have at least seen that while there is in the Fathers a tendency tQwarda__a . theory oP ^^ absolutism in the ruler, which finds its complete expression^ m St Giregory the Great, there are also other tendencies which ^ seem to counteract this. These tendencies may be said to (' ^ centre round the conception of ^ bftUce, in spite of the fact that<> \/^ St Augustine's hold upon this cShception is so loose ; for in this matter, as in so much of his theology, St Augustine probably represents, not the normal, but a somewhat eccentric though influential, mode of thought. We think it is correct to say that the Fathers tend to think of the principle of justice as of . something which lies outside the power of the civil authority — something which it does not create, and to which it is in some measure answerable. We may -perhaps justly consider that there is some relation between this conception of a principle of justice outside the civil order and the gradually developing con- sciousness that while the civil order is itself one manifestation or expression of the principle of justice, this same principle finds expression in another order, the ecclesiastical, which is,

properly speaking, not sn Tnnp.b within tha .m-Qtft ^q parflllpl \^J

J^ We find in the Fathers the consciousness that the Church has its own laws and principles, its own administrative author- ity, which is not at all to be regarded as dependent upon the'- State, but as something which stands beside it and is inde- pendent of it ; that the relations between the Church and the ;






/


176 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS, [part hi.

^State are those of two independent though closely related powers, relations which it becomes necessary, as time goes by, to understand and define more clearly.

I, Before the conversion of Constantinelmdeed, there was little question about the relation between the State and the Church : the Church was not merely separate, but was generally treated

J by the State as an enemy — an enemy which it would be well, if possible, to destroy. The Church was a voluntary society ^within the Empire, dependent for every public right that it might enjoy upon the grudging consent of the State. Christians asked for toleration, and maintained that they could not give up their faith and worship at the command of any earthly power; but toleration was all that they asked, and they asked it in the name of humanity, and on the ground that their religion, so far from being hurtful to the State or to good morals, would rather tend to loyalty and good order. The Church was necessarily

% conscious of its independence, but this independence was a - purely spiritual one, and it claimed no rights or properties of a secular kinc^xcept as derived from the sanction and authority of the State;/

The conversion of Constantine and the official Christianisation | of the Empire brought with them an entirely new set of circum- 1

. stances ; and the Church had to find its true place in these \ with much difficulty and labour. The change which the con- version of the Empire brought about does not seem to have been at all clearly recognised at first; at least we have been unable to find any source of information as to this in the litera- - ture of the time. The actual historical circumstances, however, 1 ) gradually compelled men to form some sort of theory of the ' relation of the two societies. The relation of the Church and Church law to the civil authorities was gradually defined ; great | questions were indeed left outstanding, but we feel that at least | some of the Fathers arrived at certain more or less clearly de- 1

' fined conceptions of the relations between Church and State. We think that, while some of the Fathers use ambiguous phrases, there can be no serious doubt that after the conversion of Constdntine, as much as before it, churchmen did normally * refuse to recognise any authority of the civil ruler in spiritual |






CHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE.


177


i


matters. Bufin us of Aquile i a has presftrvftd i^ his hist9rv a • ^ report of a speecn wni cii (Jonstantine^ as he says, made to theT* vy b iflhepo of Ijhu C'h W6h assembled in the Council of Nicex /\ According to this report, Constantine recognised very clearlv / I the limitations of the imperial authority in relation to Churchy^ ^ J order. He acknowledges frankly that he has no.jurisdictioiilf / over bishops in spiritual matters, while they have jurisdiction/ j over all Christians.^ A little later than the Council of Nice,' I we find Hosius of Cordova, as quoted by St Athanasius, in spitei^ • / of his close connection with the imperial court, repudiating m aK the most emphatic terms the notion that the emperor had any\ \f I right to interfere in Churct affairs. He warns Constantiua, I

not to intrude into ecclesiastical affairs : God had granted to /

him the kingdom, to the churchmen the care of the Church ; he \

should remember that just as any one who should revolt against him would disobey God, so if he presumed to draw Church affairs under his control he would be guilty of a great fault.^ '^ Hosius's tone is very emphatic, much more so than we should perhaps have expected from the somewhat servile attitude of churchmen like Eusebius of Csesarea, and it would seem to indicate the presence of a more general appreciation, at that time, of the independence of the Church relatively to the State than has been always recognised. If such language could be attributed to Constantine, and used by a friend of the court like

(Qru


JufinuB, Hist. Eccl., i. 2 : " Deus vo^ constituit sacerdotes, et potestatem vobis dedit de nobis quoque judi- candi, et ideo nos a vobis recte judi- camnr. Vos autem non potestis ab hominibus judicari. Propter quod Dei «oliu8 inter vos exspectate judicium, et vestra jurgia qusecumque sunt, ad illud divinum reserventur examen. Vos etenim nobis a Deo dati estis dii, et conveniens non est ut homo judicet Deos, sed ille solus, de quo scriptum est : ' Deus stetit in synagoga deorum ; in medio autem decs discemit.'"

How far Rufinus's report is histor- ically correct is a matter on which we •express no opinion. We cite the pass- Age not to illustrate the standpoint

VOL. I.


of Constantine, but that of a Western oiHmhman like Rufinus.

^r^osius of Cordova, letter quoted t in St Athanasius, * Historia Arianorum,' / 44 : M^ rl0€i fftavrhy fis t& iKKXTjctaff' TiKd' firjih ffh irepl ro6rcov riyLiv irapa- K€\€iov ' &AAd uaWov irap' iifMoy <rv fidvdav€ ravra,fflio\ fiaffiKtiav 6 Ofhi 4v€X€(pi<r€if ' riixiv rk ti?$ 'EicicAi7<r(as 4irl(rr€va'€,/^al &(rir€p 6 r^p a^v h.px^^ imoKkim-oav kvriXiy^i r^ Siara^ainivw 6€y, oSt« <l>ofii^0TiTi fi^i Kal <ri», tA ttjs ^EKKXTjclas els ^avrhv MKkojVj {nce{tOvvos iyKK'fifAttTi fieyd\<f> ydtrp. 'Arddorf, ^ry- paTrraif rk Kaiaapos Kaiffopt, koI rh rod 0€ov rf Oe^, OVrh roivw rifuv &p- X^iv ^irl T^s T^y ^l^ariVf oUre ffh rod 0vfii§if i^oualav ^X«* fiafftXev, M


\^






178 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.


Hosius, we need not perhaps be surprised to find a man of the

violent temper oJML]^afai ^ftyilagliari using language identical in

sentiment but somewhat more unqualified in tone, in the height

of thecontep ** ^^ th'^ AfiiQr^|^^ jfl.n pn.rf.y with the Emperor Con-

°^I1tiir° w^fKrMif these phrases of Eufinus and Hosius we

should indeed have hesitated as to the genuineness of the work

r from which we quote. LugJl^Jiftdigaantly protests that Con -

l^stantius is no judge of bisnops, bu | rrat5er should obey the^

\ and thyir lawa ! and^Hft fionclndfts hv savinior that thft ftrnpftror is

Cnot even a Christian, and appointed by God to rule his people,

Gbut only a heretic and a persecutor.^ Lucifer's tone is like that

of the spurious letters of Gregory II. in the eighth century :

we might even imagine ourselves in the early stages of the

^ Iij^estitora^-gfilltr^^ of the eleventh century.

4 Against these passages we must no doubt set certain sayings

which have a somewhat different character. We have already

quoted a passage from the writings of St Optatus of Milevis,

in which we find represented a different attitude towards the


Hv Lucifer of Cagliari, *Pro Sancto Atnanasio,' i. (in Migne, Patrol. Lat., vol. xiiL p. 826) : " Sed dicis : isto in loco Deo devotissimus Moyses quomodo sacerdotum fecit mentionem, sic et judicis. Proba te super nos factum judicem, proba ad hoc te constitutum imperatorem, ut nos armis tuis ad omnem implendam voluntatem amici tui diaboli perdu- ceres; cum probare non possis quia prseceptum sit tibi, non solum non dominari episcopis, sed et ita eorum obedire statutis, ut si subvertere eorum decreta tentaveris, si fueris in superbia comprehensus, morte mori jussus sis. Quomodo dicere poteris, judicare te posse de episcopis, quibus nisi obedieris, jam, quantum apud Deum, mortis poena fueris multatus? Cum haec ita sint, tu qui es profanus, ad Dei domesticos, quare istam sumis in Dei sacerdotum auctoritatem ? Cum etiam ipsos judices Judseos, tunc quando in lege manebant Dei, ex genere habere permiserit suo. *Si enim* inquit


Moyses 'dixeris, Statuam supra me principem, quomodo et reliquse gentes . . .' Et subsequitur, cur noluerit alienigenam fieri principem, ne scilicet ad sectam suam traheret alios. Prop- terea dicit : * Ne revocet nos in jEgyp- tum,* hoc est, ad idolorum cultum, quasi dicat: Quis est tu, inquam, qui tibi usurpasti banc auctoritatem, quam tibi Deus non tradidit, et si traderet, et inter te esse permitteret, primo in loco Christianum te esse oportuerat, quia Bcelus esset alienigenam Dei servos ju- dicare, inimicum. religionis domesticos DeL Deinde si fuisses Christianus, et te participem censuisset Deus sacer- dotibus fieri ad gerendum populum ejus, acciptf qualem te esse praeceperit in Deuteronomio. ' Et erit cum sederit in principatu suo, scribe hoc in libro ante sacerdotes et levitas, et erit cum ipso. . . .' Quid tu hujusmodi habes, nisi omnia contraria, nisi cuncta, quae Dei impugnent domum? Primo es hsere- ticus, deinde persecutor Dei domestic eorum."






l:^


CHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE. 179

State, and its interference with Church matters. Donatus had evidently treated the intervention of the emperor in favour of the Catholic party just as Lucifer of Cagliari had treated his interference against it, and had indignantly argued that the > emperor had no right to interfere in Church matters. St Optatus /


«*^ urges in reply that the Church is in the empire, not the empire'


V


in the Church, and seems to treat the attitude of Donatus as that of one who set himself over the emperor, while, he urges, there is no one over the emperor but God.^ Optatus seems to go rather far towards admitting the supremacy of the imperial I * jurisdiction even in Church matters.

It is natural to conjecture that some such notion lies behind that strange^ phrase of Ambrosiaster, to which we have already / referred, ge calls the king the Vicar of God, and says that ^ he has the image of God, and the bishop has that of Christ.^ The phrase is indeed very diflBcult of interpretation, but it is / at least possible that it is intended to signify some superiority/ of jurisdic tionl If, then, we find in some of the Christian writers a very clear '\ , and explicit HApl graHnn nf f] i< > prlnniplft tli^^ ^^" ^^"^" ^•* no { j^isdiction in ^ Church matters, we must also recogBJaa^tbat ^ others tend to a more doubtful position. We may in part ex- plain the phrases of the latter as only referring to the power of the State to carry out secular penalties for eccclesiastical offences: no doubt the Catholic Church, when it invoked the arm of the temporal power to put down heretics and schis- matics, conceived that its position was secure, — that it was for the Church to judge in spiritual matters, for the secular power to carry out the consequence of its judgments in secular conditions. But actually the policy of persecution "i did tend to make the State the arbitrator between different religious parties. At the same time, we do not think there can be any doubt as to the normal character of the Church theory with regard to its relation to the State. Indeed, the considera- tion of the views of these writers is, we think, of importance, mainly as preparing us for the examination of the much more complete treatment of the subject in the work of St Ambrose.

1 See p. 14A "See p. \^

CjOOQ IC 


J


^80 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part m.

In St Ambrose the theory of the relation between the Church and State is more or less clearly defined. He is clear that certain rights of the Church are sacred and inviolable, in the very nature of things, and in accordance with the nature of God's ordinance in the world. He is very clearly conscious that the Church has its own jurisdiction, to which all Christian men, whatever their rank, are subject, and that the jufisdiction of the State does not extend over any strictly ecclesiastical matters.

We have already seen that St Ambrose, like all the Fathers, recognises the divine character of the civil order of society, j He insists that the Christian man must^nder obedience to xhe civil ruler in virtue of his religion: not even the priest is to act disrespectfully towards the civil ruler, but, on the other hand, if the ruler commits any grave offence, theiu the priest must reprove him.^ The ministers of the Church have- jurisdiction over all Christian men, and their jurisdiction ex- tends even over the Emperor or other civil ruler.^ For even the Emperor is the son of the Church, subject to its authority, to its discipline : no title, St Ambrose says, is more honourable than that of son of the Church, — the Emperor is within the /Chu rch, not over it . ^l /We find it, tlierefore, very natural that ' ^e shoula near o'Rt Ambrose exercising the last discipline of the Church, even against so pious and orthodox a ruler as the great Theodosius. The stufy of the exclusion of Theodosius from the Eucharist is, of course, very familiar, and it is not necessfiry here to detail the circumstances. For the massacre

>^St Ambrose, Enarr. in Ps. xxxvii. qui abnuat in causa fidei, in causa, in-

43: "Vides ergo quia regibus non quam, fidei episcopos solere de impera-

temere vel a prophetis Dei, vel a toribus Christianis, non imperatores de

sacerdotibus facienda injuria sit; si episeopis judicare."

nulla sint graviora peccata, in quibus vL^t Ambrose, Sermo contra Auxen-

debeant ai-gui : ubi autem peccata tium, 36 in Ep. xxi. : " Quod cum

graviora sunt, ibi non videtur a Sacer- honorificentia imperatoris dictum nemo

dote parcendum, ut justis increpationi- potest negare. Quid enim honorificen-

bus corrigantur." tins, quam ut imperator Ecclesise filius

(^ St Ambrose, Ep. xxi 4 (Ad Valent. esse dicatur ? Quod cum dicitur, sine

II. ) : ^' Quando audisti, clementissime peccato dicitur, cum gratia dicitur. Im-

Imperator, in causa fidei laicos de perator enim intra Ecclesiam, non supra

episcopo judicasse. . . . Atcertesivel Ecclesiam est; bonus enim imperator

Scripturarum seriem divinarum, vel quserit auxilium Ecclesise non refutat."

Vetera tempora retractemus, quis est Contrast with St Optatus. See p. 148.






CHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE.


181


in ThfiHflf^]^Qj[p.fl. Theodosius was responsible, and St Ambrose excluded him from attendance at the celebration of the Euch- arist. It is perhaps worth while to cite some words from St Ambrose's letter to Theodosius, and to observe the mingled deference and firmness with which St Ambrose tells Theo- dosius that he cannot "oflGerr the sacrifice" if he is present.^ It may, perhaps, serve to bring out more clearly the signif- icance of this event, when we observe that this action was not isolated, but that for a much smaller matter, as we learn from a letter to his sister, St Ambrose had been prepared to .

take almost the same action. Certain Christians had burned u^'"*^^'^*^' down a synagogue of the Jews, and some monks had burned 1 down a church belonging to adherents of the Valentinian heresy. Theodosius, very justly, as we should probably think, .y' ordered the Christians to rebuild the synagogue, and the punishment of the monks. But St Ambrose took another view of the matter, and regarded the action of Theodosius as being contrary to religion. He wrote him a letter on the subject, and then preached on the matter in his presence, and, the sermon ended, demanded of Theodosius an assurance that he would withdraw the obnoxious order, before he would con- sent to celebrate the Eucharist.^ Practically, St Ambrose was


^ Si Ambrose, Ep. li. 13': "Egocerte in omnibus aliis licet debitor pietati tu86, cui ingratus esse non possum, quam pietatem multis impeitktoribus prseferebam, imi adsequabam: ego inquam, causam in te contumacise nullam habeo, sed habeo timoris ; offerre non audeo sacrificium, si volueris assistere."

2 St Ambrose (to his sister), Ep. xli. 27 : " Ubi descendi, ait mihi : De nobis proposuisti. Respondi: Hoc tractavi, quod ad utilitatem tuam pertineret. Tunc ait : Re vera de synagoga repar- anda ab episcopo durius statueram, sed emendatum est. Monachi multa scelera f aciunt. Tunc Timasius magister equi- tum et peditum coepit adversum mona- chos esse vehementior. Bespondi ei : Ego cum imperatore ago, ut oportet ; quia novi quod habeat Domini timo-


rem : tecum autem aliter agendum, qiyftam dura loqueris.

2#. Deinde cum aliquamdiu starem, dico imperatori : Fac me secunmi pro te offerre, absolve animum meum.' Cum assideret, annueretque, non tamen aperte polliceretur, atque ego starem, dixit se emendaturum rescriptum. Statim dicere coepi, ut omnem cogni- tionem toUeret ; ne occasione cognitionis comes aliqua Christianos attereret in- juria. Promisit futurum. Aio iUi: Ago fide tua ; et repetivi. Ago fide tua. Age, inquit, fide mea. Et ita ad altare accessi, non aliter accessurus nisi mihi plene promisisset. Et vere tanta ob- lationis fuit gratia, ut sentirem etiam ipse eam Deo nostro commendatiorem fuisse gratiam, et divinam prsDsentiam non defuisse. Omnia itaque ex sen- tentia gesta sunt."






182 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART in.

threatening Theodosius with exclusion from attendance at the celebration of the sacrament.

St Ambrose, then, is very clear in his assertion of the prin- . ciple that the Church exercises jurisdiction over all Christian ^ men, even the most exalted — even over the chief of the State. And at the same time he asserts, with equal emphasis, the . principle that in religious matters, the civil magistrate has .f no authority over ecclesiastics. We have cited one of the emphatic passages in which St Ambrose asserts that in mat- ters of faith the layman has no jurisdiction over the priest.^ He evidently traces this rule to the divine law, and that law, he urges, is greater than the imperial ;2 but he also urges that the principle has been admitted by the imperial legislation. In the letter from which we have just cited St Ambrose urges this point with great persistence. H g^had been request ed to appear before the Imperial Court, and' he refu ses to comply, on thH ground jjial this was anThfrmgement of a_Iaw^of Valentinian I.^ We do nor^ropose" to "enter into the history I of ecclesiastical exemption from secular jurisdiction, a sub- • ject of formidable complexity, but it is necessary to observe it as illustrating the development of the position of the Church as being, within its own sphere, independent of the State.

It is not only in relation to the jurisdiction of the Church over the laity in spiritual matters, and its independence

^ See p. 181, note 2. ordinis eum judicare debere, qui ncc

2 St Ambrose, Ep. xxi. 10 (Ad munere impar sit, nee jure dissimilis ; Valent. II.) : "Ecce, imperator, legem hsec enim verba rescripti sunt, hoc est, tuam jam ex parte rescindis : sed sacerdotes de sacerdotibus voluit judi- utinam non ex parte, sed in universum ! care. Quinetiam si alias quoque ar- legem enim tuam noUem esse supra Dei gueretur episcopus, et morum esset legem. Dei lex nos docuit quid sequa- examinanda causa, etiam haec voluit mur, humanse leges hoc docere non ad episcopale judicium pertinere. . . , possunt." 5. Eris Deo favente, etiam senectutis

3 St Ambrose, Ep. xxi. 2 (Ad maturitate provectior, et tunc de hoc Valent. II.) : " Cui rei respondeo, ut censebis quaUs ille episcopus sit, qui arbitror, competenter. Nee quisquam laicis jus sacerdotale substemit. Pater contumacem judicare me debet, cum tuus, Deo favente, vir maturioris sevi, hoc asseram, quod augustse memorise dicebat : non est meum judicare inter pSter tuus non solum sermone re- episcopos ; tua nunc dicit ' dementia, spondit, sed etiam legibus suis sanxit. Ego debeo judicare. . . ."

In causa fidei vel ecclesiastici alicujus






OHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE. 183

of the civil ruler in all such matters, that v^e can recognise

in St Ambrose the sense of the existence of a power and

law which is altogether outside of the sphere of the civil

ruler. We can see in his writings the beginning of the im- yy(^^

portance of those questions with regard to Church property, ^

round which so much of the controversies of later times turned.

We have fortunately a tolerably full account in St Ambrose's

own writings of the position he took up, when the emperor

wished to insist on his giving up one or more of the churches

in his diocese for the use of the Arians. In a letter to his

sister he gives an account of the discussion between himself

and the officials sent to demand thisi They insisted that

he should acquiesce promptly, for the emperor was within

his rights, for all things were in his power. He replied that

if t.hft p.TY^ peror were to demand his private property, he would ' yt

n ot refuse it; but t hos e things which were fj^t'^j^'^'^r, wayp^ ^Af. ^^/

s ubject to the imper ial power. Further on, however, he

qualifies this statement by urging that the emperor cannot

lawfully seize a private house, much less the house of God.

When he is again urged to surrender a church, he replies that

it is neither lawful for him to surrender it nor for the emperor

to accept it. The emperor, if he wishes to reign long, must be

subject to God, and obey the rule to give to Caesar what is

Caesar's and to God what is Grod's. Palaces belong to the em- \ j

peror, churches to the prie^, and he cannot surrender a church.^ y

^ Ep. XX. 8 : " Convenior ipse a com- auferendam ? Allegatur imperatori

itibus et tribunis, ut basilicse fieret licere omnia, ipsius esse imiversa.

matura traditio, dicentibus impera- Respondeo, noli te gravare, Imperator,

torem jui'e suo uti, eo quod in potes- ut putes te in ea, quae diviua simt, im-

tate ejus essent omnia. Respondi, si periale aliquod jus habere. Noli te ex-

a me peteret, quod meum est, id est, tollere, sed si vis diutius imperare, esto

fundum meum, argentum meum, quid- Deo subditus. Scriptum est, qusD Dei

vis hujusmodi meum, me non re£raga- Deo, quae Caesaris, Csesari. Ad impera-

tunim .; . quamquam omnia quae mei torem palatia pertinent, ad sacerdotem

sunt, essent pauperum : verum ea quae Ecclesiae. Publicorum tibi moenium

sunt divina, imperatoriae potestati non jus comnussum est, non sacrorum. . . .

esse subjecta. ... 22. Tradere basilicam non possum

19. Mandatur denique: Trade bas- sed pugnare non debeo. . . .

ilicam. Respondeo : Nee mihi fas est 23. Si haec tyrannidis videntur,

tradere, nee tibi accipere, Imperator, habeo arma, sed in Christi nomine ;

expedit. Domum privaii nullo potes habeo offerendi mei corporis potest-

jure temerare, domum Dei existimas atem. Quid moraretur ferire, si tyran-






^


I


184 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

In the public discourse which St Ambrose delivered upon the same subject he repeats the same observations, but also throws some further light upon the question of what he understood to be the Church property, which was sacred to God. He protests his habitual respect for the emperor, but the demand for a church he cannot comply with. But, he adds, the lands of the Church pay tribute to the emperor ; and if the emperor wishes to take these, he will not resist.^ Evidently he draws a dist jnctign hftf.wf^gn j;he churches and other eccle si- astical property . The distinction is one of some importance with regard to later developments of the relation of the State to Church property.

St Ambrose, then, is clear that there are distinct limitations to the imperial authority when the emperor comes into relation with religious matters. The Church has its o wn pos ition and authority, which is independent of that of the "Btate . We think that it is not unreasoilAbItt to judge that CEere was some relation between these clear convictions of St Ambrose and that

  • tendency which we have already observed in him to limit the

absolute authority of the civil ruler, even in secular matters — at least, to conceive of his authority as limited by the principle • of justice, and perhaps as limited by the laws of the State.

In the latter part of the fifth century the question of the

relation between the authority of the State and that of the

Clhurch is discussed very fully, especially in the letters and

jff^'i"^ /treatises of Pope G elasius I.; and these not only show us how

J . - w ^ / clearly the question"was then apprehended, but^ also lay the

^ foundations on which the theoryj)f the ninth century was

based. It is true that these disciassi(3HS "anT definitions

num putaret ? Veteri jure a sacerdoti- cedere : suppliciis me libenter oflEerre,

bus donata imperia, non usurpata : et nee metuere quae parantur. . . . vulgo dici quod imperatores sacer- 33. Agri Ecolesise solvunt trib-

dotium magis optaverunt, quam im- utum : si agros desiderat imperator,

perium sacerdotes. . . . Addidi quia potestatem habet vindicandorum ; nemo

numquam sacerdotes tyranni f uerunt, nostrum intervenit. Potest pauperibus

sed tyrannos ssepe sunt passi." coUatio populi redundare: non faciant

^ St Ambrose, Sermo contra Auxen- de agris invidiam, toUant eos, si libitum

tium, in Ep. xxi. : " Scitis et vos ipsi est imperatori : non dono sed non

quod imperatoribus soleam deferre non nego."






CHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE. 185

go to establish a theory of a strict dualism in society, and\,^ they are not therefore in accord with the tendency of those medisBval thinkers who thought of society as organised under the terms of a complete unity. The development of the theory of unity in society is one of the most important of the move- ments which we shall have to study, — one of the most inter- esting aspects of mediaeval political theory : we are at the same time not certain^ whether its historical significance has not been to some extent exaggerated, — whether scholars have not sometimes mistaken the formal or superficial tendencies of mediaeval political thought for the fundamental. "We are not quite sure whether the real importance of the conception of an absolute or formal unity in society, either in mediaeval or in modern political theory, is quite what some may imagine. But this is a subject about which we shall have more to say in later volumes. The discussions and definitions of the fifth century belong to a stage in the development of political theory when* the conception of dualism in society was taking shape and mak- ing itself felt as of importance in practical administration : we can at the same time recognise in them some of the elements out of which, in later times, the theory of the complete unity of society was to be constructed.

The historical circumstances which produced the literature which we have now to examine were of a highly complex kind. The Council of Chalcedon had tried to end the disputes of the"^ Alexandrian and Antiochene schools in the Church by a defin- j ition of the doctrine of the union of the human and divine j natures in our Lord, which was intended equally to condemn the extreme or so-called monophysite tendency of the Alex- andrian and the extreme, or so-called Kestorian tendency of the 1 Antiochene school. In the main, while its decisions resulted^ in the separation from the Church of a certain number of ex- tremists at each ^d, the decisions of Chalcedon did conclude the historical settlement of the terms of the faith of the Church l^ with regard to our Lord's nature. But it was more than two centuries before the disputes on the subject in the Church were set at rest. The monophysite tendency was so strong, especially in Egypt, that in 482 the Emperor Zeno, with the advice ap-






/


186 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.

parently of Acacius, Patriarch of Constantinople, issued a state- ment known to us as the "Henoticon," in which he tried to ^ state the doctrine of our Lord's nature in such a way as to ^ conciliate the Egyptians. In the West, however, and notably by the Bishops of Eome, these proceedings were looked upon with the greatest disfavour, and Felix II. finally anathematised Acacius. It is not clear that Felix or his successor, Gelasius I., actually excommunicated either Zeno or any of the other em- perors who remained in communion with Acacius, and with Peter, the Patriarch of Alexandria; but practically all com- munion with those who held to Acacius was broken off, and the Emperors and the Bishop of Eome found themselves in formal opposition to each other.

The circumstances of the time were no doubt favourable to the development of an independent attitude in the "Western Church, for this was the period during which the Gothic invasions and occupation had practically destroyed all the power of the Byzantine emperor in Italy. This may perhaps partly explain the confidence of the tone adopted by the bishops of Eome to- wards the emperors, though it would be a mistake to think that such an attitude towards the civil ruler was unprecedented : we have indeed seen something of the same kind in the case of St Ambrose.

We may perhaps with advantage notice some details in the

theor y of Felix II. and Gelasius L with regard to the relations

of the Church and the emperor before we discuss their formal

definitions on this subject. They both assert with great

emphasis the subordination even of the emperor to the Church

in spiritual matters. Eelj^ exhorts Zeno to remember that it is

' /well for him if he strive to submit his royal will to the priests

\j^of Christ: w hen th e things concerning God are in question,

^^^e king shouia learn rather tha n presume to teac h.^ In

/Wpeiix. II., Ep. viii. 5 : " Certum est Ecclesise formam sequi, non huic hu-

enim, hoc rebus vestris esse salutare, manitus s,equenda jura prsafigere, neque

ut cum de causis Dei agitur, et juxta ejus sanctionibus velle domiDari, cui

ipsius coDstitutum regiam voluntatem Deus voluit clementiam tuam pise de-

sacerdotibus Christi studeatis subdere, votionis coUa submittere : ne dum men-

non prseferre, et sacrosancta per eorum sura ccelestis dispositioms exceditur

prsesules discere potius quam docere. eatur in contumeliam disponentia."






CHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE.


187


the tenth letter of Po£e_Q£laaius the same thing is said, with perhaps a little additional precision and a special assertion of the authority of the apostolic see. The secular power should^ learn, not judge, of divine things from the bis hops, and spec ially 'Brbm the V icar, ot Si Pel er: nut eveiTtEermost powerful of Christian rulers of the world may draw such things into his hands.^ The subject is drawn out in greater detail in the first letter attributed to Gelasius, a letter thought to have been written by him in the name of Pope Felix II. to the Easter bishops. The emperor has no authority, Gelasius urges, to^ consider the cause of an ecclesiastic or to receive him to com- munion : this is contrary to all church order. The emperor is^ the son, not the ruler, of the Church : God gave the authority of riiler jin JbLis Church to bishops and priests, not to secular rulers o r "to the civil law. The emperor has indeed received his authority from God, and should -Jthetoforft-joot set himself^


against the divine order.^

^ Gelasius I., Ep. x. 9 : " Si quantum ad religionem pertinet, non nisi apostoli- cse sedi juxta canones debetur summa judicii totius; si quantum ad sseculi poteetatem, ilia a pontificibus- et prse- cipue a beati Petri vicario debet cog- noscere, qusa divina simt, non ipsa eadem judicare. Nee sibi hoc quis- quam potentissimus sseculi, qui tamen Christianus est, vindicare praesumit, nmrreligionem forsitan persequens." (ybtelaaiua I., Ep. i. 10, Ad Epis- copos Orientales : " An imperator ilium discussit atque suscepit? Con- stat interim iUum ecclesiasticis regulis non receptum: ab ecclesiastica igitur regu]a receptio ejus omnis aliena est. Quod si dixeris : * Sed imperator catholicus est ' ; salva pace ipsius dixerimus, filius est, non praesul Ec- clesise : quod ad religionem competit, discere ei convenit non docere ; habet privilegia potestatis suae, quae adminis- trandis publicis rebus divinitus con- secutus est; et ejus beneficiis non ingratus contra dispositionem coelestis ordinis nil usurpet. Ad sacerdotes enim Deus voluit, quae Ecclesiae dis-


ponenda sunt, pertinere, non ad saeculi potestates ; quae si fideles sunt, Ecclesiae suae et sacerdotibus voluit esse sub- jectas. Non sibi vindicet alienum jus, et ministerium, quod altero deputatum est ; ne contra eum tendat abrupte, a quo omnia constituta sunt, et contra illius beneficia pugnare videatur, a quo propriam consecutus est potestatem. Non legibus publicis, non a potestatibus saeculi, sed a pontificibus et sacerdotibus omnipotens Deus Christianae religionis dominos et sacerdotes voluit ordinari, et discuti recipique de errore remeantes. Imperatores Christiani subdere debent exsecutiones suas ecclesiasticis praesul- ibus, non praeferre. Nulla ergo nee certa discussio est, nee manere potest ista Busceptio ejus, quem Ecclesia suis legibus nee ordine competenti nee dis- cussit omnino nee communioni res- tituit. Ideoque potius errori ejus commimicavit Acacius catholicamque fidem ei prostituit, quam ilium ad com- munionem catholicam revocavit ; cujus enim non est ordinata receptio, sequitur, ut in errore permanserit."






188 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PABT III.

As we have said, we do not find in these letters any trace of a definite or explicit excommunication of the emperor ; but it is evident from them that they do not look upon the emperor as in any way exempt from the operation of such general discip- linary measures as they had taken. Felix II. seems to put before the Emperor Zeno the choice between communion with St Peter or with Peter of Alexandria ; ^ and while G^lasius I. expresses himself in courteous and friendly terms, and re- pudiates the notion that he has condemned the emperor, yet we think that his phrases practically mean that communion with the excommunicate separates the emperor from the Eoman Church.2

The attitude of Felix and Gelasius towards the emperor is courteous, and even deferential, but it is at the same time quite firm. It is clear that while they were reluctant to break with the emperor, to have an open quarrel with him, they had no hesitation in resisting him. It is, in this connection, there- fore, very interesting to find that we have in one of the letters of Gelasius perhaps the first example of a regular enumeration of occasions on which churchmen had, as he thinks, been com- ^pelled to resist and reprove the secular ruler. Gelasius begins ' by referring to the rebuke of David by the prophet Nathan, and then mentions the public separation of Theodosius from the communion of the Church by St Ambrose, the rebuke of Theodosius the younger ^by_StJLeOr-the action o f Pope Hilar y

^ Felix II., Ep. viii. 2 : " Unde tare curaverim ? Decessores mei sacer-

quoniam adhortationem meam duxistis dotes, qui prsevaricatoribus se communi-

onerosam, in vestro relinquo delibera- casse propria voce confessi sunt, a

tionis arbitrio, utrum beati apostoli communione apostolica submoverunt.

Petri an Alexandrini Petri cuiquam sit Si isti placet se miscere damnatis, nobis

eligenda communio." non potest imputari; si ab eis velit

2 Gelasius I., Ep. x. 2 : " Quid sibi abscedere, tanto magis a nobis non

vult autem, quod dixerit imperator, a potest esse danmatus, sed potius ad

nobis se irreligiose damnatum, cum gratiam sincerse communionis admissus.

super hac parte et decessor mens non Ad senatum vero pertinet Romanum,

solum minime nomen ejus attigerit, sed ut memor fidei, quam a parentibus se

insuper quando principia adeptus regiae suscepisse meminit, contagia vitet com-

potestatis exseruit, in ejus se rescripsit munionis extemse, ne a communione

imperii promotione gaudere : et ego hujus sedis apostolicee, quod absit, red-

nuUa ipsius unquam scripta percipiens, datxir extemus." honorificis eum, ut nostis, litteris salu-






CHAP. XV.] RELATION OP CHURCH AND STATE.


189


against the Emperor Anthem ius. and of Fop^ Rimplipinff sini^ry Pope FeKx^agaihstTKe us urper Basiliscus and the lefyjtimate ^ Emperor Zeno.^ Thls^" enumeration of cases in which the authority of the Church had dealt with and rebuked the heads of the civil government serves to furnish us vrith an interesting view of the circumstances out of which arose the growing consciousness of the existence of an authority in the Church independent of, and in its own sphere superior to, that of the State. ^^^

We may again note Vh^t Pope Gelasius was concerned not^ only to assert the authority o t t he CtrQTChrlg"air" spiri tual matter s, but also to^establish the pri nciple that the civil ^ p ower had no jurisdiction over ecclesiastical persons, at least i n spiritual matters. We have a letter in which he indig- ,^ nantly protests to the Eastern bishops against their suffe ring ecclesiastical persons to be tried by secular authorities.^/ We


. 1 Gelasius L, Ep. xxvi. 11 : " Nathan propheta palam publiceque in facie regi David et commissum pronuntiavit er- rorem, et ipsum commississe non tacuit, et confessione correctum consequenter absolvit. Beatse memoriae Ambrosius, Mediolanensis sacerdos ecclesiae, ma- jorem Theodosium imperatorem a com- munione publico palamque suspendit, atque ad poenitentiam redegit regiam poteetatem. "Beatsa memorise papa Leo, sicut legitur, imperatorem Theo- dosium juniorem Ephesino latrocinio libere coarguit excedentem. Sanctse memoriae quoque papa Hilarius Anth- emium imperatorem, quum Philotheus Macedonianus ejus familiaritate sufful- tus diversarum conciiiabula nova sec- tarum in Urbem vellet inducere, apud beatum Petrum apostolum palam, ne id fieret, clara voce constrinxit in tantum, ut non ea facienda cum interpositione flacramenti idem promitteret imperator. Sanctae memorise nihilominus papa Simplicius, et post eum sanctae me- moriae papa Felix, non solum BasiHscum tyrannimi, sed etiam imperatorem Zenonem pro iisdem ipsis excessibus


auctoritate libera saepius increpasse noscuntur ; flectique potuisset, nisi Constantinopolitani praesulis accender- etur instinctu, qui particeps extemae communionis efifectus, necessario, in quod inciderat, jam fovebat, malens in suae praevaricationis obstinatione per- sistere, quam curandus ad salubria remeare, sicut ipse rerum probavit eventus." For a discussion of the authenticity of this passage, we would refer to Thiel's Preface to his edition of these letters.

2 Gelasius I., Ep. xxvii. 8 : " Cur igitur compassi non estis tantis fratri* bus vestris. Cur non adiistis imper- atorem ? Cur non Ecclesiae causam et sacerdotii miserabilem decolorationem continuatis vocibus deflevistis? aUe- gantes ; numquam de pontificibus nisi Ekiclesiam judicasse ; non esse human- arum legum de talibus ferre senten- tiam absque Ecclesiae principaliter constitutis pontificibus : obsequi solere principes Christianos decretis Ecclesiae, non suam praeponere potestatem, epis- copis caput subdere principem solitum, non de eorum capitibus judicare."


/^






190 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [part III.


are not prepared to express a definite judgment upon the extent of the immunity which Pope Gelasius claims for ecclesi- astics : it is enough for our purpose to observe how vigorously f he repudiates the idea of the State having any authority over v. thepi, in matters, at any rate, belonging to the Church.

/^he theory of the relation of the two authorities, the

^ . Church and the State, is definitely set out in the fourth

- Tractate and the twelfth letter of Pope Gela siusT} Together

these furnish us with a statement of the actual spheres of

the two powers, and also with some explanation of the cause

their separation. Before the coming of Christ, Gelasius says,

lere were some who were justly and legitimately both kings and

^iests, such as Melchizedek; and Satan imitated this among

the unbelievers, — hence it was t^t the pagan emperors held

' the office of Pontifex Maximuaj The true and perfect king

and priest was Christ Himself, and in that sense in which His

people are partakers of Hj^ nature they may be said to be a

^ royal and priestly race. /But Christ, knowing the weakness of

^iv*'^ i human nature, and carefuOor the welfare of His people, separ-

/ </^ted the two offices, giving to each its peculiar fimctions and

duties. Thus th e Christia n emperor needs the ecclesiastic for

^ t he attainment of eternal life, and the ecclesiastic depends upon

the government of the emperor in temporal things.^ There



y\


J\


^ Gelasius I., Tractatus iv. 11: "Quodsi haec tentare formidant, nee ad suae pertinere cognoscunt modulum potestatis, cui tantum de humanis rebus judicare permissum est, non etiam prse- •esse divinis ; quomodo de his, per quos divina ministrantur, judicare prae- sumunt ? Fuerint heec ante adventum Chi'isti, ut quidam figuraliter, adhuc tamen in camalibus actionibus con- stituti, pariter reges exsisterent et pariter sacerdotes, quod sanctum Mel- chisedech fuisse sacra prodit historia. Quod in suis quoque diabolus imitatus est, utpote qui semper quae divine cultui convenirent sibimet tyrannico spiritu vindicare contendit, ut pagani imperatores iidem et mayimi pontifices dicerentur. Sed quum ad verum ven-


tum est eumdem regem atque ponti- ficem, ultra sibi nee imperator ponti- ficis nomen imposuit, nee pontifex regale fastigium vindicavit : (quamvis enim membra ipsius, id est, veri regis atque pontificis, secundum participationem naturae magnificae utrumque in sacra generositate sumpsisse dicantur, ut simul regale genus et sacerdotale sub- sistant) : quoniam Christus memor fragilitatis humanae, quod suorum saluti congrueret, dispensatione mag- nifica temperavit, sic actionibus propriis dignitatibusque distinctis officia potes- tates utriusque discrevit, suos volens medicinali himiilitate salvaii, non hu- mana superbia rursus intercipi : ut et Christiani imperatores pro aetema vita pontificibus indigerent, et pontifices pro






CHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE.


191


are, then, two authorities by which chiefly the world is ruled,^ the sacred authority ot tne prelates ana tne royal power ; but the burden laid upon the priests is the heavier, for the y will liave to* give account m the divine judgment, even for the kings of men : thus it is that the emperor lo oks to them tor t he means of his salvation, and subm its to th em and to their judgment in sacred matters. The authority of the emperor is derived from the divme order, and the rulers of religion obey his laws: l^e should therefore the more zealously obey them. If the bishop 'IS silent when he ough t to speak for the divme religion he will run great danger, and so also Will he who contemns this authority instead of obeying it. If the fai thful owe obedience to all pries t s, how much more do they o we^ j; th e bishop of that see which Grod has set over s^ \ l priests.^

The most important points in these definitions of the char- acter and relation of the two powers are, first, the dogmatic^ statement and careful explanation of the fact that in Christian


\^


f"


temporalium cursu rerum imperialibus dispositionibus uterentiir : quatenus spiritalis actio a camalibus distaret in- cursibus, et 'Deo militans minime se negotiis ssecularibus implicaret/ ac vicissim non ille rebus divinis prsesidere videretur, qui esset negotiis ssecularibus implicatus : ut et modestia utriusque ordinis curaretur, ne extolleretur utroque suffultus, et competens quali- tatibus actionum specialiter professio aptaretur."

^ Gblasius I., Ep. xii. 2 : "Pietatem tuam precor, ne arrogantiam judices divinse rationis officium. Absit, quseso, a Romano principe, ut intimatam suis sensibus yeritatem arbitretur injuriam. Duo quippe sunt, imperator auguste, quibus principaliter mundus' hie regitur : auctoritas sacrata pontificum, et regalis potestas. ^ In quibus tanto gravius est pondus sacerdotum, quanto etiam pro ipsis regibus hominum in divino reddituri sunt examine rationem. Nosti enim, fill clementissime, quod licet prsesideas humano generi digni- tate, rerum tamen prsesulibus divin- arum devotus coUa submittis, atque


\'


ab eis causas tuae salutis exspectas, inque sumendis coelestibus sacramentis eisque ut competit disponendis, subdi te debere cognoscis religionis ordine potiua quam preeesse, itaque inter haec ex il- lorum te pendere judicio, non illos ad tuam velle redigi voluntatem. Si enim quantum ad ordinem pertinet publics^ disciplinae, cognoscentes imperium tibi supema dispositione collatum, legibus tuis ipsi quoque parent religionis anti- stites, ne vel in rebus mundanis exclusae yideantur obviare sententiae ; quo, oro te, decet afifectu eis obedire, qui prse- rogandis venerabilibus sunt attributi mysteriis ? Proinde sicut non leve dis- crimen incumbit pontificibus, siluisse pro divinitatis cultu, quod congruit ; ita his, quod absit, non mediocre periculum* est, qui, quum parere debeant, des- piciunt. Et si cunctis geueraliter sac- erdotibus recte divina tractantibu& fidelium convenit corda submitti, quanto potius sedis illius prsesuli con- sensus est adhibendus, quem cunctis sacerdotibus et Divinitas summa voluit praeeminere, et subsequens Ecclesis& generalis jugiter pietas celebravit?"







192 THE NEW TESTAMENT AND THE FATHERS. [PART III.

(^ciety the spiritual and the temporal powers are intrusted to 'two different orders, each drawing its authority from God, each supreme in its own sphere, and independent, within its own sphere, of the other. We shall have frequent occasion in later chapters to observe the importance of this conception of a two- fold authority in society — this attempt to divide the whole field of human activity into two separate parts, and to establish an independent authority for each part. "We shall see how the ninth-century writers in particular take these statements as the normal expression of their own position, and we shall have to consider how this is related to the theory of the later Middle Ages. But, secondly, it is necessary to observe that Gelasius ^ is also conscious of the fact that while these two authorities are

each independent of the other, and supreme in their own spheres,

they are also dependent upon each other, and cannot avoid V^* relations with each other ; s o that while each is supreme in i ts ^ own sphere, each is also subordinate in rel ation to the other s phere . The king is Subject to IM bisnop in spiritual matters, the bishop to the king in temporal matters. Gelasius is con- scious of the fact that no division between the two powers can be complete — that we are compelled to recognise the fact that each has, in certain relations, authority over the other; and, more than this, we may say that Gelasius perhaps feels that the question which is the greater of the two cannot be wholly I .avoided. He restricts himself, indeed, to arguing that the burden laid upon the ecclesiastics is the heavier ; but we can see in his words the beginning of a tendency whose ultimate development we shall have to trace in the scholastic writers. The definitely dualistic theory of authority in society has rarely been more clearly set out than by Gelasius, but his definitions show us the difficulties with which that theory >has constantly to contend.

In the Fathers, then, we see clearly the first development of

those difficult questions concerning the relations of the temporal

and spiritual authorities in society, round which so much of medi-

j sdvel political theory was to take shape. There can, we think,

be little doubt that in the end nothing contributed so much to

« emancipate the judgment of theologians from the tendency to






>


CHAP. XV.] RELATION OF CHURCH AND STATE. 193

^_^. recognise an absolute authority in the monarch, as the clearly<^ -^M^felt necessity of defending the independence of the Church.^ It was this, probably more than any other single cause, which compelled the ecclesiastical thinkers to analyse again, and more «-^^ completely, the source and character of civil authority. There is, indeed, in the Fathers little trace of any very direct connection between the general course of political theory and these questions of the relations of Church and State, though . it is noteworthy that St A mbrose , who is the first careful I exponent of the independence of ^he Church, is also that ^ one of the Fathers who seems most conscious of the limita- -r^ tions of the imperial authority even in secular matters. But we think that it is very necessary to take account of the patristic theory of the relations of Church and State ; for, however little they may have anticipated the ultimate signif- icance of these questions, we, when we look back from th^ standpoint of the ninth century or of the later Middle Ages^ can see that here are the beginnings of one of the mostf L>

  • important elements of the later political theory.


VOL. I. N










PAET lY.

THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE NINTH CENTURY.


CHAPTEE XVL

NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY.

We have examined the history of the political theory of the ancient world in its last stages, and the modifications intro- duced into this theory by Christianity. It is, we think, necessary for the proper understanding of the course of political theory to keep very clearly before us the fact that the political theory of the Fathers is that of the ancient world, . that the modifications introduced by Christianity are to be regarded rather as modifications of detail than as completely or fundamentally changing the conceptions which were already current. Unless we are entirely mistaken, the Fathers take the framework of their political theory whole and ready-made from their predecessors and contemporaries, and do but fit into this framework' such conceptions as are to be regarded as in some sense peculiar to themselves. As w6 have endeavoured to ' show, their peculiar conceptions are, except in regard to two subjects, not very important in character. The two exceptions to this general principle are to be found, first, in the turn they give to the theory of the sacred character of government, and, second, in their development of the relation ^ between the temporal or civil and the religious or ecclesiastical / powers in society. Here, indeed, they present to us the be-






196 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [pART IV.

ginnings of modes of thougKt of the greatest historical sig- nificance, — modes of thought whose development and modifica- tions we shall have to trace in considerable detail.

The Christian Fathers cannot be regarded as political phil- osophers, but their theory is constantly and organically related to a system of political thought which, whatever its merits or truth, may be regarded as a philosophical system, the system which centres in the theory of natural law and the contrast between the conventional and the natural state. The Fathers accept these theories, and, as we have endeavoured to show, it is only in relation to these that their own conceptions become intelligible.

"When we pass to the political theory of the ninth century, we find ourselves in an atmosphere wholly different. The elements of public life are altered, the conceptions which dominate men's minds are in some most important respects new and strange; we can never forget that the barbarians have overthrown the old civilisation of the West. They may sometimes deck themselves in the trappings of the old world, they are glad to use old names and to claim the titles of ancient offices, but the world has changed. St Gregory the Great or St Augustine may have been very different men from the Eoman citizens of the Eepublic or the Early Empire, but still they were primarily Eomans, members of the ancient common- wealth, sharers in the ancient culture, while the greatest j ecclesiastics of the ninth century, ^Jlciiis* HiscJ355LP^ fiheims, lor HrOibanus MauruSj are at bottom men of the new Teutonic tradition, also no doubt the heirs of what had survived of the culture of the ancient world, but still primarily men of the new world. What is true- even of the great ecclesiastics is still more obviously true of the greatest laymen. The great Charles himself may be the " Augustus," the great and " peace- able" emperor; but he is really the head of the Franks, the representative, the repository of the tradition of the greatest and most powerful of the new Teutonic races ; a great man, a i great ruler, but still a barbarian.

And the new world is governed by new traditions, new con- ceptions of life and of law, of the meaning and character of






CHAP. XVI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 197

the social organisation. Not indeed that there is as yet much new theory — the time for that has not yet come — but new tradi- tions, new customs, a new sense of the relations between the different members of the State, these meet us at every turn. The world in which we find ourselves in the ninth century is a new world, is indeed the world as we know it now, for it cannot be seriously pretended that between the ninth century and the twentieth there is such interruption of continuity even as there is between the sixth century and the ninth. When we study the Carolingian writers, we feel at once that we are studying the writings of men whose tradition of society and government is that out of which our own has directly and immediately grown. And yet there are in the social and political theory of the ninth century older elements. There is a great gulf between the Teutonic societies of the Middle Ages and the ancient empire, but there are many relations!, many traditions which have been carried over from the one to the other. The new society has its own distinctive tradi- tions, its own individual characteristics ; but the men who give expression to these, the articulate representatives of the new society in literature, have inherited from the past traditions and theories which profoundly influence the new society : they have inherited a framework of political theory into which, in the end, they v^ill fit their own independent political and social conceptions. The ninth-century writers are Teutonic politicians, but they are obviously also the disciples of the Western Fathers. Indeed they are always trying to bring their own conceptions into harmony with the theories of the Fathers. They seem instinctively to recognise the fact that they have no formal theory of their own, and constantly fall T)ack upon the Fathers, St Ambrose, St Augustine, St Gelasius, St Gregory, or St Isidore, to find a reasoned expression of their own convictions.

At the same time, their own conceptions are often very different from those of the Fathers, and it is largely to this cause that we may attribute that appearance of incoherence, or even self-contradictoriness, which is perhaps the first char- acteristic which we notice when we study this literature. The






198 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [PART IV.

truth is, that some centurias were still to pass before, in the hands of the scholastic writers, the Teutonic traditions and the general principles of the political theory of the Fathers and the Eoman Jurists were to be reduced to one coherent whole.

The Fathers, as we have said, may not be political philos- ophers, but in reading them we feel the presence of a great framework of political theory to which even their most incidental phrases are related. The Schoolmen of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries in their turn produced a complete system of political theory by which we may again interpret even the most para- doxical of their phrases. But the vn-iters of the ninth century are n either original politicdl philosophers nor are they as yet fully conscious of the nature of the theory which lay behind the phrases of the Fathers. They are interested in, they are indeed profoundly concerned with, the solution of the in- numerable difficulties which presented themselves to the new civilisation of Europe; they are full of interest, and often exhibit a considerable analytical power in dealing with such questions as the nature of the royal power, the relation of the civil power to the ecclesiastical, the nature of the origin and authority of law, and they eagerly lay hold of any straw of traditional authority, or explanation, in the Fathers, or in the remains of the ancient jurisprudence, which may assist them in the practical solution of their difficulties. But they do not go beyond the practical use of the writings of the Fathers : they are not concerned with, or mterested in, the question of a general and systematic philosophy of political and social relations.

We shall therefore find that there is much less of reference in the ninth-century writers to the questions of natural law, the natural condition, the relation between natural and conventional institutions, than in the Fathers. All this we shall find again when we come to discuss the scholastic political theory, but in the ninth century there is comparatively little reference to these matters. Their treatment of political theory is concerned mainly with questions regarding the nature and source of authority, secular and ecclesiastical, and the relations of these authorities to each other. This does not mean that they denied


CjOOQIC 


CHAP. XVI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 199

the truth of the conceptions of the earlier writers; on the contrary, as we shall see, so far as they do refer to such general questions as those which we have mentioned, they accept the views, they reproduce the phrases, of the Fathers.

There is only one aspect of the patristic theory of the natural conditions of human nature which has an important place in the ninth-century writings, and thatis the theory of the natural equality^and liberty of man. Here it is evident that the ninth- century writers not only reproduce the views of the Fathers, but that they do this with intelligence and conviction. They find the authority for their view largely in those passages from St Gregory the Great's writings which we have in former chapters had to consider carefully ; but it is clear that the ,view of St Gregory the Great and the other Fathers is one which is firmly held and understood by them as being the foundation of their conception of human nature in society.

One of the most representative passages in the literature of the ninth century dealing with this subject is to be found in Jonas of Orlea ns* treatise for the instruction of the layman. He warns his readers lest they should mistake the differences of worldly dignity and wealth for a real difference in nature. Human nature always remains egual in^its^character, whatever may Be ihe difference" of wealth or education. It is only a foolish anHTmpious pride which causes men to forget these things. Jonas justifies himself in this view by quoting the famous phrase of StG^regory^e Great, " Omnes nanaque homines nsitura aequales sumus," and urges masters to treat their slaves with someTIuimanity, quoting from St Paul, and from a sermon attributed to St Augustine, in which he dwells on the brother- hood of Christian men by grace.^ The same sentiments are

^ Jonas of Orleans, ^fiJJOifiti^uJLiaae pia prselatione et gubematione tuer-

. L^io^ ii. 22 : " Cavendum his qui etur ; ita tamen ut natura semper

praesimt, ne sibi subjectos, sicut ordine, sequalis agnosceretur. Quod cum ita

ita natura inf eriores se esse putent ; sit, multi rebus perituris, et cito prseter-

provida namque dispensatione divina labentibus tumentes, tam eos, quibus

actum est, ut mortalis a mortali, non prsesunt, quam etiam eos, quos potentia

natura, sed quadam mundana digni- et honoribus, et divitiis pnecedunt, sibi

tate inferior, ut pote imbecillis a valido natura eequales non recognoscunt ; et






200 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [PART iv.


to be found in another treatise of Jonas, " De Institu tione B^a/' in which he admonishes the king to appoint such ofBcers as will always remember that the people of Christ over whom they are placed are by nature equal to them.^

We find another careful statement and exposition of this con- ception of the equality of human nature in the writings of Agobard^ Archbish op of Lyons . In a letter or short treatise on the baptism of those who were slaves of Jews he protests strongly against some regulations of the Emperor Lewis the Pious, which, as Agobard understood, would have prevented the baptism of such slaves without the consent of their masters, and he does this on the ground that all men are of one race, one descent, one condition.^ But we shall come back to this passage in dealing with the question of slavery.

HrabanusMftuius, again, quotes St Gregory the Great, Moralia, xxi. 15, in his Commentary on the Book of Genesis,* and Hi ncmar of Bhe ims quotes the same passage, and also Moralia, xxvi. 26, which expresses much the same sentiments.*

It is interesting to observe that the conviction of the inalien-


8i verbis agnoscimt, afifectione tamen non agnoscunt. Quod vitium ex fonte superbise emanare manifestum est. Cur enim dominus et servus, dives et pauper, natura non sunt sequales, qui unum Deum non acceptorem person - arum habent in coelis."

Jonas then quotes St Paul, Col. iv. 1, and then St Qregory, Moral., xxi. 16 : " Potentibus viris magna est virtus humilitatis, considerata sequalitas con- ditionis. Omnes namque homines, natura aequales sumus," &c.

He then quotes Pseudo Augustine (a passage to which we have before referred, see p. 116) on the harsh treat- ment of slaves. Notice especially : " Et quod magis dolendum est, Christianus dominus Christiano in his diebus servo non parcit, minime respiciens, quod si servus est conditione, gratia tamen frater est. Etenim similiter Christum induit, iisdem participat sacramentis, eodem quo et tu utitur Deo Patre, cur te non utatur ut fratre."


Jonas concludes : " Hia et caeter- orum divinorum eloquiorum senten- tiis, potentes et divites edocti, agnos- cant et servos suos, et pauperes sibi natura sequales. Si igitur servi dom- inis natura aequales sunt, utique quia sunt, non se putent impune domini laturos, dum turbida indignatione et concitanti animi furore adversus errata servorum inflammati, circa eos aut in ssevissimis verberibus csedendo, aut in membrorum amputatione debilitando, nimii existimt, quoniam unum Deum habent in coelis. Eos vero qui in hoc saeculo infirmos abjectosque cultu, et cute et opibus se impares conspiciunt, natura pares et aequales sibi esse prorsus agnoscant." 4

^ Jonas of Orleans, De Inst. Reg., v.

» M. G. H. Ep., V. ; Agobard of Lyons, Ep. vi.

' Hrabanus Maurus, In Genesim II. Q. viii.

  • Hincmar, Opus Iv. Capit. xiv. ; and

De Regis Persona, 3.






CHAP. XVI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 201

able natural equality of human nature has even found a place in the technical legal documents of the time. In the preface to a collection of capitularies issued by the Emperor Lewis the ^ Pious, it is interesting to read a formal recognition by the emperor of his equality in condition with other men/ and in a collection made from the canons of various councils we have the same sentiment expressed at greater length and in more detail, and Christian men, whether lay or clerical, are warned to behave towards those who are their inferiors with mercy, for they should remember that they are their brethren, and have one Father, that is, God, and one Mother, that is, the Holy Church.2

The theory of human equality is treated most fully in relation to the institution of slavery. In the ninth century we find again that apparently paradoxical combination of a theory of equality with an almost universal acquiescence in the institution of slavery. The explanation is the same in this case as that which we have already considered in the Fathers, namely, that slavery is a disciplinary check upon the licence and disorder of sinful men. There is one writer, indeed, the author of the ' Via Eegia,' Smaragdus, the abbot of St Michael in the diocese of Verdun, whose attitude to the institution is different, but it will be best to leave him till we have con- sidered the general position of the ninth centiiry.

Human nature is recognised by all the writers who refer to the matter as being equal. We have already quoted

  • M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. agant et misericorditer eos tractent,

No. 137, Hludowici Proemium Gen. sive in exigendis ab eis operibus,

ad Cap. tarn Eccl. quam Mundana: sivi in accipiendis tributis et qui-

" Nobis prsecipue — qui ceteris mortali- busdam debitis ; sciantque eos fratres

bus conditione sequales existimus et suos esse et unum patrem secum habere

dignitate tantum regiminis superem- Deum, cui clamant * Pater noster, qui

inemus." es in coelis,' unam matrem sanctam

2 M. fit, H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. ecclesiam, quae eos intemerato sacri

No. 164, Cap. e Couciliis Excerpta, 9 : fontis utero gignit. Disciplina igitur

•^*Quia ergo constat in gecclesia diver- eis misericordissima et gubematio op-

sarum conditionum homines esse, ut ortuna adhibenda est; disciplina, ne

sint nobiles et ignobiles, servi, coloni indisciplinate vivendo auctorem suum

inquilini et cetera hujusoemodi nomina, offendant ; gubematio, ne in cotidianis

oportet ut quicumque eis prselati sunt vitae commeatibus prselatorum admin-

clerici sive laici, clementer erga eos iculodestitutifatescant." Cf. clause 12.






202 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.

a passage from Jonas of Orleans^ which illustrates this, and we may now consider that passage from Agob ardL of Lyons to which we before referred. In this passage Agobard expresses very clearly both the principle of the equality of the origin and condition of the human race and the justification of slavery as being caused by sin. God is the creator of all mankind, having formed the first man and woman, and from them all men are descended : it is in conse- quence of men's sins and of the secret judgment of God that some men are exalted and others placed under the yoke of slavery. But while God has thus ordered that men should serve each other with their bodies, He does not allow the inner man to be subject to any one but Himself. The inner man is free.2 It is for this reason that Agobard protests so strongly against the probihition of the baptism of slaves without the consent of their masters. Men, that is, are by nature equal, and this equality continues in the soul of man, whatever may be his external condition. Agobard reproduces the view of the Fathers with hardly any change. Slavery is not, as we might say, natural, but is an institution adapted to the actual condition of human nature.^


1 See p. 199.

2 M. G. H. Ep., V. ; Agobard of Lydns, Ep. vi. : "Denique ^t pie con- siderantibus perspicuum est, quod unus omnipotens Deus, omnium cou- ditor et moderator justissimus, qui primum hominem de limo formavit et de costa ejus adjutorium illi simile sibi fecit, quique ex eis omne genus humanum, quasi ex uno fonte et una radice propagavit, omnes unius con- ditionis fecerit. Et licet peccatis exi- gentibus justissimo et occultissimo ejus judicio, alii diversis honoribus sub- limati, alii servitutis jugo depressi sunt, ita tamen a servis corporale ministerium dominis exhiberi ordin- averit, ut interiorem hominem ad imaginem suam conditum nulli homi- num, nulli angelorum, nulli onmino creaturse, sed sibi soli voluerit esse subjectum. Unde in lege sua de hac


mentis servitute, quae illi tantum debetur, mandavit: 'Dominum Deum tuum timebis et illi soli servies.' Et apostolus eumdem interiorem hominem ab omni sexu diversitate, ab omni conditionis et generis distantia liberum esse demonstrans ita docet" (quotes Col. iii. 9, 11). "Cum ergo hi qui ad baptismum veniunt per agnitionem creatoris in interiore homine, qui ab omni servitutis conditione liber est, renoventur, quae ratio esse potest, ut id servi absque permissione dominorum suorum consequi prohibeantur, nee servire eis Deo liceat, nisi licentiam ab hominibus impetraverint ? "

3 Cf. M. G. H. Ep., V. ; Agobard of Lyons, Ep. iv. ; ** De qua re ego quidem tsJem teneo rationem : omnem profecto hominem creaturam Dei esse, et in unoquoque homine, quamvis servo, majorem portionem habere dominum






CHAP. XVI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY,


203


Alcuin and Hrabanus Maurus contrast the primitive domina- tion of man over the irrational animals with the later rule of man over man, and trace slavery either to iniquity or adversity, and cite the legal explanation of the condition of the slave, servtis, as that of one who might have been slain, but has been spared (servatm)} It is necessary to observe that Hrabanus Maurus


Deum, qui in utero creavit, ad lucem hujus vitae produxit, conoessam vitam custodivit, sanitatem servavit, quam iUum qui viginti aut triginta Bolidis datis fruitur corporis ejus servitio. Nee est qui dubitet quod unusquisque ser- Yus, membrorum corporis opera camali domino debens, mentis religionem soli debeat creatori. Propter quod omnes sancti pnedicatores, socii apostolorum . . . omnes baptizaverunt, onmes' in uno corpore redigerunt, onmeeque fratres et filios Dei esse docuerunt, ita tamen ut unusquisque in quo vocatus est, in hoc permaneret, non studio sed necessitate. Sed et si qui possent liberi fieri, magis u^r- entur. Im-promptu est etiam ratione coUigere si qui ethnicorum ad Christ- um fugiunt, et non recoUigimus sed repudiamus propter camales dominos, esse impium et crudele cum humanse animse nullus esse possit dominus nisi conditor."

^Alcuin, Inter, et Resp. in Librum Geneseos, Inter. 278 : " Filii Jacob interrogati quid opens haberent, responderunt : Pastores ovium sumus, sicut et patres nostri. Quare Pat- riarchos primos, pastores ovium et non Reges gentium fuisse legimus? R. Quia sine uUa dubitatione justa servituB, et justa est dominatio, cum pecora homini serviunt; et homo pecoribus dominatur. Sic enim dictum est homini cum crearetur. ' Faciamus hominem ad imaginem et similitudinem noetram, et habeat potestatem . . . omnium quae sunt super terram.' Ubi insinuatur rationem debere dom- inari irrationali vitae. Servum autem hominem vel iniquitas fecit vel adver-


sitas. Iniquitas quidem sicut dictum est : " Maledictus Chanaan, erit servus fratribue suis." Adversitas vero, sicut accidit ipsi Joseph, ut Tenditus a fratri- bus servus alienigenae fieret. Itaque primos servos, quibus hoc nomen in Latina lingua inductum est, bella fecerunt ; cum enim homo ab homine superatus, jure belli possit occidi, quia servatus est, servus est appeUatus. Inde et mancipia, quia sunt manu capta."

Hrabanus Maurus, In Genesim IV. cap. ix. : " Commendatur in patri- archis, quod pecorum nutritores erant a pueritia sua, et parentibus suis, et merito. Nam haec est sine uUa dubi- tatione justa servituB et justa domi- natio, cum pecora homini serviimt, et homo pecoribus dominatur. Sic enim dictum est cum crearetur : ' Faciamus hominem ad imaginem et similitudi- nem nostram, et habeat potestatem piscium maris et volatilium coeli et omnium pecorum quae sunt super terram.' Ubi insinuatur, rationem debere dominari irrationabili vitae. Servum autem hominem homini vel iniquitas, vel adversitas fecit. Iniquitas quidem, sicut dictum est : * Maledictus Chanaan; erit servus fratribus suis.' Adversitas vero, sicut accidit ipsi Joseph, ut venditus a fratribus, servus alienigenae fieret, itaque primos servos quibus hoc nomen inditum est in Latina lingua, bella fecerunt. Qui enim homo ab homine superatus jure belli posset occidi, quia servatus est servus appeUatus est. Inde et man- cipia, quasi manu capti sunt. Est etiam ordo naturalis in hominibus ut servi- ant viris feminae, et filii parentibus,






204 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [pabt iv.

in this passage also gives an explanation of slavery, which is obviously related to the Aristotelian theory, that slavery is the natural and justifiable result of the superiority of some men in reason over others. It will perhaps be remembered that in Cicero^ there are traces of the survival of this theory along- side of the doctrine of natural equality. Hrabanus recognises, indeed, that the actual facts of slavery are not always in accordance with this rational order, and exhorts the pious to submit in view of the rationally ordered and eternal felicity which awaits them. The two views are not wholly inconsistent with each other, the natural and fundamental equality does not exclude differences of capacity and intelligence. But this is not the usual line of thought of the Fathers or the ninth- century writers. It may be well to compare this with the parallel theory of a natural hierarchy of order in government, stated by St Gregory the Great,^ while in his general view government, or at least coercive government, is a consequence of sin.

Slavery, then, is just and lawful under the actual conditions of human nature. But this does not adequately represent the sanction given by the Church of the ninth century to the institution of slavery. A letter of Hrabanus to a certain Beginbaldus shows us that it was maintained that it was an irreligious as well as unlawful thing for a slave to attempt to escape from his master. Beginbaldus had asked Hrabanus whether it was lawful to say mass for a slave who died while escaping from his master. Hrabanus replies that he does not find any reason against this, and orders prayers for the slave unless he has committed some other crime. At the same time he admits that it is a grave sin to fly from one's master. He quotes the canon of the Council of Grangrse in which those who teach slaves to despise their masters and to fly from them are

quia et illic haec justitia est ut arum camalium diversitatem, ferunt

infirmior ratio serviat fortiori. Hsdc justi temporalem perveraitatem, in fine

igitur dominationibus et servitutibus habituri ordinatissimam et sen>piter-

clara justitia est, ut qui excellunt nam felicitatem."

ratione, excellant dominatione. Quod ^ See p. 11. -v

cum in hoc seou^o per iniquitatem ^ See p. 117.,^ { >► I ,

hominum perturbatur, vel per natur-






CHAP. XVI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY.


205


anathematised, and admits that he must be still more deserving of anathema who actually escapes from his master. But he also urges that the degree of the sin depends upon the reason of his flight, whether it is due to mere pride or to the cruelty of his master. The fugitive slave should be exhorted to return to his master, as Hagar did to Sarah, and Onesimus to Philemon.* We have already dealt with this canon ^ of Grangrae in our discussion of the Patristic theory of slavery, and it may be said in explanation of it that, considering the fact that tj|^ Church gave its sanction to the institution of slavery as a disciplinary institution, such a condemnation of those who incited slaves to fly was at least logically proper. But the letter of Hrabanus seems to indicate the presence among Christian men in the ninth century of a much harsher view. The question of Eeginbaldus clearly shows that it was held by some Christians that a slave who fled from his master was guilty of a mortal sin, and Hrabanus's answer makes it plain that though he thought that the precise degree or quality of


^ M. G. H. Ep., V. ; Hrabanus MauruB, Ep. 30: —

"V. De servo autem qui fugerit dominum suum, interrogabas, si ille in ipsa fuga mortuus fuerit, utrum liceret pro eo missas cantare aut psalmodias. Hoc in divinis libris non invenimus prohibitum, sed tamen scimus ab apos- tolls fortissime prseoeptum, ut servi subditi sint in omni timore dominis, non tantum bonis et modestis, sed etiam discolis, et obedientes illis fiant in omnibus.

In canone autem Gangrensis con- cUii ita scriptum est : ' Si quls servum sub pretextu divini cultus doceat dominum contempnere proprium, ut discedat ab ejus obsequio, nee ei cum benevolentia et omni honore deserviat, anlEkthema sit.' Unde datur inteUigi quod si ille anathema meruit, qui docet servum proprium dominum con- tempnere, et ab ejus obsequio recedere, quanto magis ille, qui dominum suum spemit et ejus servitio subdi noluerit ?


Sed tamen distantia est inter eum,. qui propter superbiam et ilium, qui propter necessitatem fugit, coactus crudelitate domini sui. Nam Agar famula- Sarse fugam iniit, affligente earn domina sua, sed angelo ammon- ente, ut revertereti!^ et fieret subjecta dominatrici suae, reversa est ad domi- nam suam. Sic et Honesimus servua Philemonis efiEugit a domino quo, sed Paulo apostolo docente credidit Christo et baptizatus est et sic per patrodnium apostoli restitutus est proprio domino.

Ammonendus est enim servus quilibet fugitivus per fideles Christi doctores, ubicumque fuerit inventus,, ut revertatur ad dominum suum et fiat ei subjectus, ne forte contempnens prseceptum domini, perpetuo anathem- ate percutiatur. Afbamen si in ipsa fuga obierit, orandum est pro eo, nisi forte aliquo crimine majore implicetur aut in perfidiam devolvatur, \mde fruc- tuosa pro eo non possit esse oratio."

2 See p. 121.






206 POLITICAL THEOKY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.

the sin depended upon the motive prompting the slave's escape, yet such an attempt was in itself sinful.

We may again find illustrations of the ecclesiastical view of slavery in the legislation of the Church as well as of the State with regard to the qualifications of those who were to be ad- mitted to ordination. We could quote a series of enactments from the Council of Frankfurt in 794 to the Council of Tribur in 895 by which the ordination of a slave is prohibited except with the consent of his master.^

The Council of Frankfurt requires the permission of the master,* but does not say whether the slave must be emanci- pated, but in all the other passages we cite it is laid down that the slave should only be ordained when he has been handed over by his master to the bishops to be free for the rest of his life, and in one passage the master is warned that he will then lose all rights over the slave.^ It is perhaps worth noticing, also, that in a letter or precept of Lewis the Pious the slave thus emancipated is warned that in the event of his sinning against the sacred orders which he has received, he will be obliged to return to his former slavery.*

According to one set of regulations, if a slave procures his ordination by fraud he is to be handed over to his master, or if he was ordained in ignorance of the fact that he was a slave, he may be retained in his office if his master consents, or his master may reclaim him as a slave.^

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. 28, 112, neorum tuorum necnon et de jure

114, 138, 173, 252; M. Q. H. Ep., monasteriorum, quae in tua diocoesi con-

V., Ep. var. 8. Cf. also Pseudo Isidore, stituta sunt, ad prsesbiteratus ordinem

Stephen, Dec. II. electum coram clero et plebe, prsesente

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL vol. i. et consentiente eo, cujus dominatui

No. 28, Synod Franc. : " De servis idem servus usque in id temporis erat

alienis : ut a nemine recipiantur neque addictus, a jugo servitutis absolvas et

ab episcopis sacrentur sine licentia perpetuo liberum efficias, ea tamen

dominorum." conditione, ut noverit se is qui libertate

' M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL vol. i. donatur in pristinam servitutis con- No. 112, Statu ta Rhispacensia, &c., 31. ditionem relapsurum, si sacri ordinia

  • M. G. H. Ep., V. ; Ep. Var. 8 : quern susoeperit praevaricator fuerit
    • Proinde has nostras imperialis et regise conprobatus."

auctoritatis Utteras tu8& sanctitati dan- ^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. voL i.

das decrevimus, per quas tibi et succes- No. 138, 6 : " Et si quilibet servus

soribus tuis talem concessam noveris dominum suum fugiens, aut latitans

potestatem, ut servum ecclesiasticum aut adhibitis testibus munere conductis

tam de tua parochia quam de sufiraga- vel corruptis aut qualibet calliditate






CHAP. XVI.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY.


207


It is perhaps deserving of notice that we find it alleged as a reason for such regulations, that it is improper that the service of God should be conducted by men of ignoble position. We have an excellent commentary on such a view in the very interesting account which Jonas of Orleans and Agobard of Lyons give of the common attitude of the wealthy and noble persons of their time towards the inferior clergy. Their ob- servations illustrate what seems to have been a real difiBculty of the time — a difiSculty which alone would have compelled the Church to enforce very strict rules about the condition of those who were to be admitted to orders. Jonas of Orleans gives us a very gloomy picture of the social condition of many of the clergy. They were often employed by wealthy laymen as their stewards, and were considered unfit to be their companions at table.i Agobard is equally gloomy, and even more vivid, in his picture. All great men, he says, have a domestic priest, not that they may obey him, but simply that he may be useful to them in performing religious services and in discharging any secular function to suit their convenience. When they want a domestic chaplain, he says, they bring to the bishop some slave whom they have brought up in their house or bought, and demand his ordination .^


vel fraude, ad gradus ecclesiastices pervenerit, decretum est ut deponatur, et dominus ejus eum recipiat. Si vero avus vel pater ab aUa patria in aliam migrans in eadem provincia filium genuerit, et ipse filius ibidem educatus et ad gradus ecclesiasticos promotus f uerit et utrum servus sit ignoraverit, et postea veniens dominus illius legi- bus eum adquisiverit, sancitum est ut, si dominus ejus illi libertatem dare voluerit, in gradu suo permaneat ; si vero eum catena servitutis a castris dominicis extrahere voluerit, ut gradum amittat; quia juxta sacros canones vilis persona manens sacerdotii dignitate fungi non potest." Of. St Gelasius, Ep. 21. See p. 122.

^ Jonas of Orleans, De Inst. Laicali, ii. 20: "Sunt etiam quidam sacer- dotes divitiis et honoribus mimdi carentes, qui adeo contemptui a


quibusdam laicis habentur, ut eos non solum administratores et pro- curatores rerum suarum faciant, sed etiam sibi more laicorutn servire compeUant, eosque convivas mensse suae habere dediguentur ; qui videlicet habere sacerdotes Nomine tenus sibi videri gestiunt, re autem ipsa propter quam habendi sunt, nolunt, talesque intercessores apud Deum habere vol- unt, quales esse prorsus despiciunt." 2 M. G. H. Ep., v.; Agobard, Ep. 11 : "Unde et contumeliose eos nom- inantes, quando volunt illos ordinari pr93sbiteros, rogant nos aut jubent, dicentes : * Habeo unum clericionem, quem mihi nutrivi de servis meis propriis aut beneficialibus sive pagen- sibus, aut obtinui ab illo vel illo homine, sive de illo vel illo pago, volo ut ordines eum mihi prsesbifcerum."






208 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

The Church of the ninth century acquiesced in the existence of slavery, and adapted its own legislation to this. It is well, however, also to observe that the influence of the Church seems still, as in the period of the later Empire, to tend towards a mitigation of the condition of slavery. The Church still con- tinijed to impose its own penalties upon those who killed the slave. We finc^ a Council of Maintz in 847 a.d. renewing the capons of the Councils of Agde and of EUiberis, which imposed the penalty of excommunication for certain periods upon those who killed their slaves intentionally or by accident.^ We have already considered that passage from the writings of Jonas of Orleans in which he protests agajast the harsh treatment of slaves.^ It is also interesting to find in the " Edictum Pistense " of 864 a revival of a regulation contained in a novel of Valen- tinian, by'which those who sold themselves or their children, because of their great poverty or in time of famine, could be redeemed at a price slightly higher than that for which they had sold themselves or their children.*

There is, as we have said, one writer in the ninth century who goes far beyond this in his attitude to slavery, and who seems to desire its abolition. This writer, SDaaragdijs, is the author of a little treatise or handbook, the * Via Eegia,' on the character and duty of the good king. We shall have occasion to refer to him again in connection with the theory of the royal power, though there is in this portion of his work little that •is very different from other treatises.

' 1 M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii No. decim solidos similiter recipiat ; aut si

248, 22. amplius, secundum suprascriptam

^ See p. 199. rationem augmentum pretii conse-

s M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. No. quatur. . . . Et si quia dixerit, quia

273, c. 34. "Tamen illud capitulum, non vult aut tempore famis aut pro

quod cum Sanctis ecclesiasticis regulis alia necessitate pretium suum dare pro

ex maxima parte concordari inven- libero homine, si semper ilium servum

imus, hie ponere necessarium duximus habere non debet, adtendat quid ei

in quo dicit : Ut quicumque ingenui Dominus per apostolum suum dicat :

filios suos, jquod et de ipsis liberis 'Qui habuerit,' inquiens, 'substantiam

hominibus, qui se vendunt, observari hujus mundi et viderit fratrem suum

volumus, qualibet necessitate seu necesse habere et clauserit viscera sua

famis tempore vendiderint ipsa ne- ab eo, non manet caritas Dei in eo.'"

cessitate compulsi, emptor, si quinque Cf. Nov. Valent., iii. Tit. xi., Interpre-

solidis emit sex recipiat ; si decem, duo- tatio.






CHAP, xyi.] NATURAL EQUALITY AND SLAVERY. 209

With regard to slavery the position of the treatise is dififerent. The author quotes a passage from Ecclesiasticus, which enjoins that a slave should be treated as one's own soul, as a brother,^ and entreats the king to forbid the making of slaves in the kingdom — that is, we suppose, he desires to prevent any of the subjects of the king from being enslaved by their fellow- subjects. Then, after quoting a number of passages from the canonical and apocryphal Scriptures of the Old Testament, on the subject of slavery, he urges that the Christian man should set his slaves at liberty, considering that it is not nature but sin that subjected men to each other, seeing that we were all created equal. He concludes by urging the king to honour God with his riches and slaves, by giving alms of the former and by setting the latter at liberty .2

We think that it is clear that the author of the treatise feels that there is something wholly unchristian in the slavery at least of Christian men, and that he would like to see this ended. He does not, indeed, actually ask the king to abolish the institution, though he does ask him to forbid the enslave- ment of any of his subjects ; but he does look upon it as being the true mode of honouring God, to set the slave at liberty. It is certainly interesting to find this view held in the ninth century, but we must not make any mistake : this view is not the normal one ; the premisses of Smaragdus are the same as those of the other ninth-century writers, but the conclusions deduced by him from them are different The theory of slavery in the ninth century is the same as that of the Fathers : slavery is not natural or primitive, but is a just punishment of man's sin, and a remedial discipline by which his vicious in- clinations may be restrained.

^ Smaragdus Abbaa, Via Kegia, 1. eraiiBquianonillieo8natura.8ubegit,Bed

^ Smaragdus Abbas, Via Eegia, 30 ; culpa ; conditione enim sequaliter creati

Prohibe ergo clementissime rex ; ne sumus, sed aliis alii culpa subacti. . , .

in regno tuo captivitas fiat. . . . Vere Honorifica ei^go, justissime ac piissime

obedire debet homo Deo et ejus prse- rex, pro onmibus Deum tuum, quia ut

«epta in quantum iUe possibilitatem scriptum est, 'Pro omnibus lionor4Acavit

•dederit, obedire. Et inter alia prse- te,' sive in servis tibi subactis, sive in

cepta salutaria, et opera recta, propter divitiis tibi concessis, ex illis liberos faci-

nimiam illius choritatem imusquisque endo, et ex istis eleemosynas tribuendo,

liberos debet dimittere servos, consid- praeceptis illius obedire non cesses."

VOL, I.






210


CHAPTER XVII.

THE DIVINE AUTHORITY OF THE KING.

We have seen that the ninth -century writers maintain the tradition of the natural equality of human nature — an equality which, in a certain sense, is permanent and inalienable; but

  • we have seen that this is not inconsistent with their main-

taining that slavery is a necessary and wholesome discipline. It is so also with government; in one sense it might seem that this is incompatible with the theory of the natural equality of man, but these writers look upon it as a necessary discipline by means of which life is preserved and order is maintained. The State is a divine institution; its coercive discipline may indeed be a consequencie of the Fall, but it is the divine remedy for the Fall, and as such it must be respected and obeyed by all men. We have seen that in some of the Fathers this concep- tion is developed into a theory that the person and authority of the ruler is so sacred that disobedience^ to him or* resistance to

^^^J^^-lM^^^*^ ^^^ eqiiivftlflnt. fn HisnhpHiftnpft anH rpaiftt^^pr^ tO

God Him self. By some of the Fathers the divine authority of the State is transferred whole and entire to the particular ruler* This view is in the ninth century formally held by many, perhaps indeed by all writers. But the actual conditions of the political life of the time often came into conflict with this view, and while the writers of the time may have continued to maintain it in form, they were in fact often compelled to adopt quite another attitude towards the head of the State. We also begin to find in them the influence of a tradition which does not descend from the ancient world. The ninth-century writers are for the most part ecclesiastics.






CHAP, xvn.] THE DIVINE AUTHORITY OF THE KING. 211

but they are also, at least in Northern Europe, men of the Teutonic tradition. And the Teutonic tradition of the authority of the king is not the same as that of the Latin Fathers.

The conflict of these ideas is the cause of much apparent incoherence and inconsistency : we find the same man speaking at one time as though the divine authority of the king could never be resisted, at another time as if his authority were limited and restricted. The diffidulty also of defining the limits of the authority of the ecclesiastical and the civil powers produced a constant friction, which tended to destroy any unqualified theory of the absolute authority of the State.

We find but little speculation or theory as to the beginnings of society and the State, and what little there is, is obviously second-hand and borrowed from earlier writers. In a treatise attributed to Alcuin, * De Ehetorica et Virtutibus,' there is an interesting passage on the primitive conditions of human life, drawn, as the author says, from ancient sources, in which man is represented as having originally lived like the beasts, wan- dering about in the fields, without any rational or moral principle or rule of life. A great and wise man at last appears, and, recognising the qualities and capacities of human nature, gathers men together into one place, and thus brings them to live a peaceable and humane life.*

^ Alcuin, ' Dialogue De Rhetorica et res opportunitas animis inesset homin-

Virtutibus : ' " Carclus, Primum mibi, um, si quia earn posset elicere et prseci-

magister, hujus artis (vel studii) initium piendo meliorem reddere. Qui dispersos

pande. homines in agris et in tectis sylvestribus

^Alh, Pandam juxta auctoritatem abditos ratione quad&m compulit in

veterum. Nam fuit, ut fertur, quod- unumlocum,etcongregaviteosinunum,

dam tempus, cum in agris homines aliquam quietem inducens utilem atque

passim bestiarum more vagabantur, honestam; primo propter insolentiam

nee ratione animi quidquam, sed reclamantes, deinde propter rationem

pleraque viribus corporis adminis- atque orationem studiosius audientes,

trabant. Nondum divina religio non- ex feris et immanibus mites reddidit

dum humani officii ratio colebatur, et mansuetos. Ac mihi quidem videtur,

sed caeca et temeraria (dominatrix) domine mi rex, hoc nee tacita, nee

cupiditas ad se explendam viribus inops dicendi sapientia perficere

corporis abutebatur. Quo tempore qui- potuisse, ut homines a consuetudine

dam vir mftgnus et sapiens cognovit subito converteret et ad diversas vitae

quae materia et quanta ad maximas rationes traduceret."






212 POUTICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [PART IV.

We find a very similar account of the primitive condition of man in Hmba nus M aurus's ' De Universe/ taken from St Isidore of SeviUe. IJndertfie3efinition of "oppidum" he tells us that in the earliest times men were naked and unarmed and had no protection against the wild beasts, no shelter against the heat or cold, no safety against each other. As time went on they learned to make houses in which they could dwell in safety, and in this way towns began to spring up.^

We can scarcely found any conclusions on such scanty and incidental references to the beginnings of society ; it is evident that both the author of the *De Ehetorica' and Hrabanus M Maurus are simply writing down fragments of ancient descrip- . I tions of society, which they accept, but upon which they are not ^ reasoning. In themselves these statements are both too vague and too commonplace to enable us to fix very definitely the philosophic tradition to which we might say they belong. We can hardly go further than this, that they represent a tradition which held that behind the period of the organised society of men there lay a time when there was no fixed order among mankind. It is a state of nature, but not, so far as these passages go, a good or ideal state, but rather one of disorder and misery. It would agree well enough with the conditions of human life, as they might be pictured after sin and vice had come into the world, and before the great institutions, by which sin is controlled and checked, had been developed.

We have seen that the ninth-century writers maintain the

primitive or natural equality of men ; but they recognise that

the actual conditions of life demand government, as they justify

slavery. This is well expressed in a treatise of Hincnaarj)f

\ . Rheims. God has set diverse orders in the world, as is shown

^ Hrabanus Maurus, De Universo, hominibus satis erant tuti. Tandem

xiv. 1. " Oppidum quidam ab opposi- naturali soUertia speluncis silvestribus-

tione murorum dixerunt : aliiabopibus que tegumentis tuguria sibi et casas

recondendis, eo quod sit munitum : quod virgultis arundinibusque contexuerunt,

sit conventus in eo habitantium, et quo esset vita tutior, ne his, qui nocere

opem ferat mutuam contra hostem. possent aditus esset. Hsec est origo

Nam primum homines, tanquam nudi oppidorum, qu83, eo quod opem darent,

et inermes, nee contra belluas prsesidia idcirco oppida nominata dixerunt.*'

habebant, nee receptacula frigoris et See p. 172. caloris, nee ipsi inter se homines ab






CHAP. XVII.] THE DIVINE AUTHORITY OF THE KING. 213

by the apostolic exhortation to obey kings and rulers for God's sake ; for although, as St Gregory says, nature brought forth ' all men equal, sin has put some below others, and this by / God's dispensation, who has ordained that one man should be ruled by another.^ Indeed the writers of the ninth century . reproduce the strongest phrases of the Fathers with refer- ^ ence to the dixiJaft JD^ture of the civil power. In the middle of the century we find this enunciated with great force in the * ^^j^^'tiila ^?tiPiP'^^'n ' These lament the disturbances and ^ ^> • discord in the kingdom, and complain that some men will not endure subjection to the king. They forget that, as St Paul says, all power is from God, and that he who resists the power resists the ordinance of Gk)d. God is indeed the true King of kings and Lord of lords, but He has ordained that the ruler is to be a true king and lord in God's place (vice sua) on the earth. The devil fell from heaven because he would not accept his subjection to his Creator ; and so he who will not recognise the power ordained by God in the world, makes himself the servant of the devil and the enemy of God.^


^ Hincmar of Rheims, Opus Iv. Capit. xiv. : " Ad quod instar sunt ordines in sseculo Dei ordinatione dis- tincti, fiicut monstrat apostolus, dicens : ' Subjecti estote onmi humanse creaturae propter Deum, sive regi tanquam prse- cellenti, sive ducibus tanquam ab eo missis ' (1 Pet. ii. 13). ' Liquet,' inquit beatus Gregorius (Moral., lib. xxi. c. 1.5), ' quod omnes homines natura sequales genuit sed variante meritorum ordine, alios aliis culpa postponit. Ipsa autem diversitas, quae accessit ex vitio, divino judicio dispensatur, ut quia omnis homo aeque stare non valet, alter regatur ab altero.' "

'"* M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. No. 272, Capitula Pistensia, i. : "Quia per discordiam et regnum istud tempor- ale imminuitur et pene desertum et setemum regnum perditum habemus, quia nee omnes reges esse possumus nee regem super nos a Deo constitutum — quia, sicut scriptum est, * imposuil


homines super capita nostra,' — * habere sustinemus, non attendentes, quia,' sicut dicit apostolus, * non est poteetas nisi a Deo, et qui potestati resistit, Dei ordinationi resistit' ; quoniam Deus qui essentialiter est * rex regum et dominus dominantium,' participatione nominis et numinis Dei, id est potestatis suae, voluit et esse et vocari regem et domin- um pro honore et vice sua regem in terris. Et sicut archangelus, qui uimc est diabolus, cum suis sequacibus, quia per humilitatis subjectionem conditqri suo subditus esse noluit et per aequali- tatem caritatis coangelis suis socius esse despexit, de coelo cecidit, ita et illi, qui potestati a Deo constitutse propter Deum et in Deo subjecti esse nolunt et pares vel cosequales in regno habere non sufferunt, per quam de- bitam subjectionem et parilem sequali- tatem Del amici et angelorum consortes esse poterant, subjecti diabolo et Dei inimici constituuptur."






214 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

^ These phrases can be paralleled over and over again in the

-7 Capitularies ^ and in the writers of the time, — Smaragdus,

f Sedulius Scotus, Jonas of Orleans, Hrabanus Maurus, Hincmar

of Eheims, Cathulf us.^ They represent the accepted view that

temporal authority is derived from Gk)d, and that all men must

obey the authority for the sake of God.

It is this conception which is embodied in the phraser used ^ hy r!fa^lftA.thA Great and his successors: "Karolus gratia Dei rex '* ; " Karolus §ef enissimus augustus, a Deo coronatus magnus pacificus imperator, Bomanum gubemans imperium, qui et per misericordiam Dei Rex Francorum atque Longobardorum " ; "Hludowicus, divina ordinante providentia imperator augus- tus"; "Hludowicus divino nutu coronatus."^ These phrases ^ serve to express the conception that it is God who is the ^ ultimate source of all authority. This is also, we venture to think, the conception which was ultimately conceived to be expressed in the consecration of the king or emperor at his coronation. We shall have a good deal to say about this later, for the mediaeval interpretations of the rite and of the part taken in it by the clergy are of considerable importance. For the present it is enough to observe that the introduction of ' a religious element into the solemn appointment of a king or emperor, while at first it probably meant little more than that the blessing of God was being invoked upon the monarch, was very soon taken to be symbolical of the fact that it is from God that authority came.*

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL Nos. 5, 290, rites. How far back this may have

293, 302. gone in the West we do not know :

r ^ E,g,f Smaragdus Abbas, Via Regia, the earliest coronation with religious

,18; Sedulius Scotus, De Rectoribus service of which there is trustworthy

Christianis, 1 and 19 ; Jonas of Orleans, evidence is that of Pippin in 752, and

^ De Inst. Kegia, 7, 8 ; Hrabanus Maurus, the earliest form of coronation service

' M. G. H. £p., V. 15, iii. ; Hincmar of in the West is that contained in the

Rbeims, De Regis Persona, 1, 8 ^ M. G. Pontifical of Egbert, which it is thought

^ H. £p., iv. Var. Car. Mag. Regn. 7. may have been in use in the first half

2 M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. voL L Nos. of the eighth century.

19, 45, 132, 134. We would refer the reader to the

  • From the time of the coronation of articles by the Rev. J. E. Brightman,

Leo II. as emperor in the year 473 a.d., on the Byzantine Imperial Coronations,

the appointment of the emperor in the and by the Rev. H. A. Wilson, on the

East was accompanied by some religious English Coronation Order, in the






CHAP, xvil] the divine authority OP THE KING. 215

The writers of the ninth century, then, maintain the tradition |^ of the Fathers, that the State is a religious institution, that the authority of the civil government is sacred, and that all Christian men should obey it, as^ representing the authority of God Himself. But they go much further than this. We have just considered a passage from the * Capitula Pistensia,' and we must now observe that the king is here spoken of as standing in , God's place (vice sua) in the world. Smaragdus uses an almost exactly similar phrase when he speaks of the king acting " pro vice Christi." ^ Sedulius Scotus calls the king the " Vicar of ^ God." 2 It is true that Sedulius calls him God*s vicar in the ^ government of the Church, a statement which we shall have to consider again in connection with the relations of the ecclesiastical and civil powers, — but probably he includes the State in the Church.

A writer called Catliullus, of whom little is known, and who is represented in literature only by a letter or short treatise,^ addressed to CJharle§..^the^reat, uses a similar phrase. Hc^ bids the king remember God always with fear and love, for ho^ stands in His place over all His members, to guard them and^ reign over them. The bishop is said to stand in the second place, to represent Christ.^ Our readers may remember that the writer known as Ambrosiaster expresses a similar thought when he says that the king, whom he calls the Vicar of God, has the "image of God," and the bishop has the "image of Christ." * Whether Cathulfus draws the phrase from Am-

  • Journal of Theological Studies' for praelatorum et subditorum tribuit, ut

April and July 1901, for a detailed dis- singulis personis et quse justa sunt

cussion of the exact character and sig- decemat, et sub sua dispositione prior

nificance of the ecclesiastical ceremony. ordo devote obediendo fideliter sub-

^ Smaragdus Abbas, Via Kegia, 18 : ditus fiat."

    • Fac quidquid potes pro persona quam ' M. Q. H. Ep., iv. Variorum Carolo

gestas, pro ministerio regali quod portas, Magno Regnante Scriptse, 7 : "Memor

pro nomine Christiani quod habes, pro esto ergo semper, rex mi, Dei regis tui

vice Christi qua fungeris." cum ^imore et amore, quod tu es in

'^ Sedulius Scotus, De Bectoribus vice illius super omnia membra ejus

Christianis, 19 : ** Oportet enim Deo custodire et regere, et rationem red^

amabilem regnatorem, quem divina dere in die judicii, etiam per te. Et

ordinatio tanquam vicarium suum in episcopus est in secundo loco, in vice

regimine Ecclesise suse esse voluit, et Christi tantum est."

potestatem ei super utrumque ordinem * See p. 149.


\






216 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

brosiaster we cannot tell, — it is at least possible that it is from him that the phrases which speak of the king acting in God's place come; but it is also possible that this method of speaking was traditional among Christians, though it has not come down to us in any patristic writer of the West, except Ainbrosiaster. It is important to observe the phrase the "Vicar of God." We shall presently have to consider its meaning in these writers in relation to the Church : in a later volume we shall see that it came to mean a great deal in the controversy between Church and State. It is significant for us for the moment as representing in the most terse form the universal judgment of the time that the king is the representative of God, — that it is from God that he draws his authority.

The king thus stands in God's place, is His representative on earth, and the writers of the ninth century use very strong phrases to express their condemnation of rebellion against his authority. The Council of/ Main tz in 847 inserts in its decrees a very strong condemnation of conspiracy and rebellion against the lawful authorities in Church and State, and threatens those ^ guilty of such acts with excommunication.^ Some of the manu- scripts which contain the documents of this council say that these sentences come from an epistle of Hrabanus Maurus. In one of his letters, written some years earlier, he speaks very strongly on the wickedness of revolt, and enforces this by a number of quotations from the Old and New Testa- ments, citing especially the conduct of David, who would not raise his hand against the Lord's anointed, and recounting

^ M. O. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. nominetur. Unde statuimuB atque

No. 248, Concilium Moguntinum. 5. auctoritate ecclesiastica confirmamus

De conspiratione : '^ Si yero pax et eos, qui contra regem yel ecclesiasticas

Concordia summum inter homines et dignitates sive reipublicae potestates

maxime Christianos bonum judicatur in unoquoque ordine legitima disposi-

et prsemio summo remunerandum, id tione constitutas conjurationes et

est, ut ejus merito filii Dei vocemur, conspirationes rebellionis et repug-

nonne, e contrario discordise et dissen- nantiae faciunt, a communione et

sionis summum est malum et summa consortio catholicorum veram pacem

poena plectendum? Ita ut sapiens amantium summovendos et, nisi per

dicat animam Domini ilium detestari, poenitentiam et emendationem paci se

qui inter fratres discordiam seminat ecclesiasticse incorpaverint, ab omnibus

atque ideo filius diaboli non immerito filiis pacis sancimus extorres."






CHAP. XVII.] THE DIVINE AUTHORITY OP THE KING. 217


the judgments that overtook several of those who in later times rose in insurrection against their legitimate lords.^

Hincmar of Eheims uses equally strong phrases on the neces- sity of obedience. In his treatise, * JDe FiH a ri grnlo Reg^ Ser- * vanda,' he also cites the example of David's conduct towards Saul as the true model of right conduct,^ and then quotes those very strong words of St Gregory the Great on which we com-/^ mented in a former chapter, in which he warns subjects that if they transgress against their rulers, they transgress against God, who set them over men.^ In one of his letters he speaks more directly and strongly still. Nothing, he says, is done in the^ world except by God, or by His just permission. When kings, | therefore, reign by God's appointment {ex illo) it is the work of / God's ^ercy, that their people may be safe. When they rule, not by his appointment {non ex illo), but by His perinission, it is God's punishment on a sinful people. The true (believers do. not resist the power, which is either given or permitted by God,, but, humbling themselves under God's hand, give thanks to Him

Ep.,


^ M. G. H. Ep., V. ; Hrabanus Maurus, Ep. 15, ill. : *'Quod autem regise dignitati honor sit a subditis offerendus, et quod Deo displiceat con- tumatia subditorum, ostendit scriptura divina tarn in sententiis quam etiam in exemplis. Nam in Exodo scriptum est : * Diis non detrahes et principi populi tui non maledices.' . . .

"Horum ergo casum atque ruinam pertimescens David unctus jam rex non ausus est levare manum suam contra Saul regem, sed viris illis, qui eum persuaserunt, ut Saul quasi sibi traditum in deserto Engathi vel in deserto Ciph percuteret atque interi- meret, respondit dicens, ' Piropitius sit mihi Dominus, ne faciam banc rem domino meo Christo Domini, ut mittam manum meam in eum, quoniam Christus Domini est.' Et item : * Quis inquit, extendit manum suam in Christum Domini et innocens erit ? Vivit Dom- inus, quia nisi Dominus percusserit eum, aut dies ejus venerit ut moriatur, aut in proelium descendens perierit, propitius sit mihi Dominus, ne ex-


tendam manum meam in Christum Domini.' . . . Nam tyranni, qui contra dominos legitimos subita insolentia se serexerant, non impuliiti evaserant, sed justo judicio Dei dampnati poenas condignas luebant. Cujus rei inditia sunt bella famosissima gloriosissimi et fidelissimi imperatoris Theodosii, quae gessit contra Maximum tyrannum Gratiani domini sui interfectorem fratrisque ejus Valentiniani de regno expulsorem, quem sola fide major, universa autem apparatus belli com- paratione minor, sine dolo et sine controversia Theodosius clausit, coepit, occidit. Similiter et contra Arbogastem atque Eugenium infestissimos tyrannos . . . quos utique christianissimus im- perator, potentia Dei, non fiducia hominis fretus, magis orationibus quam armis subegit."

2 Hincmar of Rheims, De Fide Carolo Rege Servanda, xxxiii.

8 Hmcmar, De Fid. Car. Reg. Serv., xxxiv : " Nam cum in prsepositis delin- quimus, ejus ordinationi qui eos nobis prsetulit obviamus." See p. 152.






218 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.

for good princes, and rejoice even while they groan under those who are permitted by God to reign for their chastisement. They do indeed resist wicked works and commands, but they endure patiently, for God's sake, the evils which are brought upon them by wicked princes.^ This passage is the more noticeable that the general purpose of the letter is to protest against infractions of the privileges of the clergy by the king. These passages will be sufficient to show how strongly the doctrine of the divine authority of the civil government, and the duty of obedience to it, was held in the ninth century. It might seem as though these writers were still wholly under the influence of the extreme position of St Gregory the Great. We can indeed understand how they came to this view. God is the source of all authority; the king as ruler derives his power from God, the evil king as much as the good ; the former indeed, as we have seen, in the last passage quoted from Hincmar, holds his power by God's permission rather than by His appointment, but still he holds it by (jod's permission for the chastisement and correction of evil. Therefore, they say, we must always obey the king, and submit to him, even when unreasonable and unjust, lest we should be found to be resisting God. These writers think that their principles are the same as those of Gregory the Great. We must now con- sider other aspects of their theory of government, and we shall be led to recognise that while they repeat these patristic phrases with sincerity, their own final judgment is influenced also by considerations of quite another kind.

^ Hincmar of Rheims, Ep. xv. Ad principibus gratias referuut ; et de his

Carolum Regem : " Quia nihil fit in qui ad purgationem suam a Deo reg-

mundo, nisi quod aut Deus miseri- nare permissi sunt, gementes exsultaut ;

corditer facit, aut fieri juste permittit. sicut scriptum est * Exsultaverunt filise

Cum itaque reges ex illo regnant, Judse in omnibus judiciistuis, Domine.'

misericordia illius est, ut salventur SicquenonresistuntordinationiDei,qui

populi eis commissi : cum vero non ex novit, non mala facere, sed ordinare.

illo, sedpermittente justoipsiusjudicio Resistunt autem iniquis iniquorum

reges regnare videntur, vindicta est operibus et mandatis. Unde scriptum

peccatoris populi et regnantis cumulus est : * Verba sapientium quasi stimuli,

poenae. Sed fideles quique potestati et quasi claves in altum defixi,* quia

aut a Deo coUatse aut a Deo permissae nesciunt culpas palpare, sed pungere,

non resistunt, cum juxta Petri vocem : et tolerant patienter propter Dominum

' Sub manu Dei humiliantur, et de bonis illata mala sibi a principibus malis.'-






219


CHAPTER XVIII.

THE THEORY OF THE KING AND JUSTICE.

So far as we have gone in our examination of the political theory of the writers of the ninth century, we have recognised the influence of the theories of St Gregory the Great as to the duty of an unlimited obedience to the civil ruler ; for in the main it is his sentiments and phrases which they are reproducing. No doubt they reproduce these with honesty and sincerity ; no doubt they imagined that they really held just the same opinions as St Gregory. But when we examine their writings further, we discover at once that we have here only one aspect of their view of the nature and source of the authority of government.

The truth is, that while the writers of the ninth century are most anxious to express themselves in the language of the Fathers, most anxious to be faithful to the traditions which they had inherited from them, their own standpoint is really in many ways a very dififerent one from that of St Gregory the Great. The situation of the ninth century was, in fact, a very different one from that of the sixth century. The whole Western Church must probably have been influenced by the violent rupture between the Bishop of Eome and the iconoclastic emperors. Italy had risen in revolt against the attempt to suppress the use of images, and the Bishops of Rome, though they had tried to moderate the violence of the revolt,^ yet had necessarily been compelled by their own convictions to approve the Italian resistance to the impious wishes of the iconoclastic emperors ; and such armed resistance must have tended to neutralise the tradition of St Gregory the Great.

^ Liber Pontificalia : Gregory II., xvii. and xx.


VjOOQIC 


220 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part I v.

, The transference of the empire from the Byzantine to the \ Frank, and the fact that the Western ecclesiastics had in the ninth century to do, not with the civilised chiefs of the ancient Aj ^ Eoman civilisation, but with the half-barbarous Teutonic kings and emperors, must have exercised an even greater influence 7 upon the temper of the great churchmen. They might ex- press themselves in the most deferential terms to their rulers, but actually they were civilised men, — at least they had the tradition of civilisation, — while the rulers were for the most part uneducated and half-barbarous. It must have become very diflBcult for the churchmen to think of an unqualified obedience to men who in some very important matters were their inferiors. And there was yet a third circumstance which profoundly affected the political conceptions of churchmen and laymen alike. They might, as Christians, desire to be faithful to the traditions of the Christian Fathers, like Gregory the ) ' Great, but actually and necessarily they were still more power- fully influenced by the traditions of their own race. We shall have to examine the Teutonic tradition of Government presently in more detail : for the moment it is enough to say that the ^ Teutonic tradition knew nothing of an unlimited authority in the

rjllfilV but a great deal of the relation of the king to his great or wise men, and even to the nation as a whole ; and for the ^most part the churchmen outside of Italy, and even to a large Vextent in Italy, were men of the Teutonic race or tradition. The situation of the ninth century was wholly different from that of the sixth ; and while, as we have seen, the writers of the ninth century, in their anxiety to be faithful to the tradition of the earlier Christian writers, constantly repeat such phrases as these of St Gregory the Great, they are also continually and quite clearly governed by other traditions and give expression to other principles. In this and the following chapters we have to consider these. We begin by examining their conceptions of the relation of government and justice. We have seen that the writers of the ninth century look upon the king as the repre- sentative of God, and sometimes speak as though this were true, whether he is good or bad, just or unjust. This does not, how- ever, mean that they are blind to the difference between the just






CHAP, xvili.] THEORY OF THE KING AND JUSTICE. 221

king and the unjust, whom they do not hesitate to call a tyrant. It is true that some of the Fathers had spoken as though this made no difiference in the duty of the subject, and we have seen that St Augustine actually omits the characteristic of justice from his definition of the State; but, as we have also seen, other Fathers represent another tendency, and the influence of one of these is very strong in the ninth century.

We have in a previous chapter mentioned the definitions of civitas and populvs given by St Isidore of Seville. ^Scaba&us Maurus reproduces them,^ and it is perhaps worth noticing that in .doing this he follows St Isidore in his reproduction of Cicero's definition of the State as against St Augustine. We cannot, indeed, argue from this that he intends to repudiate St Augus- tine's definition ; but the fact may serve to illustrate what we have already said, that St Augustine's definition of the State does not seem to have exercised any considerable influence in the Middle Ages.

We have also in a previous chapter mentioned the definition of the king given by St Isidore of Seville. Kings, he says, are so called from ruling, but he does not rule who does not correct : if the ruler acts rightly, he will keep the name of king ; if he transgresses, he will lose it . There is an ancient proverb, " Thou s halt be king, if t hou does t ri ghtly ; if not, thou shalt not be king." ^ His definition is constantlv referred t o by tbj^ writers of th e ninth century. Hrabanus Maurus reproduces it verbatim in his ' De Universe,' ^ and it is more or less exactly cited by Sedulius Scotus,* by Jonas of Orleans,^ by Cathulfus,^

^ Hrabanus Maurus, De Universo, corrigit. Recte igitur faciendo regis

xiv. 1 : *' Civitas est hominum multi- nomen tenetur, peccando amittitur.

tudo societatis vinculo adunata ; dicta Unde et apud veteres, tale erat

a civibus, id est, ab ipsis incolis urbis. proverbium : Rex eris si recte facies.

Nam urbs ipsa moenia, sunt; civitas si non facias non eris." autem non saxa, sed habitatores vo- - ^ De Universo, xvL 3. cantur." Id., id., xvi. 4: "Populus * De Rectoribus Christianis, 2.

est coetus humanae multitudinis ^ De Instit. Regia, 3 : '* Rex a recte

juris consensu concordi communione regendo vocatur ; si enim pie, et juste,

sociatus." et misericorditer regit, merito rex

^ St Isidore of Seville, Etym., ix. 3 : appellatur ; si his caruerit nomen regis

Reges a regendo vocati sicut enim amittit>"

sacerdos a sanctificando, ita et rex ^ M. Q. H. Ep., iv. Var. Car. Mag.

a regendo : non autem regit qui non Regn., 7.






222 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.

and by Hincmar of Rheims.^ In itself this definition might mean much or little, but i t obtains a very considerable signifi c- ance when we observe again how sharply the ** king is con - trasted with the " tyran t/' St Isidore, in the same place whe re he defines the me a ning of " king," als o defines the meaning of ' tyrant." This name, he says, had formerly been used as equivalent to that of king, but in later time was used to denote & wicked and cruel ruler.^ This definition, again, is repro- duced exactly by Hrabanus Maurus,^ less precisely by Jonas of Orleans ; * and Hincmar of Eheims seems to have it in his mind when he says that without clemency, patience, and love a man may become a tyrant, but cannot well attain to the kingdom.^ St Isidore of Seville adds to his definition of the king the observation that the principal royal virtues are JKstitia and pietas,^ Hrabanus Maurus^ and Hincmar of Eheims reproduce his phrase.^

The ninth-century writers are also strongly influenced by a work of very uncertain date, which some of them seem to have regarded as being by St Cyprian, though it has also at various times been attributed to Origen, St Augustine, or other Fathers. It seems clear that the work is of a much later time than any of these, but we have not been able to find that any one has


^ Ad Episcopos de Institutione Carolomauni, 16.

2 St Isidore of Seville, Etym., ix. 3 : " Tyranni Grsece dicuntur, iidem Latiue et reges ; nam apud veteres inter regem et tyrannum nulla discretio erat; ut 'Pars mihi pacis erat dextram tetigisse tyranni.' Fortes enim reges tyranni vocabantur, nam * tyro ' fortis, de quibus Dominus loquitur : * Per me reges regnant, et tyranni tenent terram.' Jam postea in usum accidit tyrannos vocari pes- simos atque improbos reges, luxuriosse dominationis cupiditatem et erudel- issimam dominationem in populis exercentes."

' De Universe, xvi. 3.

  • De Instit. Regia, 3 : " Antiqui

autem omnes reges tyrannos vocabant ;


sed postea pie, et juste, et misericorditer regentes regis nomen sunt adepti ; impie vel injuste, crudeliterque princi- pantibus, non regis sed tyrannicum aptatum est nomen."

  • De Divortio Lotharii et Tetbergae,

Prsef. : "Et licet sint aliae virtutes sine quibus ad regnum non pervenitur setemum, tamen sine his tribus quas posuimus, tyrannus fieri potest, reg- num autem salubriter nemo potest obtinere terrenum, id est sine man- suetudine . . . sine patientia . . . sine vera dilectione."

^ Etym., ix. 3: "Regiae virtutes prsecipuse duse, justitia et pietas : plus autem in regibus laudatur pietas ; nam justitia per se severa est."

' De Universo, xvi 8.

8 Ad Episc. de Inst. Carol., 17.






CHAP. XVIII.] THEORY OF THE KING AND JUSTICE. 223

yet dated it exactly.^ This treatise, *De Duodecim Abusivis Sseculi/ which is of much value and interest throughout as a criticism of the condition of society in the period, whatever that may precisely be, to which it belongs, has one chapter which is specially important in relation to the conception of justice in the State. The ninth chapter deals with the unjust king, and. declares that the king must not be unjust, but must restrain the unjust: it is the proper purpose of his ofiBce to rule, but how can he rule and correct others unless he first corrects himself? Justice in the king means to \ oppress no man unjustly, to judge righteously between men, to defend the weak, to punish the wicked, to protect the Church, to put just rulers over the kingdom, to live in God and the Catholic faith, and to keep his children from evil. The king who does not rule according to these principles will bring many evils and disasters on his country and his descendants. The king should remember that as he has the greatest station among men, so also he will sufifer the greatest punishment if he does not do justice.^ This chapter is quoted


^ We take the critical details from Hartel's edition of the works of St Cyprian, vol. iii., Prsefatio, p. Ixiv.

^ De Duodecim Abusivis Sseculi, 9 : "Nonas abusionis gradus est rex in- iquus. Etenim regem non iniquum sed correctorem iniquorum esse oportet. Unde in semet ipso nominis sui digni- tatem custodire debet: nomen enim regis intellectualiter hoc retinet, ut subjectis omnibus rectoris officium pro- curet. Sed qualiter alios corrigere poterit qui proprios mores ne iniqui sint non corrigit? Quoniam justitia regis exaltatur solium et veritate solidantur gubernacula populorura. Justitia vero regis est neminem injuste per potentiam opprimere, sine acceptione personarum inter virum et proximum suum judicare, advenis et pupillis et viduis defensorem esse, f urta cohibere, adulteria punlre, iniquos non exaltare . . . ecclesias defendere, pauperes eleemosynia alere, justos


super regni negotia constituere, senes et sapientes et sobrios consiliarios habere . . . iracundiam diflTerre, patriam fortiter et juste contra ad- versarios defendere, per omnia in Deo vivere, prosperitatibus non ele- vare animum, cuncta adversa patienter ferre, fidem Catholicam in Deum habere, filios suos non sinere impie agere, certis horis orationibus in- sistere, ante horas congruas non gustare cibum. . . . Qui vero regnum secundum banc legem non dispensat, multas nimirum adversitates imperii tolerat. Idcirco enim ssepe pax populorum rumpitur et offendicula etiam de regno suscitantur, terrarum quoque fructus diminuuntur et ser- vitia populorum preepediuntur, multi etiam dolores prosperitatem regni inficiunt. . . . Ecce quantum justitia regis sseculo valeat, intuentibus per- spicue patet. Pax populorum est, tutamentum patriae, immunitas plebis.






224 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.


by Jonas of Orleans^ and by Hincmar of Rheims^ in their treatises dealing with the nature of the royal authority.

The formal treatises on kingship in the ninth century are indeed very largely made up of admonitions to the king to follow after justice and mercy, to seek wisdom and to fear } God. Smarao fdus bid s the king to love justice and judgment, ^ the royal way trodden in older times by former kings. He admonishes him to do justice to the poor and the orphan, if he desire that God should establish his throne.^ Alcuin in his letters continually urges upon the various rulers to whom these are addressed the same principle, that their chief duty is to do justice and mercy to their people.* S edulius Scotus, in his treatise on the nature of the Christian ruler, lays much stress on the same points.^ He and Cathulfus have a very interesting enumeration of the eight qualities which are

pronum in mbericordia — secundum quod ille miseretur subjectis, misere- bitur ei Deus — sobrium in moribus, veridicum in verbis, largum in donis, providum in consiliis : consiliarios habere prudentes, Deum timentes, honestis moribus omatos. . . . Legimus quoque, quod Regis bonitas totius est gentis prosperitas, victoria exercitus. . . . Magnum est totam regere gentem. A regendo vero Rex dicitur : et qui bene regit subjec- tum sibi populum, bonam habet a Deo retributionem, regnum scilicet coeleste. Valde feliciter regnat in terra, qui de terreno regno merebitur coeleste. Orationibus vero et vigiliis eo instantius ad Deum insistere debet, quo non pro se solummodo, sed et pro totius gentis prosperitate Deum deprecari debet. Similiter Principes et Judices populi in justitia et pie- tate populo prsesint. Viduis, pupillis et miseris sint quasi patres ; quia sequitas Principum populi est exultatio. Ecclesiarum Christi sint defensores et tutores ; ut servorum Dei orationibus longa vivant prosperitate." Cf. Ep. 30, 64, 217. « De Rect Christ., 2, 3, &c.


munimentum gentis, cura languorum, gaudium hominum, temperies sens, Berenitas maris, terrse fecunditas, Bolacium pauperum, hereditas filiorum et sibimet ipsi spes futurse beati- tudinis. Attamen sciat quod sicut throno hominum primus constitutus «8t, sic et in pcenis, si justitiam non fecerit, primatum habiturus est. Omnes namque quoscumque pecca- tores sub se in prsesenti habuit, supra J3e modo plagali in ilia poena habebit."

^ De Inst. Regia, 3.

' Ad Episc. de Inst. Carol, 7, and De Regis Persona, 25.

3 Via Regia, 8 and 9 : " DUige ergo, rex, justitiam et judicium, quae est via i*egia, et a prioribus regibus autiquitus trita. . . . Sed tempera justitiam et crudelitatem soUiciter cave sinistram. ^ . '. Si vis ergo, rex, ut thronus tuus a Domino firmetur, non cesses justificare pauperem et pupiUum."

  • M. G. H. Ep., iv. ; Alcuin, Ep.

18 : " niorum est, id est, Sacerdo- tum, verba Dei non tacere. Vestrum •est, o Principes, humiliter oboedire, diligenter implere. Regis est, omnes iniquitates pietatis suae potentia ob- primere ; justum esse in judiciis,






CHAP, xvni.] THEORY OF THE KING AND JUSTICE.


225


the most firm supports of a just king.^ Jonas of Orleans , as we have already mentioned, cites St Isidore's definition of the king and the tyrant, and also the ninth chapter of the treatise *De Duodecim Abusivis Sseculi,' and himself urges with much vigour on the king the duty of doing justice. The king's chief duty, he says, is to govern the people of God with equity and justice, and to strive that they may have peace and concord. He is to prevent all injustice and to appoint fit per- sons to administer the State under him, for he will be respon- sible if they are unjust. Such ministers must learn that the people of Christ are by nature their equals, and that they must rule them justly, and not lord it over them or ill-treat them, thinking that they belong to them, or are put under them for the glory of the rulers. Such notions belong to tyranny and unjust power, and not to justice.^


^ M. G. H. Ep., vol. iv. ; Ep. Var. Car. Mag. Regn. Script., 7: "Sunt autem octo columnse regis justi proprise. . . . Prima est Veritas in rebus regalibus ; secunda pacientia in omni negotio ; tertia largitas in muneribuB ; quarta persuadibilitas in verbis ; quinta malorum correptio et constrictio ; sexta bonorum elevatio et exaltatio, septima levitas tributi in populo, octava aequitas judicii inter divitem et pauperem." Cf. Sedulius Scotus, De Rect. Christ., 10.

^ De Inst. Regia, 4 : " Regale ministerium specialiter est populum Dei gubemare et regere cum sequitate et justitia, et ut pacem et concordiam habeant studere. Ipse enim debet primo defensor esse ecclesiarum et servorum Dei. Ipsorum etiam officium est saluti et ministerio sacerdotum solerter prospicere, eorumque armis et protectione Ecclesia Clmsti debet tueri: viduarum, orphanorum, cseter- orumque pauperum, necnon et omnium indigentium inopia defendi. Ipsius enim terror ac studium hujuscemodi, in quantum possibile est, esse debet : primo ut nulla injustitia fiat ; deinde, si evenerit, ut nullo modo earn sub-

VOL. I.


sistere permittat, nee spem delites- cendi, sive audaciam male agendi cuiquam relinquat ; sed sciant onmes quoniam si ad ipsius notitiam per- venerit quidquam mali quod ad- miserint, nequaquam incorreptum aut inultum remanebit : sed juxta facti qualitatem erit et modus justse correptionis. Quapropter hoc in throno regiminis positus est ad judicia recta peragenda, ut ipse per se provideat et perquirat, ne in judicio aliquis a veritate et sequitate declinet. Scire etiam debet quod causa, quam juxta ministerium sibi commissum administrat, non hominum sed Dei causa existit, cui pro minis- terio quod suscepit, in examinis tre- mendi die rationem redditurus est. Et ideo oportet ut ipse, qui judex est judicum, causam pauperum ad se ingredi faciat, et diligenter inquirat, ne forte iUi qui ab eo constituti sunt, et vicem ejus agere debent in populo, injuste aut negligenter pauperes op- pressiones pati permittant. . . .

"5, His quae prsemissa sunt de- claratur quod hi qui post regem populum Dei regere debent, id est duces et comites, necesse est ut tales

P






226 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [PART iv.

In anotJier passage of the same treatise Jonas urges that jus- tice preserves a kingdom, while injustice causes its ruin ; ^ and he prefixes to another chapter, in which he urges on subjects the religious obligations of obedience to the king, the observation that the duty of the royal oflBce is to care for the wellbeing of the subjects, and that therefore, as they desire that the king should aid them, they should obey and serve him.^ Hincmar of Bheims, as we have already seen, cites St Isidore's definition of the king and the tyrant, and the treatise *De Duodecim Abusivis Sseculi' on the unjust king, and he repeats Jonas of Orleans' observations on the duty of kings' ministers.^

We find Jonas' statement of the nature of the true king and of his chief duties reproduced in the address presented by the bishops to Lewis the Pious in the year 829. In this they first cite passages from the writings of St Isidore of Seville, St Gregory the Great, and Fulgentius of Ruspe, to illustrate the difference between the tyrant and the king, and the true char- acter of the king, and then urge upon him to remember that his chief duty is to govern with equity and justice, to defend Churches and the servants of God, the widows, orphans, and all other poor and needy people. His duty is to prevent all injustice, if possible, and if it does occur, to put it down. He should therefore be always ready himself to hear the cause of the poor, lest any of his ministers should act unjustly, or suffer the poor to be oppressed. Men of every rank must remember

ad constituendum provideantur, qui consultum ferre debere; et idcirco

sine periculo ejus, a quo constituuntur, oportet ut omnes subjecti fideliter,

constitui possint, scientes se ad hoc et utiliter, atque obedienter eidem

positos esse ut plebem Christi sibi pareant potestati : quoniam qui potes-

natura sequalem recognoscant, eamque tati a Deo ordinatae resistit, Dei

clementer salvent, et juste regant, non utique ordinationi, juxta apostoli docu-

ut dominentur et affligant, neque ut mentum) resistit. Sicut enim subjecti

populum suum sestiment, aut ad suam a rege sibi volunt pie et juste opitu-

gloriam sibi ilium subjiciant : quod non lari, ita specialiter ei primum ad sal-

pertinet ad justitiam, sed potius ad utem animse suse procurandam, deinde

tyrannidem et iniquam potestatem." generaliter ad honestatem et utilitatem

^ De Inst. Reg., 6. Cf. De Inst. regni secundum Dei voluntatem dis-

Laicali, ii 24. ponendam atque administrandam, in-

^ De Inst. Reg., 8: "Constat re- dissimulanter atque irretractibiliter so-

galem potestatem omnibus sibi sub- latium opportunum debent exhibere."

jectis secundum sequitatis ordinem ^ Ad Ep. de Inst. Carol., 14.






CHAP. XVIII.] THEORY OF THE KING AND JUSTICE. 227


that if they will have to answer for every idle word, much more will they have to give account to God for the office which He has intrusted to them.^

J gincmar of Ehei ma and Sedulius Scotus seem to express these conceptions in stronger terms than any others. Hincmar quotes, without comment indeed, but no great comment was


^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. No. 196, Episcoporum ad Hludovicum Im- peratorem Relatio, 56 : " Ut quid rex dictus sit; Ysidorus in libro Sen- tentiarum scribit : ' Rex enim,' inquit,

  • a recte agendo vocatur: si enim pie

et juste et misericorditer regit, merito rex appellatur : si his caruerit, non rex sed tyrannus est.' Antiqui autem ut idem Isidorus in libro Ethi- mologiarum scribit, omnes reges tyrannos Tocabant. Sed postea pie •et misericorditer regentibus regis nomen adeptis, impie vero, injuste, <irudeliterque principantibus non regis, Bed tyrannicum aptatum est nomen. Unde et beatus Qregorius ait in Moralibus : * Yiros namque sanctos proinde reges vocari in sacris suis >eloquiis didicimus, eo quod recte agant ■sensusque proprios bene regant et motus resistentes sibi rationabili dis- •cretione componant. Becte igitur iUi reges vocantur qui tam semet ipsos, quam subjectos bene gerendo paci- i&care noverunt.' Ad quid etiam «onstitutus sit imperator, Fulgentius in libro de yeritate predestinationis et gratise, scribit : * Clemen tissimus •quoque imperator non ideo est vas misericordise preparatum in gloriam, •quia apicem terreni principatus ac- •cipit, sed si in imperiali culmine i-ecta fide vivat et vera cordis humili- tate preditus culmen regise dignitatis .sanctse religioni subjiciat: si magis in timore servire Deo, quam in timore ^ominari populo delectetur, si in -eo lenitas iracundiam mitiget» ornet benignitas potestatem, si se raagis •diligendum, quam metuendum cunctis ■«xibeat, si subjectis salubriter consulat,


si justitiam sic teneat, ut miseri- cordiam non relinquat, si pre omnibus ita se sanctee matris ecclesise catholicse meminerit filium, ut ejus paci atque tranquillitati per universum mundum prodesse suum faciat principatus. Magis enim christianum regitur im- perium, dum ecclesiastico statui per omnem terram consulitur, quam cum in parte quacunque terrarum pro temporali securitate pugnatur.'"

It is important to notice the way in which the bishops understand the authors whom they quote. They con- tinue to enforce the same ideas in the words of Jonas of Orleans : " Regale namque ministerium specialiter est, populum Dei gubemare et regere cum equitate et justitia et, ut pacem et con- cordiam habeant, studere. Ipse enim debet primo defensor esse ecclesiarum et servorum Dei, viduarum, orfanorum ceterorumque pauperum necnon et omnium iudigentium. Ipsius enim terror et studium hujuscemodi, in quantum possibile est, esse debet, primo, ut nulla in justitia fiat, deinde, si evenerit, ut nuUo modo eam sub- sistere permittat, nee spem delites- cendi sive audatiam male agendi cuiquam relinquat. . . . Undeoportet, ut ipse, qui judex est judicum causam pauperum ad se ingredi faciat et diligenter inquirat, ne forte aliqui, qui ab eo constituti sunt et vicem ejus agere debent in populo, injuste aut negligenter pauperes oppressiones pati permittant. Scire autem unum- quemque cujuslibet sit ordinis, opor- tet, quia si de ocioso sermone Deo rationem redditurus est, multo magis de ministerio sibi divinitus commisso."






228 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [pART IV,

needed by him, a phrase of St Augustine^s to which we have referred in an earlier chapter : " Bemota itaque justitia, quid sint regna nisi magna latrocinia." ^ And Sedulius Scotus, warning evil rulers of the ruin which impends over them, of the judg- ment of God which awaits them both in this world and the next, exclaims : " What are impious kings but the greater robbers of the earth, fierce as lions, ravening like wolves ; but they are great to-day and perish to-morrow, and of them God has said,

  • They reigned, but not by Me ; they arose as princes, but I

knew it not* " ^ The evil ruler or tyrant is no true king ; he is only, as Cicero indeed had called him, a wild beast, the most terrible and loathsome known to the world.

The writers of the ninth century, then, while they reproduce ^ the phrases of St Gregory the Great with regard to the divine authority of the ruler, and speak at times as though he must under all circumstances be obeyed as the representative of God, are also clearly and strongly influenced by other considerations, partly founded, no doubt, upon the authority of other Fathers ~^ like St Isidore of Seville, but also in large measure related to \ their own experience and traditions. They no doubt felt really and profoundly the truth which lay behind St Gregory's phrases, the truth that authority in the State is sacred ; they had ample experience of the consequences of discord and civil strife. But, on the other hand, they had no mind to submit to injustice or tyranny ; they were probably clearly enough conscious of the fact that many of the kings whom they had known were capric- ious and fallible rulers.

We must turn to the actual conditions of the government of the time, not to discuss the intricacies of the Frankish or other Teutonic constitutions, but that we may recognise some of the principles which lay behind the constitutional machinery and practice of those times, and that we may more completely understand the forces which were moulding the theory of the State.

^ De Regis Persona, 6. Of. p. 167. rarum latrones, feroces ut leones,

  • De Rect. Chris., 8: "Quid sunt bidi ut ursi?"

autem impii reges, nisi majores ter-






229


CHAPTER XIX.

THE KING AND THE LAW.

We have seen that the writers of the ninth century look upon ^ justice as something essential to the character of the true ruler. Without justice he is a tyrant and no king. The conception of justice was indeed no more clear in the ninth century than in the present day, or in ancient times; but we think that justice, relatively to the ruler, had a meaning in the ninth century whose importance is very great indeed. No king is just who does not observe and respect the law; the law is at least one standard of justice, clear, distinct, constantly appealed to.

We have seen in earlier chapters that in the theory of the Eoman jurists the emperor is the source of law. Justinian even speaks of him as the sole " legis lator." ^ It is true that, as we have also seen, this power is his only because the Boman people have chosen to confer their authority upon him; the people is the only ultimate source of law. But still the em^^ peror is the actual source of law. And the emperor is " legibus splutus," a phrase whose significance it is not easy to definent may indeed be doubted whether it can be clearly defined. Per- haps it only (expresses a conception whose history can be traced in such a constitutional form as that of the dispensing power of the English Crown, — a power which seems to represent the con- sciousness present, however vaguely, to any more developed reflection upon law and the State, that there must be a power in the State itself which can, if necessary, interfere to prevent the harsh or inequitable operation of the law in particular cases ;

I Cod. i. 14. 12.






230 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

a power which, being in its nature administrative rather than legislative, must be intrusted to the head of the State as ad- ministrator. It is the influence, perhaps, partly of this con- sciousness, partly of the revived study of the Eoman juris- prudence, which leads the more systematic political thinkers of the thirteenth century like St Thomas Aquinas to observe that the prince cannot properly be said to be under the law, for he must have the power of dispensing with it.^ I In the ninth century, however, the king is not the sole source of law, but only ias his part in the national relation to it; and he is not usually thought, of as above the law, or outside of it, but as bound to carry it out. The ninth-century theory of the relation of the king to justice may be reasonably connected with the theory of his relation to law. Lothair, Lewis, and Charles, at their meeting at Mersen in 851, put out a deblara- tion promising their faithful subjects that for the future they would not condemn, or dishonour, or oppress any man against the law and justice.* And when Lewis at Coblentz in 860 repeats the promises of Mersen, he adds an emphatic assurance that his faithful subjects shall enjoy the ancient law, and that all shall receive justice and law.^ Justice, when translated into constitutional tradition, means, in the first place, the observation of the national law: the king is just when he sees that this is carried out, unjust when he acts in con- tradiction to it.

p In the treatise of Hincmar of Eheims on the divorce of Lothair and Tetburga we find a formal discussion of the nature and source of the royal authority, to which we shall have to return later, for it contains much which is important* For the

^ St Thom. Aquin., Summa 1, 2, Q. damnabimus aut dehonorabimus aut

xcvi. 5 ; and Sum. 2, 2, Q. Ixvii. 4. opprimemus vel indebitis machina-

Cf. article by R. W. Carlyle in * Scottish tionibus affligemus/' &c.

Review,' Jan. 1896, "The Political ' M. G. H. Leg., sect, il vol. ii. 242.

Theories of St Thomas Aquinas." 6: "Et volumus, ut vos et ceteri

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. 205. homines fideles nostri talem legem et

6 : " Ut nostri fideles, unusquisque in rectitudinem et tale salvamentum in

suo ordine et statu, veraciter sint de regnis nostris habeatis, sicut anteces*

nobis securi, quia nullum adhinc in sores vestri tempore anteceesorum

ante contra legem et justitiam vel nostrorum habuerint . . . et justitia

auctoritatem ao justam rationem aut et lex omnibus conservetur."






CHAP. XIX.]


THE KING AND THE LAW.


231


moment we look at it only to see how he deals with the relation of the king to law. It is contended, he says, by some wise men that the prince is a king, and that the king is subject to the laws and judgment of none save God alone. This is true in one sense, he replies — that is, if he is a true king, for the king is so called from ruling ; and if he governs himself according to . God's will, and directs the good into the right way, and corrects the wicked so as to drive them from the evil way to the good and right one, then he is a king indeed, and subject to the laws and judgments of none save Grod. Whosoever, then, is a king in the true sense, is not subject to law, for law is set not for • the just but for the unjust, for wicked men and for sinners ; and he who rules himself and others according to the fruits of the spirit is not subject to law, for " against such there is no law." But the adulterer, murderer, unjust man, the ravisher, and the man guilty of other vices, whoever he may be, will be judged by the priest.^ Hincmar's treatment of the question seems to indicate that he was in some measure conscious of the difficulty of defining in precise terms the relation of the king to law ; but


1 Hincmar of RheimB, De Div. Loth, et Tetb., Quaestio vi. : " Dicunt quoque etiam aliqui sapientes, quia iste prin- ceps rex est, et nuUorum legibus vel judiciis Bubjacet, nisi solius Dei. . . .

Resp. . . . Quod dicitur, quia rex nuUorum legibus vel judiciis subjacet, nisi solius Dei, verum dicitur si rex est sicuti nominatur. Rex enim a regendo dicitur, et si seipsum secundum voluntatem Dei regit, et bonos in viam rectam dirigit, malos autem de via prava ad rectam corrigit, tunc rex est, et nullorum legibus vel judiciis nisi solius Dei subjacet: quoniam arbitria possunt dici, leges autem non sunt, nisi illse quae Dei sunt per quern reges regnant, et conditores legem justam decemunt. Et quicunque rex veraciter rex est, legi non subjacet, quia lex non est posita justo, sed injustis et non subditis, impiis et peccatoribus, sceleratis, contaminatis, parricidis et matricidis, . . . et si quid aliud sanse


doctrinsa adversaturi et his qui operi- bus camis serviunt, de quibus dicit Apostolus [quotes Qal. v. 19-21]. . . . Qui autem se et alios secundum fructus Spiritus regit [quotes Qal. v. 22, 23] . . . legi non subjacet quia ' adversus hujusmodi non est lex.' Sed solo judicio Ohristi subjacet a quo et remunerabitur cujus est qui camem suam crucifigit cum vitiis et concupiscentiis. Alioquin adulter, homicida, in Justus, raptor, et aliorum vitiorum obnoxius quilibet, vel secrete, vel publice, judicabitur a sacerdotibus, qui sunt throni Dei, in quibus Deus sedet, et per quos sua decemit judicia, quibus et in apostolis suis quorum locum in Ecclesia tenent, Dominus dixit ^Si peccaverit frater . . . (Matt, xviii. 15, 16).' Et ne quis in hoc sacerdotem parvipendat adjunxit Dominus [quotes Matt. xviiL 18]. ... Et item dicit * qui vos audit me audit, et qui vos spemit, me spemit.' "






232 POUTICAL THEOKY OP NINTH CENTURY, [part iv.

it is fairly explicit as indicating that whatever might be the relation of the true ruler to the law which he is justly adminis- tering, the evil ruler who sets at nought the moral law is liable to correction at least by the Church. We shall have to return to this particular aspect of the question later.

If in this passage Hincmar seems to express himself in the most cautious fashion, we find him speaking in more un- qualified terms in other places on the principle that it is the duty of the ruler to observe and obey the law. In another part ^f the same treatise he quotes a phrase of St Ambrose which we have already discussed, "Leges enim imperator fert, quas primus ipse custodiat," and warns the king that if he breaks the laws he may find himself condemned by the apostle's words, " Thou that preachest a man should not steal, dost thou steal ? " ^ We have considered the meaning which may be attached to this phrase as it is used by St Ambrose ; Hincmar of Bheims' com- ment on it makes it fairly clear that he understands it in a somewhat strict sense. Hincmar also quotes the passage from^ St Augustine's treatise * De Vera Eeligione ' which we have already discussed : the citation occurs as part of a discussion of the action of Charles the Bald in summoning Hincmar, Bishop of Laon, to appear before a secular court, and passing some sort of judgment on him in his absence. Hincmar argues that this action is contrary not only to the canons, but also to laws of the emperors from Condtantine downwards, and to the promises made by Charles himself to observe the canons. Therefore he concludes, in a phrase of St Gregory the Great, " It must be so, that whatever is contrary to the laws has no force," and then quotes St Augustine as saying that when men make laws they judge what is good, but when they have once been made, the magistrate cannot judge the laws, but can only act in accordance

^ Hincmar of Rheims, De Div. Loth. observentur, sicut sanctus Ambrosius

et Tetb., Qusestio v. : Reap. : " Capitula ad Valentinianum sciibit. ' Leges enim

sunt legalia imperatorum et regum imperator ferat, quas primus ipse

prsedecessorum suorum, quid sustinere custodiat,' quas si ipse fregerit, timen-

debeat qui post bannum latronem dum est ne audiat ab apostolo, 'Qui

receperit, et in chirographo regum prsedicas non furandum, furaris, qui

nostrorum hinc ezpresse decemitur, abominaris idola sacrilegium fads.'"

cujus ministerium est agere ut ilia See p. 164.






CHAP. XIX.]


THE KING AND THE LAW.


233


with them.^ It is clear that Hincmar uses St Augustine's phrase to confirm his opinion that the king cannot violate the laws which had long been in force as to the relation of the ecclesias- tical and secular courts. In the ' De Regis Persona ' Hincmar quotes the first part of the same saying of St Augustine, and then concludes that just laws which have been promulgated must be enforced by the prince.^

But the strongest and most noteworthy statement of the^ same view is to be found in Hincmar's treatise called 'De Ordine Palatii' In the eighth chapter of this work we have an exceedingly important statement of the. writer's conception of the relation of the king to the law, and of the source of the authority of the latter. He begins by a reference to the rule that no priest must be ignorant of the canons, and then proceeds to say that in like manner the sacred laws — that is, the Roman laws in the *Lex Romana Visigothorum' — decree that no one may be ignorant of the law or despise its decrees. This includes persons of every worldly rank. Kings, therefore, and the ministers of the commonwealth, have laws by which they must rule the inhabitants of every province; they have the capitularies of the Christian kings, their ancestors, which


^ Hincmar of Rheims, Pro. EccL Lib. Def. i. : " Unde legalis aententia, quam ut prsedecessores illiua, B. Qregorius in commonitorio Joanni dato decrevit esse canonicam, dicit: 'Neoesse est quod contra leges est actum firmitatem non habeat.* £t S. Augustinus in libro, 'De Vera Religione,' dicit, *In istis temporalibus legibus quanquam de his homines judicent, cum eas instituunt: tamen cum fuerint insti- tutse atque firmataa non licebit judici de ipsis judicare, sed secundum ipsas. Conditor tamen legum temporalium si vir bonus et sapiens est, illam ipsam consulit setemam, de qua nulli animse judicare datum est, ut secundum ejus incommutabiles regulas quid sit pro tempore jubendum vitandumque dis- cemat. ^temam igitur legem mun- dis animis fas est cognoscere, nefas


est judicare.' De qua B. Prosper dicit : — ' Lex eetema Dei stabili regit omnia nata Nee mutat vario tempore consilium.'

Nam si imperatores Romanorum suam legem setemam, vel perpetuam appel- laverunt, multo magis lex ilia aetema est, quae est Sancto Spiritu pro- mulgata."

2 Hincmar of Rheims, De Reg. Per., 27 : " Sanctus Augustinus in libro * De Vera Religione* leges principum ser- vandas ostendit. 'In istis,' inquiens, ' temporalibus legibus quanquam de his homines judicent cum eas instituunt, tamen cum fuerint instituted atque firmataa non licebit judici de ipsis judi- care, sed secundum ipsas. ' Igitur aut a populo promulgat89 justas leges ser- vandse, aut a principe juste ac rationa- biliter sunt in quolibet vindicandae."






234 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [pabt IV.

were lawfully promulgated with the universal consent of their faithful subjects. And he then again quotes St Augustine's sentence that men judge the laws when they make them, but when they are once made, the judge cannot judge them, but must act in accordance with them.^ We cannot here mistake Pincmar's meaning; the king's duty is to govern according to the laws; he is no more entitled than any private person to ignore the law or to violate it. His duty is to carry out the law, not to act contrary to it

In Hincmar's words we find not only a strong statement of the normal subordination of the prince to the law, but a sug- gestion of one important cause of this subordination. We think that the words which describe the " capitula " which the king is to carry out, as having been made generali consensu Jiddium, are extremely significant, and indicate one of the strongest grounds for Hincmar's judgment that he must keep the law. The law is not merely his law, nor is it merely by his will that it has been made. So far as laws have been made, they proceed from the whole State, they have been made with the general consent of the faithful subjects of the king. It requires but little re- flection to observe how far this conception is from that of the Roman jurists. The relation of the Boman emperor to laws when promulgated may be a little obscure, perhaps a little doubtful. Ulpian's "legibus solutus,"^ and Theodosius* and Valentinian's " Digna vox majestate regnantis legibus alligatuni se principem profiteri," * may represent two different tendencies of thought, but at least the emperor was normally in his own person the direct source of law. To the ninth-century writers

^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii., reipublicee miniBtri leges, quibus in

Hincmar, De Ordine Palatii, 8 : ^ Et quacumque proyinda degentes regere

sicut dictum est de legibus ecclesias- debent, habent capitula christiaiiorum

ticis, quod nuUi saoerdoti suos liceat regum ac progenitorum suorum, quae

canones ignorare nee quicquam facere, generali consensu fidelium suorum

quod patrum possit regulis obviare, tenere l^;aUter promulgaverunt. De

ita legibus sacris decretum est, ut quibus beatus Augustinus dicit, quia,

leges nesdre nulli liceat aut quae Micet homines de bis judioent cum

sunt statuta contemnere ? Cum enim eas instituimt, tamen cum f uerint

dicitur, ^ Nulli liceat leges nescire vel institutse atque firmatse, non lioebit

quae sunt statuta contemnere,' nulla judicibus de ipsis judicare, sed

persona in quocumque ordine mundano secundum ipsas.' " excipitur, quas hac sententia non con- ' Dig. i. 3. 31.

stringatur. Habent enim r^es et ' Cod. i. 14. 4.






CHAP. XIX.] THE KING AND THE LAW. 235

the king had his part in making law, so far as law is made, but ><^ he has only one part out of many. Other voices have been heard besides his, the consent of others has to be given before anything can become the national law. This conception is one of the very greatest importance in the development of mediaeval political thought, and we must proceed to examine the legisla- tion of the ninth century to make ourselves quite clear upon the matter.

We must observe in passing that the legal system of the ninth century has a very different character from that which we should attribute to modern law. The great mass of the law of the early Middle Ages was not, so far as the consciousness of men went, made at all. It was a part of the national or tribal life ; it had grown with the tribe, changing, no doubt, but the people or tribe were hardly conscious of the changes. Such tradi- tional law is contained in most of the early mediaeval codes, and its authority was like that of nature. But in the ninth century there was already developed, perhaps prematurely, the concep- tion that law needs deliberate adaptation, or at least addition, and therefore, while much of the legislation of the time is nothing but the formal reiteration of what is supposed to be immemorial custom, other parts of it represent conscious and deliberate attempts to improve or add to the traditional customs of the nation.

There_are_three bodies of s^ecukr law^JLo. which the ruler ofjhe, Teutonic States waaj:elated : first, the traditional tribal | law, which varied considerably within such extended dominions as those of the Frankish Empire ; secondly, the legis lation of ^ the.,,.an(ajefliLEQmftn Ejopire, which obtained in many districts, mainly in the form of diiferent editions of the Theodosian code, a system of laws over which the Frankish king or emperor had little control, which are usually referred to by the writers of this time as the " leges sacrse " ; and, thirdly, the actual new laws, or additions to old laws, which the king or emperor might issue, but only with tbe consent and counsel of some or all of his subjects.

The relation of the king or emperor of the ninth century to the secular law is thus very dififerent from that of the Eoman emperors of antiquity. We are only repeating the judgment of the great majority of historical scholars, and would refer to






236 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part IV,

the work of Stubbs ^ and Waitz 2 among the older writers, and to Bicbter and Kohl * and Viollet * among the more recent It is true that Fustel de Coulanges has argued with much learning and ingenuity against this view, or at leeust in favour of a considerable modification of it, but we do not think that he has succeeded in establishing his case. The matter is, however, of such great importance in the history of the development of political theory that we think it well to illustrate it briefly from the legal documents of the ninth century.

We may begin by observing the method of promulgation of a series of " capitula," to be added to the " leges," issued by Charles the Great in the year 803. One manuscript contains an account of the method of promulgating these in Paris. They were sent to Stephen the Count, who was to cause them to be read in the " mallus publicus " in the presence of all the " scabineL" When this had been done, and they all agreed that they would for the future observe the laws, the " scabinei," bishops, abbots, and counts, affixed their signatures.^ This statement, it is true, only refers to one place, but a comparison with sect. 19 of the " Capitulare Missorum " of the same year makes it fairly plain that something like this was the normal mode of promulgating these new laws. We learn that the " missi " were to inquire of the " populus " about the " capitula " which were to be added to the laws, and to see that, when all had consented, their signature or other authentication was appended to the " capitula." ^

We can now compare with this the formula with which

^ stubbs, Const. Hist, of Eng. (ed. Parisiis mallo pubplico et ipsa legere

1891), Yol. i. p. 141, &c. fecisset coram illis scabineis ; quod ita

^ Waitz, Deutsche Verfassung's et fecit. Et omnes in uno consen*

Qeschichte (ed. 1883), vol. iii. p. serunt, quod ipsi yoluissent omni

601, &c. tempore observare usque in pos-

' Richter and Kohl, " Annalen des terum ; etiam omnes scabinei, episcopi,

Frankischen Reiches," II. Abtheilung, abbatis, comitis manu propria subter

p. 586, &c. firmaverunt."

  • P. Viollet, "Histoire des Institu- « M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL vol. i. No.

tions Politiques et Administratives de 40, c. 19 : *' Ut populus interrogetur

la Prance," vol. L p. 197, Ac. de capitulis quae in lege noviter

" M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. No. addita sunt ; et postquam onmes oon-

39 : " Sub ipso anno haec capitula facta senserint, subscriptiones et manu-

sunt et consignata Stephano Comiti, firmationes suas in ipsis capitulis

ut haec manifesta fecisset in civitate faciant."






PHAP. XIX.] THE KING AND THE LAW.


237


Charles the Great issues the "Capitulare Aquisgranense." Charles does this with the consent of his bishops, abbots, counts, and all his faithful subjects.^ We find yet another very noteworthy illustration of this conception of the mode of public administration and legislation in the ' Ordinatio Imperii ' of Lewis the Pious in 817, the document which provides for ^ the partition of his dominions between his sons. These regu- lations are made in a sacred assembly and generalitas " of the whole^ieogle^Jield after the^wonted manner. After a fast of three days his em^gt^ son^^^t^fchair ) was elected by Lewis and the whole people to be his colleague in the empire. Then with the common counsel it was decided to give the younger sons. Pippin and Lewis, the title of kings, and to allot to them cer- tain lands by definite " capitula." These were considered and then confirmed by Lewis and all his faithful subjects, so that what was done by all might by all be held inviolable.^ (This


^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. No. 77 : Earolus serenissimus imperator Augustus, a Deo coronatus, magnus et pacificus, cum episcopis, abbatibus, comitibus, ducibus, omnibusque fideli- bu3 Christianse ecclesise cum consensu consilioque constituit ex lege Salica, Romana atque Qombata capitula ista in palatio Aquis, ut unusquisque fidelis justitias ita faceret qui et ipse manu propria firmavit capitula ista, ut omnes fideles manu roborare studuissent."

2 M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. No. 136 : " Cum nos in Dei nomine anno incamationis Domini octingen- tesimo septimo decimo, indictione decima annoque imperii nostri quarto, mense Julio, Aquisgrani palatio nostro more solito sacrum conventum et generalitatem populi nostri propter ecclesiasticas vel totius imperii nostri utilitates pertractandas congi'egassemus et in his studeremus, subito divina in- spiratione actum est, ut nos fideles nostri ammonerent, quatenus manente nostra incolumitate et pace undique a Deo concessa de statu totius regni et de filiorum nostrorum causa more


parentumnostrorum tractaremus. . . . Quibus (jejuniis orationibus elemosi- narum largitionibus) rite per triduum celebratis, nutu omnipotentis Dei, ut credimus, actum est ut et nostra et totius populi nostri in dilecti primo- geniti nostri Hlutharii electione vota concurrerent. Itaque taliter divina dispensatione manifestatum placuit et nobis et omni populo nostro, more solemni imperiali diademate corona- tum nobis et consortem et successorem imperii, si Dominus ita voluerit, com- muni voto constitui. Ceteros vero fratres ejus, Pippinum videlicet et Hludowicum sequivocimi nostrum, com- muni consilio placuit regiis insigniri nominibus, et loca inferius denominata constituere, in quibus post decessum nostrum sub seniore fratre regali potestate potiantur juxta inferius adnotata capitula, quibus, quam inter eos constituimus, conditio continetur. Quae capitula propter utilitatem im- perii et perpetuam inter eos pacem conservandam et totius ecclesise tuta- men cum omnibus fidelibus nostris considerare placuit et considerata conscribere et conscripta propriis






238 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part I v.


last phrase is perhaps specially worthy of notice.) We may eompare with these the terms of the " Proemium " to the ^* Capitularia tam Ecclesiastica quam Mundana" of 818, 819;

"sect. 29 of the "Capitulare Ecclesiasticum " ; the phrases of the "Cap. Legi Salicae Addita" of 819; and the "Cap. de Punctionibus Publicis" of 820.^

. But it is hardly necessary to multiply citations to establish a judgment which is almost universally accepted as to the con- stitutional theory of the Teutonic^gtates, — ^namely, that the king does not make laws by his own authority^ but requires the consent and advice of his wise men^ ^p^j !q ^^^^ JMSSlJUlI^s vague sense, of the whole nation.* It is this tradition or theory which, at last finds something like a formal and explicit defini- tion in the famous phrase of the " Edictum Pistense " of 864,

. *' Quoniam lex consensu populi et constitutione regis fit," * — a phrase which, no doubt, like so many of the obiter dicla of the Middle Ages, must not be interpreted under the terms of what we consider our clear-cut modern conceptions, but which is full of significance for the development of the theory of law, when it is taken in its proper connection with "the general tendencies of the ninth century and of the Teutonic traditions.


manibus firmare, ut, Deo opem ferente, sicut ab omnibus communi voto actum €8t» ita communi devotione a cunctis inviolabiliter conserventur ad illorum «t totius populi Christiani perpetuam pacem ; salva in omnibus nostra im- periali potestate super filios et popu- lum nostrum, cum omni subjectione quae patri a filiis et imperatori ac regi a suis populis exhibetur."

1 M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL 137 ; 138, c. 29 ; 142, c. 2, 3, 6, 8 ; 143, c. 5. Cf. Also Nos. 215 and 221.

^ We do not mean by this that the «mperor or king did not exercise a great and perhaps almost independent authority in issuing administrative ordinances, and many of these belong to the category of what would in later times ha^» been regarded as laws.

» M. G. H. Leg., sect, ii vol. ii. 273 ; Edict. Pist., 864 ; Jun. 25. " Karolus


gratia Dei rex. Notum esse volumus omnibus Dei et nostris fidelibus, quon- iam hsec, quae sequuntur, capitula nunc in isto placito nostro, anno ab incar- natione domini nostri Jesu Christi DCCCLXiy., anno videlicet regni nostri ipso propitio xxv., indictione xiL viL Ealend. Julias in hoc loco, qui dicitur PistiB, una cum fidelium nostrorum consensu atque consilio constituimus et cunctis sine ulla ref ragatione per r^gnum nostrum observanda mandamus. . . .

" 6. Et quoniam lex consensu populi et constitutione regis fit, Franci jurare debent, quia secundum regium man- datum nostrum ad justitiam redden- dam vel faciendam legibus bannitus vel mannitus f uit ; et sic ipssd res illi judicio scabiniorum in bannum mittantiir, et, si necesse fuerit, ipse in forbannum mittatur, qui ad justitiam reddendam venire noluerit."






C^AP. XIX.] THE KING AND THE LAW. 239

This phrase represents the common tradition of the Teutonic _ States, and we can see no reason to think that the transforma- tion of the Frankish kingdom into the empire made any change whatever in these constitutional conceptions. We see no reason to think that even Charles the Great dreamed of claiming the position of the ancient Eoman emperors as the sole legislator. It is true, indeed, that Charles the Great and Pippin issue laws in Italy under another form than that which is customary elsewhere, and that in these there is usually no mention of the council and consent of the great men,^ but we think that this must be understood as arising out of their position in Lombardy as conquerors.

We think, then, that the po litijgal theory pLfche nint h ^ regarded jhe ruler as being bound by the laws of the nation, not as superior to them. The' king had his part in making and promulgating law, but others had a part also, and in some vague ^ sense even the whole nation. We think that this is clear, but it^is no doubt also true to say that the historical circumstances of the Frankish States in the ninth century probably tended to give this tradition rather more reality than it may have had be- fore, or in other Teutonic States. The history of the century is the history of a perpetual series of revolts and civil wars, and as a result of these* the royal authority was certainly dwindling, 80 that as the century advances we perhaps find a more and more frank assertion of the limited and even conditional nature of the royal authority.

1 M. H. G. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. Nos. 88, 92, 93, 94, 96, 97, 98.






/..


240


CHAPTER XX.

THE THEORY OF THE SOURCE AND CONDITIONS OF AUTHORITY IN THE STATE.

^We have so far considered the source of the authority of law, and its relation to the king or other ruler. We must now examine the immediate source of the authority of the ruler.

It would be a grave mistake, we tEink, to conceive of the ninth-century writers as having any such definite theory of the delegation of the popular authority to one man as that which obtained among the Roman Jurists. . The theory of the ninth century is much vaguer than this : the divine appoint- ment, the custom of hereditary succession, the election by the great men and the people, — all these elements go to constitute the conception of a legitimate claim to the throne. In a document concerning the election of Charles the Bald to the kingdom of the Eastern Franks in 869 we have a good statement of all the grounds of succession — theright of the legitimate_heir, the appointment of God, and the election of the ng.tion.^

The ^ustom of hereditary succession — that is, of succession within one family — was among the Franks, as generally among the Teutonic tribes, accepted as normal; but it is also true that among the Franks as elsewhere, in order that a succession

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. prsesentem regem ac principem nostrum

276, Electionis Karoli Oapitula in Earolum, ut nobis prsesit et prosit,

R^gno Hlotharii Factse, 869, Sept. 9. videtur nobis, si vobis placet, ut, sicut

2. " Quia denique voluntatem Dei, post illius verba vobis manifestabimus,

qui voluntatem timentium se facit et signo certissimo demonstremus, quia

deprecatione8eorumezaudit,inconcordi ilium a Deo electum et nobis datum

unanimitate nostra videmus hunc regni principem credimus et eidem largitori

hujus heredem esse legitimum, cui nos Deo ex suis beneficiis non simus

sponte commisimus, domnum videlicet ingrati."






CHAP, XX.] SOURCE AND CONDITIONS OF AUTHORITY. 241

should be valid, it should be confirmed by some national election or recognition. We are not here concerned with the consti- tutional question of the organisation of the council of the great men or wise men of the kingdom, — ^that their election was in some sense considered as the election of the nation will hardly be doubted, we think, by any one. The question in which we are now interested is the fact of the elective character of the monarchy of the ninth century rather than its method.

In order to make the matter clear we think it is desirable to consider certain elections as illustrating this principle. There is, indeed, one instance of the appointment of rulers in the Frankish Empire of the ninth century which might seem at first sight to furnish an example of a strictly personal appointment without the sanction of the nation. This is to be found in the statement of th^diyiaion^of-bis dominions by Chgj^les the Great in 806. In this he makes no mention of the ^ counsel or consent of any one, but seems to determine all the questions concerning the appointment of his sons as colleagues to himself during his lifetime, and the division of his dominions among them after his death, by his own will and authority.^ It should, however, be observed that Einhard in his Annuals for the year 806 relates how this settlement was made by Charles at a meeting of the primores and optimates of the Franks, and that it was confirmed by the oath of the Frankish optimates and sent to Pope Leo to be subscribed by his hand.^ It is perhaps also worth noting that even if Charles might be thought to claim the right of nominating his successor, he clearly enough conceives of a return, after his death, to the custom of election. In the fifth clause of the "Divisio Eeg- norum " he provides that if one of his sons should die leaving

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect, ii. vol. i. tueri et regere debuisset, si superstes

No. 46, Divisio Regnorum. illi deveniret. De hac partitione et

2 Einhardi Annales, a. ^6, M. G. H. testamentum factum, et jurejurando

Script., vol. i. : " lllisqu<; ajttsolutis, ab optimatibus Francorum confirm-

conventum habuit imperator cum atum, et constitutiones pacis con-

primoribus et optimatibus Francorum servandse causa factse, atque haec

de pace constituenda et conservanda omnia litteris mandata sunt, et Leoni

inter filios suos, et divisione regni papse, ut his sua manu subscriberet,

facienda in tres partes, ut sciret per Einhardum missa." unusquisque iUorum, quam partem

VOL. L Q






242 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

a son, he should, if the people elect him, reign in his father's place.^ If, however, it should be contended that the relation of the action of Charles the Great to the principle of election is a little ambiguous, there can be no doubt about the matter when we turn to the successors of Charles the Great.

We have already considered the settlement of the empire in 817 by Lewis the Pious,^ and we need only here draw attention to the very explicit terms in which is expressed the consent of the whole people to the election of Lothair, the eldest son, as colleague to his father in the empire, and to the elevation of the younger sons to the dignity and title of kings and to authority in the several portions of the empire,^ and to the provision for the election by the people of their successors.*

We p«iss on to the later part of the century, and we find not only that the^grincigle,.j;)f-©leetian_is-:^ but that we can trace the gradual development of the custom of stating the conditions on which the elections are made. In the documents concerning the succession of Charles the Bald to the kingdom of Italy in 876 we have a very clear statement of the election by the bishops, abbots, counts, and others, and we have also the record of the mutual promises made by subjects and king to each other. The bishops and counts swear obedience, counsel, help, and fidelity, while Charles swears to give law, justice, honour, and mercy to all.^

1 M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. nominibus, et loca inferius denominata No. 45, 5 : " Quod si talis filius cuilibet constituere, in quibus post decessum istorum trium fratrum natus fuerit, nostrum sub seniore fratre reg&ii quern populus eligere velit ut patri potestate potiantur."

suo in regni hereditate succedat, vol- * M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. No.

umus ut hoc consentlant patrui ipsius 136, c. 14.

pueri, et regnare permittant filium ^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. iL

fratris sui in portione regni quam No. 220, Kar. II. Imp. Electio.,.

pater ejus, f rater eorum habuit." 876 Febr. : " Gloriosissimo et a Deo-

2 See p. 237. coronato, magno et pacifico impera- 8 M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. tori, domino nostro Earolo perpetuo

No. 136, Ordinatio Imperii: "Actum augusto nos quidem Ansbertus cum om-

est, ut et nostra et totius populi nostri nibus episcopis, abbatibus, comitibus

in dilecti primogeniti nostri electione ac reliquis . . . perpetuam optamus

vota concurrerent," and " Ceteros vero prosperitatem et pacem. fratres ejus, Pippinum videlicet et "Jam quia divina pietas vos beat-

Hlodowicum eequivocum nostrum, com- orum principum apostolorum Petri et

muni consilio placuit regiis insigniri Pauli ^interventione per vicarium ip-






CHAP. XX.] SOURCE AND CONDITIONS OF AUTHORITY. 243


When Charles the Bald died Lewis the Stammerer finally ^ came to the throne, with the consent of the bishops, the abbots, the primores of the kingdom, and others, and was consecrated and crowned by Hincmar, Archbishop of Eheims.^ We have


sorum, domnum videlicet Johannem Bummum pontificem et universalem papam spiritalemque patrem vestrum, ad profectum sanctsB Dei ecclesiae nostrorumque omnium incitavit et ad imperiale culmen sancti Spiritus judicio provexit, nos unanimiter vos protectorem, dominum ac defensorem omnium nostrum et Italici regni regem eligimus, cui et gaudenter toto cordis affectu subdi gaudemus, et omnia, quae uobiscum ad profectum totius sanctse Dei ecclesise nostro- rumque omnium salutem decemitis et sancitis, totis viribus annuente Cbristo concordi mente et prompta voluntate observare promittimus.

"Anspertus, sanctse Mediolanensis arcbiepiscopus subscripsi," &c.


"Sic promitto ego, quia de isto die

  • in antea isti seniori meo, quamdiu

vixero, fidelis et obediens et adjutor, quantumcumque plus et melius sciero et potuero, et consilio et auxilio secundum meum ministerium in omnibus ero absque fraude et malo ingenio et absque ulla dolositate yel seductioue seu deceptione et absque respectu alicujus personse, et neque per me neque per missum neque per literas . . . contra suum bonorem et suam ac ecclesise atque regni sibi commissi quietem et tranquillitatem atque soliditatem machinabo, . . . neque aliquod umquam scandalum movebo, quod illius prsesenti vel futurse saluti contraria vel nociva esse possit. Sic me Deus adjuvet et ista sanctorum patrocinia.

" Et ego, quantum sciero' et ration- abiliter potuero. Domino adjuvante te, sanctissime ac reverentissime archiepiscope, et unumquemque ves-


trum secundum suum ordinem et personam bonorabo, et salvabo, et honoratum et salvatum absque ullo dolo ac damnatione vel deceptione conservabo, et unicuique competentem legem ac justitiam conservabo, et qui illam necesse habuerint et rationabiliter petierit, rationabilem misericordiam exbibebo, sicut fidelis rex suos fideles per rectum honorare et salvare et unicuique competentem legem et justitiam in unoquoque ordine con- servare et indigentibus et rationabiliter petentibus rationabilem misericordiam debet impendere. Et pro nullo homine ab hoc, quantum dimittit humana fragilitas, per studium aut malevolentiam vel alicujus indebitum hortamentum deviabo, quantum milii Deus intellectum et possibilitatem (donaverit) ; et si per fragilitatem contra hoc mihi surreptum fuerit, cum recognovero, voluntarie illud emendare studebo, sic," &c.

^ M. G. H. Script., vol. i. Hincm. Rem. Annales, ad ann. 877. The primores were indignant because Lewis had granted honores to certain persons " sine illorum consensu." The primores then, with Richildis, "conventum suum ad Montem-Witmari condixerunt," and from there negotiated with Lewis. Finally Richildis and the primores go to him at Compi^gne, and Richildis " attulit ei prseceptum per quod pater suuB illi regnum ante mortem suam tradiderat, et spatam quae vocatur Sancti Petri, per quam eum de regno revestiret, sed et regium vestimentum et coronam ac fustem ex auro et gemmis. Et discurrentibus legatis inter Ludovicum et regni primores, et pactis honoribus singulis quos petierunt, 6 Idus Decembris con- sensu omnium tam episooporum et






244 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

the promises which he made at the time, and in these we find both a very frank recognition of the fact that he is appointed ^ king by the mercy of Gk)d and the election of the people, and very emphatic assurances that he will observe the ecclesiastical rules and the national laws.^

We may compare the tone in which Hincmar addresses Lewis III. While protesting his humility, Hincmar says that he may very well say to him (the king) that it was not he who elected Hincmar to his office in the Church, but Hincmar and his colleagues, with the other faitliful subjects of God and his forefathers, who elected him to be ruler in the kingdom, on the condition of his keeping the laws.*

If we find such strong pledges of good government given by the kings and emperors of the regular line, we need hardly be surprised to find that these become almost stronger in the case of the election of those who were not so near the direct succession. In the documents concerning the election of (^S^ to the kingdom of Aries in 879, we find something very like a formal statement of conditions of election. The synod or assembly sends to Boso inquiring whether he will grant law and justice to all his subjects, great and small, and will listen to all intercession, and freely hearken to all good counsel, seeking rather to make himself useful than merely to be chief. Boso replies that he is but little equal to such a charge as

abbatum, quam regni primorum ceter- dum misericordia Dei committitur,

orumque qui adfuerunt, consecratus et pro communi consilio fidelium nos-

coronatus est in regem Ludovicus ab trorum, secundum quod prsedecessores

Hincmaro Remorum episcopo." mei imperatores et reges gestis in-

^ M. G. H. lieg., sect. ii. vol. ii. No. seruerunt et omnino inviolabiliter

283 (A.) : Professio istius Hlodowici tenenda et observanda decreverunt.

filii Earoli : " Ego Hlodowicus, miseri- Ego igitur Hlodowicus rectitudinis et

cordia domini Dei nostri et electione justitise amore banc spontaneam pro-

populi rex constitutus, promitto teste missionem meam relegens manu pro-

ecclesia Dei omnibus ordinibus, epis- pria firmavi."

ooporum videlicet, sacerdotum, mon- ^ Hincmar of Rheims, Ep. xx. : . . .

€M!horum, canonicorum atque sancti- "ita et ego juxta modulum meum

monialium, regulas a patribus con- humili corde ac voce dicere possum:

Bcriptas et apostolicis adtestationibus Non vos me elegistis in prselatione

roboratas ex hoc et in futurum Ecdesise, sed ego cum coUegis meis et

tempus me illis ex integro servaturum. ceteris Dei ac progenitorum vestrorum

Polliceor etiam me servaturum leges fidelibus, vos elegi ad regimen regni,

et statu ta populo, qui mihi ad regen- sub conditione debitas leges servandi."






CHAP. XX.] SOURCE AND CONDITIONS OP AUTHORITY. 245

that offered, and would have refused it had they not been unanimous, and promises that he will maintain law and justice, and will strive to follow the example of the former good princes, and to maintain equity both to the clergy and to his other faithful men.^ We feel that this is something like a compact between the ruler about to be elected and his subjects.

This is almost more clearly still expressed in the capitularies of the election of Guido as King of Italy by the bishops met at Pavia in 889. The formal document of the election recalls the disastrous confusions that had followed the death of the Em- peror Charles, and then proceeds to state how they have met at Pavia to consider the common welfare of the kingdom, and have elected Guido, inasmuch as the divine aid has enabled him to triumph over his enemies, and inasmuch as he promises to love and honour the holy Eoman Church and to obey the ecclesias- tical laws, and to maintain their own laws to all his subjects, to put down rapine and establish and maintain peace through- out his kingdom. They report that for all these and many other indications of his goodwill they have elected him to the kingdom.^


^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. No. 284, Convent. Mantalensis, 879, Oct. 15 (A). Synodi ad Boeonem regem designatum legatio : " Si vultis omni- bus, siout boni principes . . . legem, justitiiam et rectum concedere et servare, tenentes humilitatem, quae est fundamentum virtutum . . . qui sitis accessibiles omnibus recte suggerentibus et pro aliis intercedentibus, quserentes magis prodesse, quam prseesse . . . Justus patricius vestris majoribus et minoribus apparentes . . . salubre consilium libenter audientes . . . ut neque eadem sancta synodus et primates vestri cum ea sentientes nunc de vobis in bonitate maledicantur vel detrahantur in futuro neque sacro vestro principatui nobis, ut credimus, profuturo juste derogetur. . . ."

(B.) Bosoni regis electi ad synodum responsio —

'* Ego autem conscius mese con-


ditionis et figmenti fragilis imparem me judicans tanto negotio omnimodis abnuissem, nisi per Dei nutum vobis cor unum datum et animam unam in unum consensum advertissem. . . . Omnibus ut monuistis, legem, justi- tiam, et rectum momburgium aux- iliante Deo conservabo et impendere curabo ; quo sequens prsecedentium bonorum principum vestigia tam sacris ordinibus quam vobis nostris fidelibus consulere certem sequitatem servando." 2 M. Q. H. Leg., sect. iL vol. ii. No. 222, Widonis Capitulatio Electionis.' Electionis Decretum : " Post obitum recordandse memorise domni Earoli, gloriosi imperatoris et senioris nostri, quot quantaque pericula huic Italico regno usque in prsesens tempus super- venirent, nee lingua potest evolvere nee calamus explicare. . . . Sed quia illi supervenienti perspicuo principe Widone bis jam fuga lapsi ut fumus






246 POUnCAL THBORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.


It is, however, not only at the time of the election or appointment of a king that we can see something very like a bargain or agreement between people and ruler. More than once we find the emperors or kings trying to bring back con- fidence and order by solemn assurances that they will main- tain law and justice if their subjects on their side will render them true help and obedience. In_^51J[£thdr^Lew and Charles met at Mersen, and issue(La.jiQCUiaent JnjEhich they assure" fliSr IKthfuI^ubjects of jdl j^^ks^ jji^^JSOaditiOTft that~they may he fully secure that for the future they will not condemn or dishonour or oppress any one_iijL,,viQlation of law and' justice or right ^authoril^y^iad- Jreaaan, and. that they" wilt; with the commiMi council of {}}^\t faithful siibjepts^ set'lbfward the restoration of holy (Jhurchj ^"^ ^^^ whnl^ state of the kingdom, in t.bp ft««iiignpftj}hat tha'r_^IafiCte-P" tbeirjpart will be faithiul aud obedient, and true helpers to them, with such counsel and aid ,aa is. due from^eyeryj3ub|6Ct to his prince.^ This assurance or agreement we find repeated


evanuerunt noeque in ambiguo re- liquenint tamquam oves non habentes pastorem, necessarium duximus ad mutuum ooUoquium Papie in aula regia conyenire. Ibique de communi salute et statu hujus regni solliciti pertractantes decreTimus uno animo eademque sententia prsefatum magnan- imum principem Wldonem ad pro- tegendum et regaliter gubemandum no3 in regem et seniorem nobis eligere et in regni fostigium Deo miserante prefigere pro eo, quod isdem magnificus rex divino, ut credimus, protectus auxilio de hoetibus potenter trium- phavit et hoc non sue virtutis, sed 'totom divinae misorationis providentiffi adtribuit^ in super etiam sanctam Bomanam ecdedam ex corde se dili- gere, et exaltare et eodesiastica jura in omnibus observare, et leges proprias singulis quibusque sub sua ditlooe positiB concedere et rapinas de suo regno penitus extirpare, et paoem reformare ^ custodire se ydle Deo teste professus est. Pro his eigo et


aliis multis ejus bonse voluntatis inditiis ipsum, ut prelibayimus, ad regni hujus gubemacula asdvimus, eique toto mentis nisu adhesimns seniorem, pJisRimum et regem ex- ceUentissimum pari consensu ex hinc et in posterum decementes."

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL voL it No. 205, moth., mud., et Karoli Con- ventus apud Marsnam Secundus, 851 : 6. "Ut nostri fideles, unusquisque in suo ordine et statu, yeradter sint de nobis securi, quia nullum aUiinc inaute contra l^em et justiUam vd auctoritatem ac justam rationem aut danmabimus aut ddionorabimus aut opprimemus vel indebitis machina- tionibus affligemus, et iUorum, sdlioet ▼eneiter nolns fidelium, communi con- silio secundum Dei Yoluntatem et commune salvamoitum ad restitu- tionem sanctae Dei eccLeax et statum regni et ad honorem regiom, atque paoem popuH commissi noUs portinenti ads^isum {ff»b^>imii8 in hoc, ut illi non solum non sint nobis






CHAP. XX.] SOURCE AND CONDITIONS OF AUTHORITY. 247

at Goblentz in 860 in almost identical terms/ and again by <3hariesllie^ld in the " Capitula Pistensia of ^9.2 We have also the form in which these promises were issued after the meeting at Coblentz by Lewis, and it is perhaps worth while looking at this, as it exhibits almost more clearly the character of an agreement or mutual promise.'

In the " Capitula Pistensia " of 862 we have another state- ment of the same principle of mutual obligation. These begin with a very solemn acknowledgment of the faults which have brought the present distress upon the country: the king laments that by his own evil deeds he has driven away


contradicentes et resistentes ad ista exsequenda, verum etiam sic sint nobis fideles et oboedientes ao veri adjutores atque co-operatores vero consilio et sincere auxilio ad ista peragenda quae prsBoiisimus, sicut per rectum un- usquisque in suo ordine et statu suo priucipi et suo seniori esse debet."

  • M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. No.

24Z, Hlud., Kar., and Hloth.II., Con- ventus apud Confluentes, clause 10.

2 -^^ Q, H. Leg., sect. ii. voL ii. No. 275 : "3. Ut omnes nostri fideles, veraciter sint de nobis securi, quia, quantum sciero et juste ac rationa- biliter potuero. Domino adjuvante unumquemque secundum sui ordinis dignitatem et personam honorare, et saivare et honoratum ac salvatum con- servare volo, et unicuique eorum in suo ordine secundum sibi competentes leges tam mundanas quam ecclesiasticas rec- tam rationem et justitiam conservabo, et nullum fidelium nostrorum contra legem et justitiam vel auctoritatem ac justam rationem aut damnabo aut dehonorabo aut opprimam aut in- debitis machinationibus affligam; et legem ut prsediximus, unicuique com- petentem, sicut antecessores sui tem- pore antecessorum meorum habuerunt, in omni dignitate et ordine adjuvante Deo conaervaturum perdono, cuilibet duntaxat ex eis, qui mihi fideles et oboedientes ac veri adjutores atque


co-operatores juxta suum ministeri- um et personam consilio et auxilio secundum suum scire et posse et secundum Deum ac secundum seculum fuerint, sicut per rectum unusquisque in suo ordine et statu regi suo et suo seniori esse debet."

' M. G. H. Leg., sect, [i, vol. ii. No. 242, Hlud., Kar., Hloth. XL, Con- ventus apud Confluentes, 860, Jun. Adnuntiatio domini Hludowici regis apud Confluentes lingua Theodisca, 5 : " Et volumus, ut vos et ceteri homines fideles nostri talem legem et rectitudi- nem et tale salvamentum in regnis nostris habeatis, sicut antecessores vestri tempore antecessorum nostrorum habuerunt, et nos talem honorem et rectam potestatem in nostro regio nomine apud vos habeamus, sicut nostri antecessores apud vestros an- tecessores habuerunt ; et justitia et lex omnibus conservetur ; et pauperes homines talem defensionem habeant, sicut tempore antecessorum nostrorum lex et consuetudo fuit, et sicut hie fideles nostri communiter consenserunt et scripto nobis demonstraverunt et nos cum illorum consilio consentimus et observari communiter volumus. Et si aliquis hoc perturbare voluerit, a nuUo nostrum recipiatur, nisi ut aut ad rectam rationem aut ad ration- abilem indulgentise concessionem de- ducatur."






248 POLITICAL THBORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

the H0I7 Spirit, which was given to him hj the imposition of hands of the bishops at his consecration. Then there fol- lows a passage, which we have already quoted, on the divine nature and authority of government on earth, and this again is followed by an exhortation to all to strive together for justice; and the capitulary concludes by saying that by com- mon consent it has been decreed to sign this, remembering that as all men of all ranks expect that the king shall main- tain their proper and lawful rights, so all men of all ranks must observe the proper and lawful honour and obedience due to the king.^

We have seen that the principle of the joint action of the king and the nation in making law finds a formal expression in the "Edictum Pistense"; we may find a good illustration of the significance of the promises of justice and obedience on the part of kings and subjects in another document of this time, the Capitula ad Francos et Aquitanos Missa de Carisiaco" of 856. A large part of his kingdom was in revolt against Charles the Bald, and these Capitula were drawn up with the view of pacifying the revolters, and present us with a very clear statement of the conception that just as his subjects were bound by certain obligations to the king, so he on his part was bound by very distinct obligations to them: they even speak of these mutual obligations as constituting a pactum. What is more than this, the capitula are drawn in the form

^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. iL yoL ii. ore didmos, in diviois oculis esse

Na 272, Capitulft Pistensia, 862 : vftlemus. Ut autem hsec, qu» observ-

"1. Quia iUum Spiritum Sanctum, anda supra scripsimus ac prsenomin-

qui requievit super adjutorem in avimus, nunc et de cetero certius

oportunitatibus, in tribulatione, et expre^us a nobis atque a suc-

Chnstum dominum nostrum, et oesscnribus noetris inconTulsa serventur,

quern per impoeitionem manus epis- propriis manibus his subecribere ccmi-

oopalis in consignatione accepimus, muni consensu decrevimus ea condi-

oontristatum malignis operibus a tione servata, ut, quia omnes in

nobis effugavunus. . . . cunctis ordinibus a rogia ditione sibi

"4. Quoniamnisicommunitercertav- expetunt oompetentia kgis jura ser-

erimus, ut in omnibus justitia omni- vari, regise quoque potestati in cunctis

bus oonservetur, nee rex pater patri» ordinibus lex juris debiti et honor ab

nee epiacopi propitiatores et reocm- omnibus obedienter et fideliter co-

ciliatores populi ad salutem etemam oporante Domino consenretur." See

nee, qui participatione nominis Christi pw 213. christiani vocantur, hoc, quod humano






CHAP. XX.] SOUKCE AND CONDITIONS OF AUTHORITY. 249


of an address from the loyal subjects of Charles to the revolters, and while they urge them to come back to their allegiance, and intimate plainly that they will in the future compel obedience to the just judgments of the king, on the other hand they intimate just as clearly that if the king, "juxta humanam fragilitatem," should do anything contrary to the pactum^ they will, reverently and honourably, admonish him of his duty ; and they assure the rebels that if, when he is thus admonished, he should wish to do injustice, the king will be unable to carry out his wilU The document exhibits


^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. voL iL No. 262, Cap. ad Francos et Aquit- anos Missa de Carisiaco, 856, Jul. 7 : '^Haec, qu8B secuntur, capitula misit dominus rex Karolus ad Francos et Aquitanos, qui ab eo desciverant, anno incamationis dominicse dccclyi. Nouis Julii de palatio Carisiaco per fideles missos suos Adalardum abbatem, Rodulfum, Richuinum, Adalgarium et Berengarium."

"10. Et sciatis, quia sic est adun- atus cum omnibus suis fidelibus in omni ordine et statu et nos omnes sui fideles de omni ordine et statu, ut, si ille juxta humanam fragilitatem aliquid contra tale pactum fecerit, ilium honeste et cum reverentia, sicut seniorem decet, ammonemus, ut ille hoc corrigat et emendet et uni- cuique in suo ordine debitam legem conservet. Et si aliquis de nobis in quocunque ordine contra istum pactum incontra ilium fecerit, si talis est, ut ille inde enim ammonere voleat, ut emendet, faciat ; et si talis est causa, ut ille ilium familiariter non debeat ammonere, et ante suos pares ilium in rectam rationem mittat, et ille, qui debitum pactum et rectam legem et debitam seniori reverentiam non vult exhibere et obserrare, justum justitiee judicium sustineat. Et si sustinere non Toluerit et contumax et rebellis extiterit et converti non potuerit, a nostra omnium societate et regno ab omnibus expellatur. Et


si senior noster legem unicuique debitam et a se et a suis ante* cessoribus nobis et nostris ante- cessoribus perdonatam per rectam rationem vel misericordiam com- petentem unicuique in suo ordine conservare non voluerit et ammonitus a suis fidelibus suam intentionem non voluerit, sciatis, quia sic est ille nobiscum et nos cum illo adunati et sic sumus omnes per illius voluntatem et consensum confirmati, episcopi atque abbates cum laicis et laici cum viris ecclesiasticis, ut nullus suum parem dimittat, ut contra suam legem et rectam rationem et justum judicium, etiamsi voluerit, quod absit, rex noster alicui facere non possit. . . .

"12. Et sciatis, quia vult senior noster et nos ac coeteri fideles illius, ut, si voB, qui illius fideles et con- siliarii esse debetis, volueritis, sicut vobis diximus, ad illius prsesentiam et fidelitatem atque servitium venire et nobiscum in ista societate esse, quia et ipse et nos quse voluntarie volemus, ut cum nobis hoc et quseratis et in- veniatis et statuatis et confirmetis atque conservetis et nos cum vobis similiter : et vobis aliis omnibus, sicut et nobis, debitam legem et rectam rationem dehinc inante, sicut rectum est, vult conservare, sicut sui ante- cessores, qui hoc melius et ration- abilius feoerunt, nostris et vestris antecessoribus in omni ordine con- servaverunt."






250 POUTICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [PABT IV.

not only the conception of a mutual agreement made, at his election or otherwise, between the king and the people, but also the conception that the subjects have the same right to compel the king to observe his agreement as he has to compel them to observe theirs.

The circumstances of the ninth century tended thus^tofevour the development of the conception that tHe^ruler holds his place in virtue of the election of the nation, and of his fulfih^kat of t he pro mises on which that election was based ; and there_were not wanting in the century circumstances which tended towards the further conclusion, that if the king failed to dischai^e the ob^gations which Tie had undertaken, he might not improperly "Be deposed. The deposition of the unhappy Lg wis the Pious serves to illustrate tfiis tendency, and probably also helped materially to develop it. We cannot here discuss either the general circumstances or the constitutional conditions of the deposition or abdication of Lewis the Pious. But it is for our purpose extremely important to observe the terms in which the deposition of Lewis is alluded to. It was at Compi^ne in the year 833 that Lewis was compelled to abdicate, and the bishops, there assembled, published a state- ment in which they set forth the great faults that Lewis had committed, — how he had neglected his charge, and done many things displeasing to God and men ; and they relate how they had exhorted him to repentance, inasmuch as he had been deprived of his earthly power in accordance with the counsel of God and the ecclesiastical authority.^ In the next chapter we must consider the significance of this reference to the

' M. Q. H. Leg., sect, iu voL ii. tamen memores prseoeptorum Dei,

No. 197, Episc. de Pom. quam Hlud. ministeriique nostri atque benefici-

Imp. professuB est, Relatio Compend- orum ejus dignum duximus, ut per

iensia, 833 : ** Sed quia idem prinoeps licentiam memorati principis Lotharii

ministerium sibi commissum negli- legationem ad iUum ex auctcnitate

genter tractayerit et multa, quae Deo sacri conventus mitteremus, quse eum

et hominibus displicebant, et fecerit de suis reatibus admoneat, quatenus

et facere compulerit vel fieri per- oertum consilium suae salutis caperet,

miserit et in multia nefandis con- ut» quia potestate privatus erat

siliifl Deum irritaverit et sanctam terrena juxta divinum consilium et

eccledam scandalizaverit . . . et ab eodesiasticam auctoritatem, ne suam

eo divino justoque judicio subito im- animam perderet> elaborare in extremis

perialis sit subtracta potestas, noe positus totis viribus studeret."






CHAP. XX.] SOURCE AND CONDITIONS OF AUTHORITY. 251

action of the ecclesiastical authority in the deposition of Lewis. In the meanwhile we are only concerned to observe that the bishops look upon the deposition as lawful.

It is in this same sense that Hincmar of Bheims appears to refer to the subject in his treatise on the divorce of Lothair and Tetburga, in a passage to which we have already referred. He is arguing against those who maintained that the king was sub* ject to no laws or judgments, and pointing out that kings like David were rebuked by the prophets, Theodosius by St Am- brose, goes on to say that in his own time the pious Emperor Lewis had been cast down from his kingship, and was restored to it " post, satisfactionem " by the bishops with the consent of the people.^ Hincmar seems to mean that the deposition had been unwise, but he does not suggest that in itself there was anything improper in the action; indeed the general context would suggest that he regarded such action as being under certain circumstances proper and right.

It is true that in that letter or treatise of Hrabanus Maurus which we have already cited, Hrabanus, referring to the depos- ition of Lewis, speaks very emphatically about the honour due from sons to their parents, and the honour and obedience which all men are to give to the royal authority, and illustrates the right attitude of the subject by the classical example of David and Saul, and from more recent historical examples shows the judgment which overtakes those who rise against their legitimate princes. We have already cited the letter as illustrating the persistence of the characteristic mode of thought of Gregory the Great in the ninth century, and there is nothing to surprise us in the fact that those who disapproved of the revolt against Lewis the Pious should have appealed to these principles.*

Perhaps the strongest illustration of the tendency to conceive of the deposition of the king as being under certain circum- stances justifiable is to be found in a document or proclamation

^ Hincmar of Rheims, De Div. Loth. cum populi consensu, et Ecclesise et

€t Tet., Quest, vi Resp. : "Nostra regno restituit."

aetate pium Augustum Ludovicum a ^ Hrabanus Maurus, Epist. 15, in

regno dejectum, post satisf actionem M. G. H. Ep., v. See p. 216. episcopalisjunanimitas, saniore consilio.






252 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.

. issued in 859 by Charles the Bald against those who wished to depose him. In this document, after appealing to his claim of hereditary succession from the Emperor Lewis, he argues that ^ * he was elected with the will, consent, and acclamation of the bishops and other faithful men of the kingdom, and was conse-> crated, anointed, and crowned by Wenilo, Bishop of Orleans, and that from the office in which he was then placed he cannot be cast out, at least without the judgment of the bishops by whom he was then consecrated. "They are," he says, "the thrones of God," among whom God sits, and by whom he . decrees judgments, and to their paternal correction and chas- tisement he is willing to submit, and does submit.^

We shall have to consider this passage again in discussing the relation of the ecclesiastical and secular powers, but in the meanwhile it is worthy of note, as indicating in a very forcible way that the deposition of a king, who was held to have failed to discharge bis obligations, was a thing not wholly improper in the minds of the men of the ninth century. We may very well recall those phrases concerning the distinc- tion between the king and the tyrant which we considered in a previous chapter, and we shall feel that the conception of the character of the king, as depending upon his respecting and maintaining justice, was not a mere piece of abstract sentiment, but was tending to have a more or less practical and effective influence on public life.

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect, ii yol. iL diademate atque regni soeptro in regni

No. 300, LibeUus prodamationis ad- solio sablimavit. A qua consecratione

yeraus Wenflonem, c 3 : " Sed et poet vel regni sublimitate subplantari vel

hoc electione sua aliorumque episco- proid a nuUo debueram, saltern sine

porum ac ceterorum fidelium regni audientia et judicio episcoporum,

nostri voluntate, consensu et aodama- quorum ministerio in regem sum

tione cimi aliis archiepisoopis et epis- consecratus et qui throni Dei sunt

copis Wenilo in diocesi sua apud Aurel- dicU, in quibus Deus sedet, et per

ianis civitatem in basilica sanctse crucis quos sua deoemit judicia ; quorum

me secundum traditionem ecdesias- patemis correptionibus et castigatoriis

ticam regem consecravit et in regni judidis me subdere fui paratus et in

regimine chrismate sacro perunxit et prsesenti sum subditus.'*






253


CHAPTEE XXI.

THE RELATION OF THE AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE.

We must now resume the consideration of the theory of the relations of the secular and ecclesiastical authorities. No student of the history of the Middle Ages will doubt that the theoretical and actual relations of the two great powers in society continually exercised a very strong influence upon the theory of the State and the theory of the origin and nature of political authority.

To the political theorists of the ninth century, however great their reverence for the king and the secular authority, there is obviously always present the consideration that along gide of the law of the State there stands a law which the nation has j not made, aulaj^which is more majfisticAndjaoitboritative than i that of any secular society— the law of the Christian Church;/ ' and that alongside of the secular organisation and institutions ^ there stand the organisation and institutions of the Church. Ifjhfi.. ruler is bound to respect tlje law of the nation, muchi^ more is he bound to respect and obey the law of the Church i "^ and while the great organisation of the Catholic Church may admit him to some share in its councils, may look to him for^ assistance in enforcing its decrees, yet the Church is not only independent of him in religion but looks upon him as its*^ subject in spiritual matters.

We have seen that the patristic theory of the relation of the two powers, the ecclesiastical and the civil, finds its completest _ statement and definition in the letters and tractates of izelasius J^ These may also be said to furnish us with the best starting- point for examining the theory of the ninth century. The






254 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.


bishops^ of the empir e, in a long and important statement on the condition of Church and State and the nature of ecclesias- tical and civil authority, addressed in the vear '^^^o the ^gj^T^r JSiV^^ thq F?»ii«, quqte^jad. gommf^nt on tho worda.ol . (jelasi u s' twelfth letter, in which hfl hgYl Rgjj[j;j]^t thfirft ^^^ j-^lwo authorities by which alojaa^All. thfiLJ^Otldaa gOYfirned— tjie j ^sacr ed authority of the bishop, and the powej^^of .th^. fiQYeielgSc^ The same passage is quoted by Jjyi9A,>gL,0dfiai>s in the first chapter of his work ^JteNjnstit^tionfi^Eggia,' ^ while Hincmar of Eheims cites the words of this letter and also those of Gelasius* fourth tractate.*





PjfM. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii. ^ic. 196, Episcoporum ad Hlud. Imp. Relatio, 3 : " Quod ejusdem sec- clesiae corpus in duabus principaliter dividatur ezimiis personis. Princi- paliter itaque totius sanctae Dei ecclesise corpus in duas eximias per- sonas, in sacerdotalem videlicet et regalem, sicut a Sanctis patribus tra- ditum accepimus, divisum esse novi* mus ; de qua re Gelasius Romanse sedis venerabilis episcopus ad Anastasium imperatorem ita scribit: *Du8e sunt quippe,' inquit, *imperator auguste quibus principaliter mundus hie regi- tur, auctoritas sacrata pontificum et regalis potestas ; in quibus tanto grav- ius pondus est sacerdotum, quanto etiam pro ipsis regibus hominum in divino reddituri sunt examine ra- tionem.' Fulgentius quoque in libro de Veritate Prsedestinationis et Gratia ita scribit : * Quantum pertinet,* inquit, 'ad hujus temporis vitam, in secclesia nemo pontifice potior, et in saeclo christiano nemo imperatore celsior invenitur.* "

- 2 Jonas of Orleans, De Instit. Reg., cap. i. : "Sciendum omnibus fideli- bus est quia universalis Ecclesia cor- pus est Christi et ejus caput idem est Christus, et in ea duse principaliter exstant eximise personse, sacerdotalis videlicet et regalis, tantoque est prse- stantior sacerdotalis, quanto pro ipsis


J

regibus Deo est rationem redditurus» Unde Gelasius Romanse Ecclesise vener- abilis pontifex ad Anastasium im- peratorem scribens, * Duo quippe . . . examine rationem reddituri.^ Fulgentius quoque in libro de Veri- tate Prsedestinationis et Gratiae ita scribit : * Quantum attinet ad hujus- temporis vitam, in Ecclesia nemo pon- tifice potior et in sseculo Christiana imperatore nemo celsior invenitur. '^ Ergo quia tantae auctoritatis, imo tanti discriminis est ministerium sacerdotum,. ut de ipsis etiam regibus Deo sint rationem reddituri, oportet et valde necesse est, ut de vestra salute semper simus solliciti, vosque ne a voluntate Dei, quod absit, aut a ministerio quod vobis commisit, erretis, vigilanter ad- moneamus, et si, quod absit, ab eo> aliquo modo exorbitaveritis, pontifical! studio humiliter admonendo, et sal- ubriter procurando, opportunum con- sultum saluti vestrse conferamus, ut non de silentio tacitumitatis nostrse- damnemur, sed magis de solertissima cura et admonitione salutifera remun- erari a Christo mereamur."

^ Hincmar of Rheims, Ad Episc. De Inst. CaroL cap. i : ** Hinc- marus episcopus ac plebis Dei fam- ulus. Doctrina est Christiana, secun- dum sanctarum scripturarumtramitem, prsedicationemque majorum, qua Dea ac Domino nostro Jesu Chriatu con-






05AP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHCTROH AND STATE. 255



It is important to observe not only the fact that these pass- ages are quoted, but the character of the comments which are made on them. Xbgjtjishogs^in 829 preface their quotation by f^ the statement that the body of the Church of God is divided w chiefly between two exalted persons, tjiepriestjy and Jh§jx)yal. / Jonas of Orleans puts the same view more clearly when he tells us that all faithful men should know that the uniirersal Church is the body of Christ, and that Christ is tjj^nead of the body, and in this body there are two per^s of chief authority, the priest and the king. While Gelasius thinks ofij/ these two authorities as existing in the world, the bishops and^ Jonas conceive ol iJienx. as being both within. thfiuChuich. I

It is also worth noting that while the bishops simply quote the words of Gelasius, "In quibus tanto gravius pondus est


17^


ditore et redemptore nostro, qui simul solus rex et sacerdos fieri potuit, in cujus nomine omne genuflectitur, coelestium, terrestrium et infemorum, disponente, sicut beatu8 Qelasius papa ad Anastasium imperatorem dicit, et in gestis quae nuper apud martyrium sanctsQ Macrae in synodo gesta sunt partim continetur, duo sunt, quibus principaliter, una cum specialiter cujuscumque curse subjectis, mundus hie regitur, auctoritas sacra pontificum, et regalis potestas ; in quibus personis, sicut ordine sunt divisa vocabula, ita sunt et divisa in unoquoque ordine ac professione ordinationum officia. Quamvis enim membra veri regis atque pontificis secundum participationem naturae, magnifice utrumque in sacra generositate sumpsisse dicantur, ut simul regale genus et sacerdotale sub- sistant, memor tamen Christus fragili- tatis humanae, quod suorum salute congrueret, dispensatione magnifica temperans, sic actionibus propriis, dignitatibusque distinctis officia potes- tatis utriusque discrevit, suos volens medicinali humilitate salvari, non humana superbia rursus (ut ante adventum ejus in camem pagani im- peratores, qui iidem et maxime ponti-


fices dicebantur), intercipi, ut et Christ- iani reges pro aeterna vita pontificibus indigerent, et pontifices pro temper- alium cursu rerum imperialibus dispo- sitionibus uterentur ; quatenus spirit- • alis actio a camalibus distaret incursi* bus, et ideo militans Deo minime se negotiis saecularibus implicaret, ae vicissim non ille rebus divinis prae- sidere videretur qui esset negotiis sae* cularibus implicatus, ut et modestia utriusque ordinis curaretur, ne extol- leretur utroque sufiultus, et competens qualitatibus actionum specialiter pro- fessio aptaretur.

Cap. ii. Sed tanto gravius pondus est sacerdotum, quanto etiam pro ipsis regibus hominum in divino reddituri sunt examine rationem ; et tanto est dignitas pontificum major quam regum, quia reges in culmen regium sacrantur a pontificibus, pontifices autem a regi- bus consecrari non possunt ; et tanta in humanis rebus regum cura est pro- pensior quam sacerdotum, quanto pro honore et defensione et quiete sancta& Ecclesiae, ac rectorum et ministrorum ipsius, et leges promulgando, ac mili- tando, a Rege regum est eis curse onus- impositum."






256 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

sacerdotum," Jonas, in his introduction, calls the priestly person prcestantior, and in applying this conception he ^ urges that the priest must always anxiously care for the salvation of the king and carefully admonish him lest he should turn aside from the will of God or neglect the charge which God has committed to him. While Gelasius, that is, • insists only upon the obedience which the king should render to the priests in religious matters, and the priest to the king in secular matters, Jojias_also thinks, tfeaL. the __priestis^ inj some measure responsible to see that the, kipg does his duty^ even in secular affairs.

Hincmar embodies large parts of the tenth letter and of the fourth tractate of Gelasius. Christ is the only person who was both king and priest, and although there is a sense in which Christians may be called a royal and priestly race, yet Christ, mindful of the infirmity of human nature, has allotted to each authority its own duties, so that Christian kings require the bishops for eternal life, and the bishops require the king for temporal things, and therefore the clergy should keep themselves clear of secular business, and the secular person should not interfere in spiritual matters. So far Hincmar does little more than follow Gelasius, but his development of the principle "Tanto gravius est pondus sacerdotum," &c., is different and noteworthy. The burden of the priest is greater, because he will have to give account, in the judgment, even for kings, and the dignity of the bishop is greater than that of the king, because kings are consecrated to their ofl&ce by the bishop, while the bishop cannot be consecrated by kings.

In three important points, then, we see that some ninth- century writers have developed the position of Gelasius,-^^ first, that both the secular and the spiritual powers are within the Church; the second , that in some measure the priest is responsible to see that the secular ruler does .his duty; and the third, that the dignity of the ecclesiastical person is greater, for it is by him that the king is consecrated: and «ach of these principles has importance in the ninth-century conception of the relation between the spiritual and the






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 257

temporal powers. In the main it is clear that the ninth century simply carries on from the sixth the principle of the two authorities in society — two authorities which are theoretically independent of each other in their own spheres ; but the experience of the ninth century tended to bring out the difl&culties of this position, and to develop the tendency towards the assertion of the priority of one or other of the tWoQ The conditions of the time are indeed so com- plex that we could easily quote phrases from the legal docu- ments and the general authors of the period to support almost any theory of the relations of the two powers. It would be easy to produce evidence to show that the temporal power was really superior .even in ecclesiastical matters ; to show that the consent of the king or emperor was necessary for ecclesiastical action, and that it was the secular power which controlled all ecclesiastical appointments. On the other hand, it would be quite as easy to produce evidence to show that the Church was actually superior to the State ; that the king was absolutely under the canonical law, liable to excommunication like any private person ; that it was the Church which really conferred the royal authority, and that the Church could take it away again.

A century or two later we shall find views of this kind set out in open contradiction to each other ; we shall find Europe filled with the clamour of the great struggle for supremacy between the Church and the Empire. But it is the charac- teristic of the ninth century that these apparently divergent tendencies of thought can often be traced in the same person ; that we find the same person using language which in later times would mark him clearly as a papalist, and the next moment using phrases which became the catchwords of the imperialist.

It is possible, no doubt, to maintain that in the early years of the ninth century the authority of the. State relatively to the ^hurch was at its highest^oint, and that the opposed concep- tion develops tHroughouF the century till it culminates in the pseudo-Isidorian literatura But we think that the safest judg- ment which we can form on the whole character of the ninth

VOL. I. R







258 POUTICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.

A"

century is this, th at men were convinc^ that each power had its own a^ropriatesphere^ but that they were also keenly alive tcTthe Fact^TEaFm practical life the two spheres intersected, and that no general principle could enable them to determine, with regard to many questions, what exactly was the sphere ^f the State and what the sphere of the Church.

^We may find a very good illustration of the complexity of the situation and the ambiguities of theory in the position of that writer to whom we have already so often referred, Sedulius /^ / Scotu st whose work seems to belong to the middle of the / / century. He does not seem to have had the same practical / experience of affairs as Hincmar of Bheims, and there are / therefore some points on which Hincmar is his superior; but / he shows a considerable power of putting together his views, / so that, in spite of a certain incoherence of detail, they really

form an organic whole. At any rate, it may be useful to consider for a moment what are his views as to the position of the emperor or king relatively to the Church. — ^ He begins his treatise by urging the prince to remember that he should give thanks to Grod and honour to His Church. The whole commonwealth flourishes when the king fears and honours God and provides carefully for the wellbeing of the Church.^ The charge of the king, then, is not to be thought of as merely secular. The work of the king is to set forward such conditions as will further the cause of religion as well as the temporal well- being of the State. If his heart is not set upon God's service, God may take the kingdom from him.* He has therefore great responsibilities in Church matters as well as in secular. He must prefer the wellbeing of the Church to his own personal advantage, and must help and protect all those who work in Gk)d's service.' We have here simply the conmion mediaeval conception of the duty of the ruler of the State to do what he can to further the work of the Church. Sedulius evidently did not imagine that the State could stand aside and refuse to take a part in the service of religion. But this is not all. The good ruler, he says, will set forward the wellbeing of the Church in

/^l^ Sedulius Scotus, De Rectoribus * Id. 8.

^^ChristUnis, 1. » Id. 11.






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 259

all ways, and he must remember that God has set him as His vicar in the government of the Church, and has given him power over both orders of rulers and subjects,^ and therefore he ' is especially admonished to see to the holding of synods every year.* We have in an earlier chapter referred to this title of the Vig fl? of Go d as applied to the secular ruler. Certainly as \ ^ed by Sedulius it seems cl^dy ta imply a large measure of J authority even over the Church.

^ So far we have one aspect of the theory of Sedulius. But if we now turn back to the eleventh chapter of his treatise we shall see the other side of the matter. Here also the king is^ admonished to provide diligently for the meeting of synods, inasmuch as these are of great benefit to the Church. But then, abruptly and somewhat sharply, he is warned that he must not interfere recklessly in ecclesiastical affairs ; he must show him- self humble and very cautious, and beware lest he should take > upon himself to judge of any ecclesiastical affair before he has [ learnt the decrees of the synods. The pious ruler will carefully hear what is just and lawful according to the canonical decision of the holy bishops, and will then give his consent and authority to what is just and true. He will in no way form any prcqu- didum on such matters, lest haply, falling into error, he should find himself guilty of some fault hateful in the sight of God. Sedulius enforces this with a story of how Valentinian, when he was invited by the bishops to take part in some doctrinal dis- cussion, said that he was in no way worthy to take part in such^ matters, but that this belonged to the priests.^ Sedulius follows

^ Sedulius Scotua, De Rectoribua regem : nee quidquam de negotiis

ChriBtianiB, 19 : " Oportet enim Deo ecclesiasticis judicare prsesumat, ante-

amabilem regnatorem, quern divina quam synodalia statuta cognoscat. . . .

ordinatio tanquam vicarium suum in Pius itaque rector tanquam luminosa

regimine Ecclesise suae esse voluit, et pupilla primo quod justum et legiti-

potestatem ei super utrumque ordinem mum est secundum canonicas sanc-

prselatorum et subditorum tribuit, ut torum episcoporum sanctiones perspi-

singulis personis et quse justa sunt caciter attendat; dehinc consensum

decemat, et sub sua dispensatione atque auctoritatis adminiculum his

prior ordo devote obediendo fideliter quae sunt vera et justa adhibeat. Per

subditus fiat." se vero nuUatenus de talibus prseju-

> Id. id. dicium faciat, ne forte errando ante

'Id. 11: " Unde cautum et humilem conspectum domini culpam aliquam

et valde circumspectum oportet esse detestabilem incurrat. Unde venera-






260 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH OKNTUEY. [part iv.

this up in the next chapter by urging the ruler to make himself an example of humility and obedience. If he is reproved by wise men he should repent ; and Sedulius cites the examples of David and Nathan, of Theodosius and Ambrose.^

If, then, in the title of Vicar of God in the government of

His Church Seduliud expresses something of the authority of

the king even over churchmen, in his treatment of his relation

^ to the synods and their decisions he gives us the other side of

V the matter. It must be noticed, however, that even here the

king has his own place, at least in the execution of Church law.

After he has heard the judgment of the bishops, it still remains

for him to give his consent and authority to what has been

decreed.

/ We have before cited the letter of Cathultus o n the nature of

/ the royal authority, ^fi sfAtAg^ ftven njinrft^ftgTjjiftjifiall^ than

j Sedulius, that the king is ^i^jg^^fj^.^'^l^tiv'^ ofj}:!}^^* ft"^ ^^

I certainly seems to imply that the position of the, bishop is

1 secondary. He bids the king remember God always with fear

/ and love, for he is in God's place, to watch over and govern all

I God's members, and will have to give account for these in the

^ day of judgment. The bishop is, in the second place, " in vice

Christi tantum." The king must therefore carefully see that he

' establishes the law of God over the people of Gk)d, whose place

he holds, " cujus vicem tenes." He must, with his bishops,

superintend the life of the monks and nuns, but he must do

this through spiritual pastors, not through laymen, for that

would be wickedness.^ We should judge that the position of

bilis memorise Valentinianus Imperator latur eumque ad virtutem sequendam

cum a Sanctis episcopis rogaretur qua- admonet." '^Memor esto ei^o semper,

tenus dignaretur ad emendationem rex mi, Dei regis tui cum timore et

sacri dogmatis interesse, 'Mihi,' inquit, amore, quod tu es in vice illius super

'cum minimus de populo sim, fas non omnia membra ejus custodire et regere,

est talia perscrutari, verum sacerdotes et rationem reddere in die judidi,

quibus h»c cura est, apud seiyetipsos etiam per te. Et episcopus est in

congregentur ubi voluerint.'" secundo loco, in vice Christi tantum

^ Sedulius Scotus, De Rectoribus est Ergo considerate inter voa dili-

Christianis, 12. genter legem Dei constituere super

^ M. Q. H. Ep., iv. '^ Epistoise populum Dei, quod Deus tuus dixit

Variorum Carolo Magno Begnante tibi, cujus vicem tenes, in pealmo :

Scriptse," 7 : " Cathuulfus Carolo I. ' Et nunc reges intelligit&' et reliqua ;

Francorum Begi prosperitatem gratu- item : ' Servite Domino in timore,' et






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 261

Cathulfus was practically the same as that of Sedulius, thought undoubtedly he is more emphatic in his assertion of a certain^ priority of the royal power. The letter is, however, too brief, and the discussion too incomplete, to enable us to form a very definite decision upon the subject.^

The conception of the separate provinces of the secular and the spiritual powers is so well defined in the fifth century, and so iSaref uUy restated in the ninth, that we cannot doubt that all parties, lay or clerical, would have, in theory, held that the powers were co-ordinate, and, in their own spheres, independent \ of each other. But, as a matter of fact, circumstances were too s trong for theory, and not only did the definition and delimita- tion of the boun daries of the province of each jw)wer prove a . task of insuperable diflBcu lty, but ^achjower in turn found ^ itself compelle d to trench in some measure uppn^th^ province of the other. We begin by considering some of the many points in which> in spite of the theory of the independence and authority of the Church, the Statcidid actually trench uponV its prerogatives.

We have seen how Sedulius and Cathulfus speak of the king or emperor as the vicar of God in the government of His Church ; that is, they conceive that it is part of the duty of the civil ruler to maintain good order and piety in the Church. We find the same pr i nciple very strongly d eclared by Smaraj dus. He urges upon the king that if he sees any thing wro; in the Church of Christ it is his duty to reprove and correct i If he sees any person in the Church of God running into luxur; or drunkenness, he is to forbid, to terrify him. He is to put^

reliqua; item * Adprehendite discip- ^ The letter of Cathulfus belongs

linam ne quando irascatur Dominus,' probably to the last years of the

et reliqua. . . . 'Sponsam Christi eighth century,— that is, to a time

vestire cum omamentis super omnia, when the papacy was under a doud id est ecclesiarum priyilegia constituere ' and the authority of Charles the

maxima. Monachorum vitam et can- Great in relation to the Church was

onicorum cum episcopis tuis simul at its highest point; and the letter

virginum monasteriorum regere. Non cannot therefore be taken as properly

per laicos, quod scelus . . . sed per representative of the general stand-

spiritales pastores emendare, super point of the ninth century, except

omnia Deuip timentes, sicut scriptum so far as its statements are found to

(est) in lege.' " be confirmed by later writers.







262 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH OBNTUKY. [part iv.


. down all pride and anger with threats and sharp reproofs. He is to do what he can as a king, as a Christian, and as the repre- sentative of Christ (" pro vice Christi qua fungeris '*)} We can find illustrations of this conception of the duty of the civil ruler to maintain good order and discipline in the Church in the proceedings of Charles the Great, of Lewis the Pious, and of

V Charles the Bald. In the Capitula^jdejSanRia.fiUTn Kpisropis et Abbatibus^Jjcactandis " of 81 i we have a list of topics on which the bishops and abbots are to be interrogated, and certainly the tone of the questions indicates clearly enough that Charles the Great thought it his duty to look very sharply into the conduct of the clergy even in purely religious matters.^ In the " A^mnm'ti^ fi^ '^rnn^^HP^^i oxdines," issued by Lewis the Pious in 823-5, Lewis lays down very explicitly the prin- ciple that it is his duty to admonish men of all orders as to the discharge of their duties, and frames regulations for a very comprehensive inquiry which is to be made by taking the evidence of the .bishops about the conduct of the counts in administering justice, and that of the counts as to the conduct of the bishops in their life and teaching.' In the


\^^^maragdu8 Abbas, Via Regia, 8 : "Si quid forte perversum in Ecdesia yideris Christi, satage corripere, et emendare non cesses. Si yideris all- quern in domo Dei, quse est Ecclesia, currere ad luxuriam ad ebrietatem, prohibe, veta, terre, si lelus domus Dei comedit te. Si videris superbia inflatum, aut iracundia ssevum, . . . reprime omnes, minare omnibus, et refrena seyerissime omnes. Fao quic- quid potee pro persona quam gestas, pro ministerio regali quod portas, pro nomine Christiani quod babes, pro yioe Christi qua fungoris."

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect, ii yoL L No. 72, Capitula de Causis cum Episoopis et Abbatibus Tractandis.

' M. Q. H. Leg., sect, ii yoL L No. 150: "3. Sed quamquam summa hujus ministerii in nostra persona oonsista^ yideatur, tamen et diyina auctoritate et humana ordinatione ita


per partes diyisum esse oognoscitur, ut unusquisque yestrum in suo loco et ordine partem nostri ministerii habere cognoscatur; unde apparet, quod ego omnium yestrum admonitor esse debeo, et omnes yos nostri adjutores esse debetis. . . .

" 14. Volumus studere . . . et per commune testimonium, id est epis- coporum de comitibus, comitum de episcops, comperire, qualiter scilicet comites justiUam diligant et ^Muant, et quam religiose e^nscopi ooDYer- sentur et prsddicent, et amborum relatn de idiorum fideUum in suis ministeriis oonsistentium sequitate et pace atque conoordia cognoaoere. Similiter etiam yolumus, ut omnes illis et illi omnibus de ccMnmuni societate et statu a nolns interrogatiy yerum testimonium dbi mutuo per- hibere possint."






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 263


Qft BJtulare Sept ipgiaJiifaxgi^aBl^Jolosam datiiga" of 844 we find Charles the Bald strictly forbidding the bishops to take action against those priests who had appealed to him for pro- / tection against the oppression of the bishops, and warning them ^ that they must obey his injunctions, and see that every one obeys the Canons.^ In 853 we find the same Charles sending round his missi" to hold inquiries and correct abuses in all cities and monasteries along with the bishop of each diocese.^

There are even indications in the literature and history of the y times that the r esponsibility jgf _thfi ftTPpergr^^qy/j;^ con(iusli of ^^^


theChuTch^exifindgd^ itself. We

do not wish to enter into any discussion of the exact character of the purgation of Pope Leo III. in the year 800, but at least it is clear that Charles the Great had been gravely concerned with regard to the chaises brought against the Pope. Leo III. was very careful, in purging himself by oath of the crimes laid to his charge, to make it quite clear that he did this of his own free will, and not as one amenable to the judgment of any man, and to guard against his action being taken as a precedent for his successors; but his own statement makes it clear that Charles had come to Eome, in part at least, to inquire into the matter.^ And in spite of


1


^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. iL No. 255 : '* 1. Ut episcopi nuUum inquietudinem sive exprobationem presbyteris aut aperte ingerendo aut alia qualibet occasione machinando pro eo, quod se ad nos hac vice reclamare venerunt, inferant; quia longa oppressio hujusmodi itineris eos fecit subire laborem. . . .

'* 8. Ut episcopi sub occasione, quasi auctoritatem habeant canonum, his constitutis ezcellentisd nostrse nequa- quam resultent aut neglegant, sed potius canoaes, ut intelligendi sunt, intelligere et in cunctis obaervare procurent; quia si aliter fecerint, omnimodis et qualiter canones fidelium decimis agendum statuant et qualiter intellegi ac obserrari cum mansuetu- dinis nostrse decreto debeant, synodali


dijudicatione et nostra regia auctor- itate docebuntur."

'^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. iL No. 259, Cap. Missorum Suessionense : "1. Ut missi nostri per civitates et singula monasteria, tam canonicorum quam monachoinim sive sanctimonial- ium, una cum episcopo parochise uniuscujusque, in qua consistunt, cum consilio et consensu ipsius, qui mon- asterium retinet vitam ibi degentium et conversationem inquirant, et ubi necesse est corrigant," &c.

» M. G. H. Ep., V. Ep. Select. Pont. Rom., 6. 800 A.D. Dec. 23.

  • ' Sacramentum quod Leo Papa jur-

avit. 'Auditum, fratres karissimi, et divulgatum est per multa loca, qualiter homines mali adversus me insurrexer- unt, et debilitare voluerunt, et miser-






264 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part. IV.


^ the care Leo III. had taken to guard against his action becoming a precedent, we cannot help feeling that Pope Leo IV. was following in Leo IIL's steps, and was even > / going somewhat further, when, in his letter to the Emperor f nLewis IL of about 853, he expressed his willingness that the t/ emperor and his " missi " should inquire into the charges which had been made against him, and his readiness to amend everjrthing according to their judgment.^

We think that all this will serve to show sufficiently clearly*^ , ^hat the civil ruler in the ninth century was thought of, and ^as recognised in fact, as having some real responsibility for irthe good order and conduct of the Church. He was not only , > the protector of the Church against external enemies, but was, at least in some measure, responsible to guard it against corrup- • tion and decay. How exactly this responsibility was to be carried out into practice was a very uncertain matter, and one upon which, when put to the test of practical action, men in the ninth century would probably have differed greatly ; but there


unt super me gravia crimina. Propter quam causam audiendam iste clemen- tissimus ac serenissimus dominus rex CaroluB una cum sacerdotibus et optimatibus Buis istam pervenit ad urbem. Quam ob rem ego Leo pontifex sanctse Romanae ecclesiad, a nemine judicatus neque coactus, sed spontanea mea voluntate purifico et purgo me in conspectu vestro coram Deo et angelis suis, qui conscientiam meam novit, et beato Petro principe apostolorum in cujus basilica con- sistimuB : quia istas criminosas et Bceleratas res, quas illi mihi obiciunt, nee perpetravi nee perpetrare jussi; testis mihi est Deus, in cujus judicium venturi sumus et in cujus conspectu consistimus. Et hoc propter suspi- tiones tollendas mea spontanea volun- tate facio ; non quasi in canonibus inventum sit, aut quasi ego banc consuetudinem aut decretum in sancta ecclesia successoribus meis necnon et fratribus et coepiscopis nostris imponam.' "


1 M. G. H. Ep., V. Ep. Select. Leonis IV., 40, c. 853: "Nos si aliquid incompetenter egimus, et in subditis justse legis tramitem non conservavimus, vestro ac vestrorum missorum cuncta volumus emendare judicio quoniam si nos qui aUena debemus corrigere, pejora commit- timus, certe non veritatis discipuli, sed quod dolentes dicimus, erimus pre caeteris erroris magistrL Inde mag- nitudinis vestrse magnopere clemenciam imploramus, ut tales ad hsdc qu» dizi- mus perquirenda missos in his partibus dirigatis, qui Deum per omnia timeant, et cuncta quemadmodum si vestra prsesens imperialis gloria fuisset, ex- amussim diligenter exquirant, et non tantum hsec quae superius diximus exagitent, sed sive minora sive eliam majora illis sint de nobis indicata negotia, ita eorum cuncta legitime terminentur examine, quatenus in posterum nichil sit, quod ex eia in- discussum vel indiffinitum remaneat."






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OP CHURCH AND STATE. 265

seems no doubt that this conception of the responsibility of the king was held very commonly, if not universally.

It is partly at least from this standpoint that we may most usefully consider the relation of the civil ruler of the time to the synodical and legislative organisation of the Church. We do not think that any one doubted the independent legislative and ad- ministrative authority of the synods of the Church, but yet we ^ . find that the synods are constantly spoken of as being called

^ together by the emperor or king as well as by the ecclesiastical chiefs, and that the decrees, administrative or legislative, of the synods, are issued with the co-operation of the royal power.

We may take as our first example of this condition of things the Capitulare_gf_KarlmAnn^ o^ 742. Here we find Karlmann, with the counsel"of the bishops, presbyters, and chief men of the kingdom, decreeing that a council and synod should be held to advise him how religion and the law of \y Gk>d might be restored, and then, with the bishops and great men, ordering that synods should be held every year, at which the king should be present, and by which the canons and laws of the Church should be restored.^ We find parallels in Charles thej^eat's Capitulary of -76?,^ in the "Capitulare Haristal-

iMii5e""oR^3 and in the '^Admonitio Generalis" of 789.* We are specially told that Charles the Great was present at the Synod of Frankfort_ia_794, and he is said to have pre-

^ M. O. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. No. venire posait et per falsos sacerdotes

10 : In nomine Domini nostri Jesu deceptus non pereat.

Christi. Ego Earlmannus, dux et prin- "1. Et per consilium sacerdotum et

ceps Francorum, anno ab incamatione optimatum meorum ordinavimus per

Christi septingentesimo quadragesimo civitates episcopos, et constituimus

secundo, xi Kalendas Maias, cum con- super eos archiepiscopum Bonifatium

cilio servorum Dei et optimatum qui est missus sancti Petri. Statuimus

meorum episcopos qui in regno meo per annos singulos synodum congre-

sunt cum presbyteris et concilium gare, ut nobis prsesentibus canonum

et synodum pro timore Chnsti con- decreta et secclesiae jura restaurentur

gregavi, id est Bonifatium archi- et relegio Christiana emendetur."

episcopum et Burghardum . . . cum ^ jf^ q^ h^ Leg^^ sect. ii. vol. i. presbiteris eorum, ut mihi consilium

dedissent, quamodo lex Dei et ' M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i.


aeoclesiastica religio recuperetur, quad

in diebus prseteritorum principum ^ M. O. H. Leg., sect. iL vol. L

dissipata corruit, et qualiter populus

Christianus ad salutem animad per-


SM. G.


H.


Leg.,


No. 19.




» M. G.


H.


Leg.,


No. 20.




  • M. G.


H.


Leg.,


No. 22.








266 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH OENTUEY. [part iv.


eided.^ The synod, we are told, was called together by the apostolic authority and by that of Charles the Great^ Per- haps the most marked recognition of the imperial share in such ecclesiastical business is to be found in the Epilogue to the decrees of the X/OunciLof^Arle s of 813 . In this we find the decrees presented to the emperor, and he is asked to add anything which may have been omitted, to correct anything that may be wrong, and to aid in carrying into effect what- ever may have been rightly decreed.*

It may perhaps be urged that these examples are all taken from the time of Charles the Great himself, and that his rela- tion to the Church was wholly exceptional ; but we can find some parallels at least later in the century. In 818-19 Lewis the Pious issued a number of capitula on ecclesiSsticafand secular matters, and it is worthy of note that the form in which this is done is very much the same as that in the earlier cases. 'Lewis calls together his bishops, abbots, and great men, and ^ with their advice issues the Capitula which are to be observed ' by ecclesiastics and laymen alike.* The proceedings of the

  • Synodica concUii Franconofurt. 187, "Proemium Generale ad Ci^^).

Mansi Councils, vol. ziiL p. 884 : ** Prse- cipiente et prsesidente piisimo et glori- osiBsimo donmo nostro Carolo rege."

^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect iL vol. i. No. 28, Syiiodus Franconofurtensis :

    • Conjungentibu8, Deo favente, apos-

tolica auctoritate atque piissimi domini nostri Earoli regni anno xxvi. princi- patus sui, cunctis regni Franoorum sen Italise, Aquitanise, Provintise, episcopis ac saoerdotibuB synodali concilio, inter quos ipse mitissimus eancto interf uit conventuL"

' Mansi, Councils, vol. xiv. p. 62 : '* Hadc igitur . . . quam brevissime aunotavimus, et domino imperatori praesentanda decrevimus, poscentes ejus clementiam, ut si quid hie minus est, ejus prudentia suppleatur : ni quid secus quam se ratio habet, ejus judicio emen- detur, si quid rationabiliter taxatum est, ejus adjutorio divina opitulante dementia perfidatur."

  • M. G. H. Leg., sect, ii. vol. i. No.


187, Proemium Generale ad Tam. EccL quam Mundana " : " Quinto anno imperii nostri, aooersitis nonnuUis episcopis, abbatibus, canonids et monachis et fidelibus optimatibus nostris, studuimus eorum consultu sagacissima investigare inquisitione, qualiter unicuique ordini, canonicorum videlicet, monachorum et laioorum juzta quod ratio dictabat et facultas suppetebat, Deo opem ferente consul- eremus. . . . Sed qualiter de his divina co-operante gratia consultu fiddium pro viribus et temporis brevitate, licet non quantum debuimus et voluimus sed quantum a Deo posse acoepimus, egerimus et quid unicuique ordini conununi voto communique consensu consulere studuerimus, ita ut quid can- onicis proprie de his, quidve monachis obeervandis, quid etiam in legibus mun* danis addenda, quid quoque in capit- ulis inserenda forent, adnotaverimus et singulis singula obeervanda contra- deremus," &c.






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OP CHURCH AND STATE. 267

Synod of Pcmthion in 876 seem to show that the principte that synods should be summoned by the king or emperor, "S and that he might preside at them, was still accepted. The^ Emperor Charles the Bald is said to have presided at thie^ synod, and it is spoken of as having been called together by the Pope and the Emperor.^

The history of the century seems to illustrate very exactly the theory as we have seen it in §gdnliaa_^d^SDaa^gdiis or CathnUHS^ The king is responsible for the good order of the Church, and at least has his share in the calling together of the synods of the Church and the promulgation of their decrees.

There is yet one further point of Church order in which the v influence of the secular power is very great — that is, in the j appo^ntme$Lt..j2lj^ We do not wish to enter upon'

a discussion of the many and intricate questions connected with this subject, but we must deal with it so far as is necessary to bring out the fact that here again the theory of a separation of the two powers was found impossible of literal application to the actual circumstances of the time. The ^ emperor or king did as a matter of fact exercise a most power- ful influence over all appointments of the greater ecclesiastics, i and the propriety of this is not denied by any writer of the j ninth century.

The bishops, in their address to Lewis the Pious of 829, quite frankly recognise this, and exhort him to see that the greatest care is exercised in appointing pastors and rulers in the Church of God.^ Hincmar of Rheims is quite as frank in recognising the authority of the secular ruler in the appoint- - ment of bishops. In his treatise, "De Institutione^Carolo-

^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. u. vol. ii. est in loco qui vocatur Pontigonis,"

No. 279, Synodus Pontigonensis : &c

'*£. Ideoque, quia imperialem excel- ^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect, ii vol. ii.

lentiam vestram synodo pneesse, et No. 196, Episcoporum ad Hlud. Imp.

vicarioB sedis apostoUcse pnesto nobis Belatio: "57. Iterum monendo mag-

adesse gaudemus, ko, O. Sancta syn- nitudini vestrse suppliciter suggerimus,

odus, qu» in nomine Domini voca- ut deincepe in bonis pastoribus, rec-

tione domini Johannis ter beatissimi, toribusque in ecdesiis Dei constituendis

ac universalis papse et jussione domini magnum studium atque soUertissimam

Karoli perpetui augusti congregata adhibeatis curam.






268 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY, [part IV.

manni/' he very clearly reckons the consent of the prince, and the election of the clergy and people, as the proper ele- ments in an appointment to ecclesiastical rule;^ and in a letter to Lewis III., occasioned by some dispute about the appointment of a Bishop of Beauvais, he again admits very frankly that the consent of the prince is a necessary part of the appointment to such an o£Bce. This is the more noticeable, as the general purpose of the letter is to condemn and correct what Hincmar clearly thought was an exaggerated conception of the royal authority with regard to ecclesiastical appoint- ments. We must indeed notice how emphatically Hincmar condemns the notion that the appointment of a bishop was a matter in the arbitrary power of the prince, attributing this to the suggestion of the devil himself, and that he wholly denies that the prince can order the election of whomsoever he pleases. A bishop, Hincmar seems to mean, should be elected by the other bishops of the province, with the consent of the people and clergy of the diocese, and when the prince has given his consent he is to be taken to the metropolitan for consecra- tion.2 We do not enter into any discussion of Hincmar's


^ Hincmar of Rheims, De Institutione Carolomanni, 5 : ** Qualiter autem con- sensu principis terns, qui res eoclesi- asticas divino judicio ad tuendas et defensandas suscepit, electione oleri ac plebis quisque ad ecclesiasticum regi- men absque uUa venalitate provehi debeat, et Dominus in Evangelio, et sacri canones aperte demonstrant dicente Domino: *Qui non intrat per ostium in ovile ovium, sed ascendit aliunde, iUe fur est et latro.'^'

^ Hincmar of Rheims, Ep. ziz. : c. L "* Ut sicut sacrse leges et regulae preecipiunt, archiepiscopis et episcopis collimitanearum dioeceseon electionem conoedere dignemini, ut undecunque, secundum f ormam regularem electionis, episcopi talen eligant, qui et sanctee Eccleeise utilis, et regno proficuus, et vobis fidelis ac devotus co-operator ez- istat : et consentientibus dero et plebe eum vobis adducant, ut secundum


ministerium vestrum res et facul- tates Ecclesise, quas ad defendendum et tuendum vobis Dominus oommen- davit, suse dispositioni oommittatis, et cum consensu ac letteris vestris eum ad metropolitanum episcopum ac co- episcopos ipsius dioceseos qui eum ordinare debent, transmittaUs, et sic sine scandali macula ad sanctum sacer- dotium provehatur.' . . .

c iii. Nam si quod a quibusdam dicitur, ut audivi, quando petitam apud Tos electionem conoeditis, ilium debent episcopi, et derus, ac plebe eligere, quem vos vultis, et quem jubetis (quse non est divinse legis electio, sed humanse potestatis eztorsio), si ita est, ut did a quibusdam audivi, ille malignus spiritus, qui per serpen- tem primes parentes nostroe in para- diso decepit et inde illos ejedt, per tales adulatores in auree vestras hsec sibilat; quia hoc in Scriptura tam






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OP CHURCH AND STATE. 269


position with regard to the part of the metropolitan and the other bishops of the province in the election of a bishop : it is enough for us to observe that Hincmar clearly admits the place of the secular ruler, but as clearly also is anxious that this should be defined and limited.

A position very similar to that of Hincmar is represented by the little treatise " De ElectionibusJ RniftCinyewHa," written by Florus^^iacfinus, a writer of the ninth century. Here also ^ it is candidly admitted that in certain kingdoms the custom prevailed that a bishop should be consecrated after the prince had been consulted, and Florus admits that this custom tends to peace and tranquillity, but he emphatically denies that it is necessary to a proper consecration.^ Florus maintains that


veteris quam Novi Testamenti non continetur, neque in catholiconim dictis, vel satcris canonibus, nee etiam in legibus a Christianis imperatoribus et regibus promulgatis hoc scriptum vel decretum invenitur, sed talia dicta infemus evomuit. Christus enim per apostolum loquens, talem jubet eligere : 'qui potena sit exhortari in doctrina sacra et iis qui contradicunt revincere.' Et si quis contra hoc loquitur, iniquita- ^ tern contra Dominum loquitur et inter blasphemes a Sancto Spiritu com- putatur. Sic enim atavus vester Carolus et abavus Ludovicus impera- tores intellexerunt, et ideo in primo libro capitulorum suorum promulgav- erunt scribentes. * Sacrorum,' inqui- unt, 'canonum non ignari, ut in Dei nomine sancta Ecclesia suo liberius potiatur honore, assensum ordini eccles- iastico prsebemus, ut scilicet episcopi per electionem cleri et populi secundum statuta canonum, de propria dioecesi, remota personarum et munerum ac- ceptione ob vitse meritum et sapientise donum eligantur, ut exemplo et verbo sibi subjectis usquequaque prodesse valeant.' . . . Et sacri canones dicunt, 'Primum enim iUi (quin clerici uniuscujusque Ecdesiae) reprobandi sunt, ut aliqui de alienis Ecclesiis merito prseferantur.' Et


item, * Ut episcopi, judicio metropolit- anorum et eorum episcoporum qui circumcirca sunt, provehantur ad ecclesiasticam potestatem ; hi, videlicet qui plurimo tempore probantur tam verbo fidei quam rectse conversationis exemplo.' Attendendum est igitur qualiter hoc imperiale capitulum sacris regulis et antiquorum imperatorum legibus congruat, ostendens quoniam, sicut et leges et regulad dicunt, in electione episcopi assensio regis sit, non electio, in episcoporum vero exsecu- tione sit electio, sicut et ordinatio."

^ Florus Diaconus, De Electionibus Episcoporum iv. : " Quod vero in qui- busdam regnis postea consuetude ob- tinuit, ut consultu principis ordinatio fieret episcopalis, valet utique ad cum- ulum fratemitatis, propter pacem et concordiam mundanse potestatis ; non tamen ad complendam veritatem vel auctoritatem sacrse ordinationis, quae nequaquam regio potentatu, sed solo Dei nutu, et Ecclesiae fidelium con- sensu, cuique conferri potest. . . . Unde graviter quilibet princeps delin- quit, si hoc suo beneficio largiri posse existimat, quod sola divina gratia dis- pensat ; cum ministerium suae potes- tatis in hujusmodi negotium peragendo adjungere debeat, non prseferre. . . .

'^viL Quae omnia non ideo dicimus.






270 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part nr.

the true requirements for a proper appointment are the election of the clergj and the whole people of the diocese, and con- secration by the lawful number of bishops ;^ and he urges that for nearly four hundred years from the time of the apostles no consent was asked from the secular power, and that even after the emperor was Christian this liberty for the most part continued.'

The position of Hincmar and Florus is not quite identical.

' Hincmar looks upon the consent of the prince as normally

necessary for the appointment of a bishop; Florus considers

this as a legitimate custom of some kingdoms, but not as being

C universal custom, and still less does he admit it to be of niversal obligation. But they agree in admitting that, as a matter of fact, the secular ruler has a considerable power with regard to ecclesiastical appointments, while they are both con- cerned to correct any exaggerated conception of this.


quaai poteetatem principum in aliquo minuendam putemus, vel contra religi- 08um morem regni aliquid sentiendum persuadeamus ; Bed ut darissime de- monstretur, in re hujusmodi divinam gratiam sufficere, humanam Tero poten- tiam nisi illi consonet, nihil valere. Quapropter in sacris canonibus Patrum, ubi plurimse causae commemorantur sine quibus epiaoopalis ordinatio irrita habenda est, de hac re nihil inTcnitur insertum."

^ Id., L: "Manifeetum est om- nibus qui in Eoclesia Dei sacerdotale offidum administrant, quse sunt ilia quse in ordinatione episcopali, et saonnrum canonorum auctoritas, et consuetudo ecdesiastica, juxta dis* positionem divinse legis et tradilaonem apostolicam jubeat obeervari. Videli- oet ut pastore defuncto, et sede vacante, unus de dero Ecdesiso, quern communis et coucots ejusdem deri et totius plebis consensus elegerit, et publico decreto oelebriter ac solem- niter designaverit, legitimo episoo- porum numero consecratus, locum deoedentis antistitis rite Taleat ob-


tinere ; nee dubitetur diyino judicio eb dispoeitione firmatum, quod ab Ecclesia Dei tarn sancto ordine et legitima obaervatione fuerit cde- bratum."

  • Id., iiL : *' Juxta hsec Terba beati

Cypriani, ordinatoe fuisse c<Hi8tat, et legitime pnefuisse universo populo deinceps omnes Ecdesiarum Dd anti* stites, absque uUo consultu mundanse potestatis, a temporibus apostolorum, et postea per annos fere quadrin- gentos. Ex quo autem Chrbtiani prindpee esse coeperunt, eamdem episcoporum ordinaticmibus eoded- asticam libertatem ex parte maxima permansisse, manifesta rajtio declarat. Neque enim fieri potuit, cum unus Imperator orbis terrsB monarchiam obtineret, ut ex omnibus latiasimis mundi partibus, Asise viddioet, Europeo et A£ric», omnes qui (nrdinandi orant Episoopi ad ejus oognitionem de- duoerentur. Sed fuit semper integra et rata ordinaUo, qnam sancta E ocl e sia juxta traditionem apoetd- icam et rdigiosse obserrationis formam odebravit."






GHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 271


It is perhaps necessary to say a word about the theory f - of the relation^ofjhfijeimperor to the papal elections. We may begin by observing that Floras Diaconus "assumes that the consent of the civil power is never asked for in this case.^ Whether such a statement can be taken as accurately rep- resenting the relations of the emperor to the papal elections in the ninth century is doubtful. The" Paatttm- Hlndosdci Ri pumJaschf^li fontifice" of 817 does, indeed, agree with this m its careful provision that no one is to interfere with, the election of a Pope, but that it is to be left in the hands" of the Eomans, and that they are freely to elect him whom the divine inspiration and the intercession of St Peter suggest.' Only after the consecration is an ambassador to be sent to Lewis or his~ successor to arrange for the continuance of friendship and peace between the Emperor and the Pope.^ The terms of Lothair's *1 GpjiStitutiQ^BomaBat" -QlJ32i are so far in agreement with this. It reiterates the provision of theZ^ Pactum, that no one is to take part in the election of a / Pope except the Eomans themselves.^ There is in existence,


^ Id. vi. : " Sed et in Romana Ecclesia usque in prsesentem diem cemimus abe- que interrogatione Prinoipia solo dis- positionis judicio et fidelium suffragio, legitime pontifices consecrari ; qui etiam omnium regionum et civitatum qu» illi Bubjectse sunt, juxta antiquum morem, eadem libertate ordinant atque con- stituunt sacerdotes ; nee adeo quis- quam absurdus est, ut putet min- orem illic sanctificationis divinam esse gratiam, eo quod nulla mundanae potestatis comitetur auctoritas."

» M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i. No. 172 : <<£t quando divina vocatione hujus sacratissimse sedis pontifex de hoc mundo migraverit, nullus ex regno nostro, aut Francus aut Longobardus aut de qualibet gente homo sub nostra potestate constitutus, licentiam habeat contra Romanes, aut publico aut private veniendi vel electionem faciendi ; nul- lusque in civitatibus vel territoriis ad ecclesise beati Petri apostoli potestatem pertinentibus aliquod malum propter


hoc facere presumat. Sed liceat Romanis cum omni veneratione et sine qualibet perturbatione honorifi- cam suo pontifici exibere sepulturam, et eum quern divina inspiratione et beati Petri intercessione omnes Romani uno consilio atque conoordia sine aliqua promissione ad pontificatus ordinem ele- gerint sine qualibet ambiguitate vel contradictione more canonico con- secrari. Et dum consecratus fuerit, legati ad nos vel ad successores nostros reges Francorum dirigantur, qui inter nos et illos amicitiam et caritatem ac pacem socient, sicut temporibus pie recordationis domni Karoli attavi nostri, seu donmi Pipini avi nostri vel etiam donmi Earoli imperatoris genitoris nostri consuetude erat faciendi."

« M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL vol. L No. 161 : " 3. Volumus ut in electione pontifids nullus prsesumat venire, neque liber neque servus, qui aliquod impedimentum faciat illis solummodo






272 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iy.

however, a form of oath, supposed to be of this time, required of all those who were to take part in the papal election : this not only makes the electors swear allegiance and fidelity to the emperor, but also includes a provision that he who is elected is not to be consecrated until he has taken such an oath in the presence of the " missus " of the emperor as that taken by Pope Eugenius. From a passage in "^i^nharfl'^ Anyala for 827, it would appear that on the death of Valentinus, his successor, Gr^ory IV., was elected, but not consecrated until the ambassador of the emperor had come and examined into the character of the election.^ It must, however, be noticed that these documents, and especially the Pactum," while they are probably genuine in substance, are probably not all authentic in detail

Our examination of these matters will, we think, have served to bring out suflSciently clearly the fact that, whatever might be the theory of the division of functions between the ^ secular and the spiritual powers, (^e secular _pqggr did in practice certainly tend to exercise a very consi derable authon ty even io^ the strictly sjjiritual sphere. We may say that the foundation of the whole situation, as far as theory is concerned, lies in this, that it is the duty of the civil ruler to care for the


Romanis, quibus antiquitus fuit oon- suetudo conoessa per constitutionem sanctorum patrum eligendi pontificem. Quod si quia coutra banc jussionem nostram facere prsesumpserit, exilio tradatur."

^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. H. voL L No. 161. Form of oath to the emperor to be taken by electors to the Papacy, which seems to belong to the time of Pope Eugenius : " Promitto ^o iUe per Deum omnipotentem et per ista sacra quattuor evangelia et per banc cruoem domini nostri Jesu Christi et per corpus beatissimi Petri principis apostolorum, quod ab hac die in futurum fideUs ero dominis nostris imperatoribus Hludo- wico et Hlothario diebus vitse mese, juxta yires et inteUectum meum, sine fraude atque malo ingenio, salva fide


quam repromisi domino apostolico ; et quod non cons^itiam ut aliter in hac sede Romana fiat electio pontificis nisi canonice et juste, secundum vires et inteUectum meum ; et iUe qui electus fuerit me consentiente consecratus pontifez non fiat, priusquam tale sacramentum f aciat in prsesentia missi domini imperatoris et populi, cum juramento, quale dominus Eugenius papa, sponte pro conserratione omnium &ctum habet per scriptum."

The editor cites, to illustrate this, from Einhard's Annals for 827 : "2. . . . quo defuncto (».«., Pope Valen- tinus) Qregorius (IV.) electus, sed non prius ordinatus est quam legatus im- peratoris Romam venit et electionem populi qualis esset examinavit."






CHAP. XXI.3 AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 273

wellbeing of the Church, and to interfere when he sees that ^ the Church is, for any reason, being badly administered or falling into corruption. We can see how this conception naturally gives rise to the theory that it is the king's duty to see to the regular meeting of synods, and thus gives him necessarily a share in the legislative, as well as the adminis- id trative, control of the Church. It is easy also to see how this conception of the responsibility lying upon the king to see that justice and righteousness prevailed in the Church as well as elsewhere, might lead to a considerable ambiguity in his relation to the discipline of the Church. The relations of the empire to the Papacy in the causes of Leo III. and Leo lY. are but the final examples of a tendency to look to the civil power to set things right in the Church, when there was no one else who could act. And, finally, the tendency to subject ecclesiastical appointments to some control on the ptlrt of the civil ruler, while it has many other political and social rela- tions, may also be regarded in part at least as illustrating the same conception, that the secular power has its own responsi- bility for the good order of the Church, and has therefore necessarily something to say with regard to the persons to whom the government of the Church is to be intrusted.

We have said enough, we think, to make it clear that in the ninth century the theory of a strict duality of authority in society does not prevent the civil power from acting very frequently in the sphere of the ecclesiastical, and that this intervention is not only tolerated in practice, but is to a considerable extent justified in theory.

We must now consider the other side of the subject, the/^ extent to which the ecclesiastical authority intervened in civil affairs, and the character and conditions of this interference. We may begin by observing that if the king or emperor is by some writers styled the Vicar of Grod, the same title, is also claimed for the bishops.^ Hrab^nua^^aurus calls the ^ ' priests or bishops the vicars of the prince of shepherds in

^ M. O. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. iL 83 : *' Nob autem Dei judicio sui ab illo No. 298, Concilium Meldeose Parisiense, vicarii constituti," &c

VOL. I. S






274 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

the Church of God, and warns them to be determined i^ainst the proud and contumacious, to be careful that no earthly power terrifies them in their rule of souls, and no worldly blandishments soften their rigour.^

What is more important than this title of Vicar of God, it is certain that the people of the ninth century were perfectly clear that the ecclesiastic is bound to correct and reprove persons of every rank and degree, — to use against them, if necessary, the severest penalties of the Church. A very strong phrase is used by a synod held in 859, which expresses this very directly and forcibly: the bishops are exhorted to be united in their ministry and holy authority, and with mutual counsel and help to rule over and correct kings and the great ones of the earth, and the whole people committed to them in - the Lord.* The same view is very strongly expressed by many writers. A^guiB^xhorts the priest to declare the Word of Gk)d, and the prince to obey.^ Jonas of .Orleans quotes that passage from the history of Bufinus, discussed in an earlier chapter, r in which Constantino is represented as saying to the bishops that God has made them the judges of all, and that they cannot be judged by any.* The same passage is quoted by the bishops in that address to Lewis the Pious which we have already frequently cited.^ There is, therefore, nothing that \we should regard as new, when we find the pseudo-Isidorian ^ Decretals using very strong language about the subjection of

^ M. G. H. Ep., v., Epistolarum tatem unitiBintetmutuoconsilioatque

Fuldensium Fragmenta, 20, 0. iv. : auzilio regee regnorumque primores,

" RabanuB inquit : Quomodo in Christi atque populum sibi commissum in

saoerdotibuB discreta debet esse pietas Domino regant et corrigant."

erga condigne poenitentes, ita debet et ' M. Q. H. Ep., iv., Alcuin, Ep.

fortiB esse constantia contra superbos 18: "Illorum est, id est^ sacerdotum,

atque contumaces. Nee debet ulla verba Dei non tacere. Vestrum est,

terrena potestas terrere rectorem o principes, humiliter oboedire, dili-

animarum nee mollire secularibus genter implere." Cf.-Ep. 108: '*Kt

blandimentifl ngorem Christi pontifi- sis obediens servis .Dei, -qui te de

cum, qui vicarii principis pastorum in mandatis ejus ammoneant."

ecclesia Dei esse videntur. ... In * Jonas of Orleans, *'De- Instit.,

Epistola ad Humbertum episcopum." Laic," u. 20. See p. '4 77.

^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. iL voL ii. ° M. G. H. Leg., sect. iL voL iL

Ko. 299, Synodus apud Saponarias No. 196, Episoop. ad Hlud. Imp.

habita,2: "EpiM^pinamque secundum Relatio, 22. illorum ministerium ac saoram auctori-






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIBS OF CHURCH AND STATE. 275

princes to bishops. In his 39th Decretal letter Clement is ? represented as saying that all princes of the earth are to obey J * the bishops, to submit to them and help them, and that those | who oppose them, unless they repent, are to be put out of the Church.^

The political theory of the ninth century, then, very clearly recognises that there is an authority in the Church which ex- ) ^ tends over all persons, even the most exalted in society. It will be useful to consider more closely the relation of the civil order and the civil rulers to the law and discipline of the Church. We have already examined the treatment in Hincmar's work, * DeOrdine Palatii,' of the relation of the king to the Iftw pf_the State; we have seen that Hi ncmar expresses the general view of the ninth cen^tury .when l^maintaina. that these laws are binding upon the king.* Hincmar -gees on to i^^ say that much more. must the Jdng .Qbey_ tjm.. diyijoto. JajLai* There is a system of divine law in the Church to which all ' men owe their obedience. We do not wish to enter into so complicated a subject as that of the gradual formation of the body of Church law : to do so would take us very far away from our proper topic. It will here suflSce if we point out that by the ninth century there were in existence and cir- culation in Western Europe collections _of_Church regulations on doctrine and discipline, and these regulations were looked upon as havings in some sense a divine authority. There are some words in Hincmar's treatise *Pro Ecclesise Libertatum

gf^ione ' which may very well benbafeen as representative of theaRitude of the ninth century towards these laws. This is the treatise written by Hincmar in the early stages of the quarrel between Charles the Bald and Hincmar's nephew, Hincmar, Bishop of Laon. Hincmar at first sided wholly with

^ Pseudo - Isidore, ClemeDt, Dec. liminibus ecdesiae alienos eese prse-

xzxix. : " Omnes principes terrse et cipiebat."

•cunctos homines eis obeedire et capita ' See p. 233.

sua Bubmittere eorumque adjutores ' M. Q. H. Leg., sect. iL voL ii.

ezistere prsecipiebat. . . . Omnes ergo Hincmar of Rheims, De Ordine Pal*

qui eis contradicent, ita damnatos atii, 9 : " Multo minus autem regi, vel

et infames usque ad satisfactionem cuilibet inquocunqueordine contra leges

xnonstrabat, et nisi converterentur a divinas licet agere per contemptum. "






276 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

his nephew, and wrote this treatise to protest against the royal action, which at first he looked upon as an outrageous inter- ference with ecclesiastical prerogative. A vassal of the Bishop of Laon had complained to Charles of his treatment by the bishop, and Charles had summoned the bishop to appear and to answer before his courts. When he did not appear, Charles put his property under the ban. Hincmar of Rheims protests against such action as being wholly improper and even scandal- ous, and quite contrary to the canons and the laws. He quotes St Leo as saying that the canons were enacted by the Spirit of God, and confirmed by the reverence of the whole world, and were established by men who now reign with God in heaven and still work miracles on the earth.^

We think that these words are highly characteristic of the general attitude of men in the ninth century towards Church

law. No one, we think, doubted that in some sense all men of

all ranks were bound to obey it. Earlier in the century Ago- bajaLofJjyona had used phrases jimiter to^ those otJixoiimBX^ Agobard is writing of the proceedings of the bishops at Attigny and Compi^gne, and represents himself as making a speech in which he discussed the nature and authority of the canons of the Church. In former times, he said, the holy bishops had ^ come together and decreed that the canons must be preserved inviolate, inasmuch as they had been confirmed by the Spirit of God, the consent of the whole world, the obedience of princes, the agreement of Scripture, and that from that time it had been an accepted doctrine that any action against the canons was an action against God Himself, and against His universal Church, and that they could not be violated without danger to religion.^ A little earlier in date still we find a letter

^ Hincmar of Rheims, Pro EccL Lib. adhuc nobiscum in constitutionibus

Defen., i: '^Etquisoculumsimplicem, yivant' : sed et legibus, quibua una

id eat, rectam intentionem, quam in cum eisdem sacris canonibus moder-

vobis nescit, putabit : ubi factum atur Eoclesia, constat adversum ? " Domino contrarium, et inimicum sacris ' M. Q. H. Ep., v. ; Agobard, Ep., v.

canonibus, sicut beatus Leo scribit, c 4 : '* CJonvenerunt episcopi, yiri sancti,

' Spiritu Dei ccmditis et totius mundi quibus tunc babundabat eoclesia, statu-

reverentia consecratis, quorum con- erunt inlibatos oonservari debere sacroe

ditores in ccelo cum Deo regnantes,* canones, qui firmati sunt spiritu Dei,

et in terns miraculis coruscantes, consensu totius mundi, oboedientia






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 277


/


by 8ipg«rn,](^ Bift>^o p of Aquileia, mutilated unfortunately and only partly comprehensible, in which we have a very emphatic exhortation to Charles the Great on the duty of obeying the canons. In spite of the fragmentary state in which it has come to us, we can make out fairly clearly the emphatic terms in which Charles is admonished to observe and enforce obedience to the canons.^

There is, th en, a body of law in the Church which all men must obey aod ta^whichi all other laws^uafc. conform them- selves. .Hincmar considers the question of a possible collision between the national system of law and the divine law, and is perfectly clear that in such a case the human laws must be ^, .altered and made conformable to the divine;^ and in another treatise written by Hincmar we have an exposition of the su periority of the divine law, and men are reminded that they may now justify themselves in their actions by appealing to human laws and customs, but in the day of judgment they will have to answer, not to the Roman, or Salic, or Gundobadian laws, but to the divine and apostolic laws. Hincmar urges that in a Christian kingdom even the public laws should be in accordance with the principles of Christianity.*


principum, consonantia Bcripturarum. Ex quo tempore acoeptum et receptum est non aliud esse agere cuiquam ad- versus canones quam adversus Deum, et adversus ejus imiversalem ecclesiam, neque sensum est umquam a quibus- que fidelibus, ut talia statuta absque periculo religionis violarentur."

^ M. G. H. Ep., iv. ; Ep. var. Carolo Magno Regnante, 8 : " Vestra est . . . [sac]rorum canonum inviolabiles sane- tiones salubriter promulgatas nuUo quo- libet usurpationis ti[tulo] . . . mutilare, diceute scriptura: Terminos patnim tuorum ne transgredieris presertim cum sere . . . vestrse mansuetudo decrevit omnium ecclesiarum prsesules divinis legibus subjaoere et pri . . • secum . . . [irrep]rehensibilia docu- menta sancto dilucidante Spiritu prse- libata modis omnibus custodire."

' M. G. H. Leg., sect, ii vol. ii.


De Ordine Palatii, 21 : * * Si quid vero tale esset, quod leges mundanse hoc in suis diffinitionibus statutum non haberent aut secundum gentilium con- suetudinem crudelius sancitum esset, quam Christianitatis rectitude vel sancta auctoritas merito non con- sentiret, hoc ad regis moderationem perduceretur, ut ipse cum his, qui utramque legem nossent et Dei magis quam humanarum legum statuta metu- erent, ita deoemeret, ita statueret, ut, ubi utrumque servari posset, utnimque servaretur, sin autem, lex sseculi merito comprimeretur, justitia Dei conservar- etur."

' Hincmar of Rheims, De Raptu Viduarum, etc, c. xiL: Defendant se quantum volunt qui hujusmodi sunt, give per leges, si ullse sunt, mundanas, sive per consuetudines humanas, tamen si Christiani sunt, sciant se in die






278 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

There is again, therefore, nothing new in the strong phrases

m which the Pseudo-Isidorian Decretals express the prin-

^ ^^ple that no emperor or other potentate may do anything

^y contrary to the divine commands : if the judges, at the king's

^ desire, should command anything unjust or contrary to the

evangelical, or prophetic, or apostolic doctrines, such commands

have no authority.^

The secular ruler, then, must, like other persons, obey the divine law, and if he refuses to do this he is subject to the discipline of the Church. It is indeed clear that there were some in the ninth century who doubted or denied that the authority of the Church extended so far as to the excom- munication of the king or emperor. From that section of Hincmar's treatise on the divorce of Lothair and Tetburga, to which we have so often referred, it is clear that there were some who denied that the king was liable to the judgment of the bishops of his own dominions, or to that of any other bishops. Some wise men, says Hincmar, maintained that the king is subject to no laws or judgments but those of God . alone, who made him king ; and that, as he should . not be excommunicated by his own bishops, whatever he may do, so he cannot be judged by other bishops. Hincmar, indeed, makes short work of this contention, describing it concisely as blasphemous and full of the spirit of the devil, and then shows by a series of examples, drawn from the Old Testament ' and Church history, that kings were reproved by the prophets - and separated from the Church by bishops ;2 and at the end

judicii nee Romania, nee Salicis, nee a judieibus ordinata non valeat, nee

Qiindobadis, aed divinis et apostolicis quiequam quod contra evangeliese vel

legibus judieandos. Quanquam in prophetiese aut apoatoliese doctrinss

regno Christiano etiam ipsas leges constitutionem sueeessorum patrum

publieas oporteat esse Christianas, aetum fuerit, stabit. Et quod ab in-

eonvenientes videlicet, et eonsonantes fidelibus aut heretieis factum fuerit

ChristianitatL" omnino qassabitur."

^ Pseudo-Isidore, Marcellinus, Dee. ^ Hincmar of Rheims, De Div. Loth.

, iv. : "Non licet ei^ imperatori vel et Tetb. Quceitio 6. "Dicunt quoque

cuiquam pietatem custodienti aliquid etiam aliqui sapientes, quia iste prin-

contra mandata divina preesumere nee oeps rex est, et nuUorum legibus Tel

quiequam quod evangelicia propheti- judiciis subjaoet nisi solius Dei, qui

oisque et apostolicis regulis obviatur eum in regno, quod suus pater ill!

agere. Injustum enim juditium et dimisit, regem constituit^ et si Yoluerit

definitio injusta regis metu vel jussu pro hac vel alia causa ibit ad placitom.






OHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 279


of this section of the treatise he lays it down that the synods of the Church know no respect of persons.^

Hincmar's judgment is clear, and we do not doubt that almost all ecclesiastics in the ninth century would have agreed with him. That the Popes may have been unwilling to go the length of directly and explictly excommunicating the emperors of the fifth and sixth centuries, we have seen in former chapters. But in their relations to the Frankish rulers the Popes were not so restrained. As early as 770 we find Stephen III. threatening to excommunicate Charles and Carlo- \ man if they neglected his injunctions against a marriage with the daughter of the Lombard king Desiderius ; ^ and in regard to this very question on which Hincmar writes we find that Pope Nicholas threatened at last to excommunicate Lothair unless he would take back Tetburga.^


vel ad synodum, et si noluerit, libere et licenter dimittet : et aicut a suis eplscopis, quidquid egerii, non debet excommunicari, ita ab aliis episcopis non potest judicari, quoniam solius Dei principatui debet subjici, a quo solo potuit in principatu constitui ; et quod f acit, et qualis est in regimine, divino sit nutu, sicut scriptum est :

  • Cor regis in manu Dei, quocunque

voluerit vertet illud.'"

Hesponno, " Hsec vox non est catholici Christiani, sed nimium bias- phemi, et spiritu diabolico pleni." He cites David's reproof by Nathan, Saul's by Samuel, Rehoboam's by the prophet, and proceeds : *' Quando pec- cavenint reges, et filii Israel, et traditi sunt in manus gentium, sicut Manasses et Sedechias, vel timuerunt a facie Domini sicut Ezechias, per prophetas vel iram a Domino susceperunt, vel misericordiam meruenint. Et in Deuteronomio scriptum est (Deut. xvii. 8-18). Per sacerdotes enim dicit Dominus (Ps. ii. 10-12). Et apostolica auctoritas commonet, ut et reges etiam obediant prsepositis suis in Domino, qui pro animabus eorum invigilant, ut non cum tristitia hoc faciant. Et beatus Qelasius papa ad


Anastasium imperatorem scribit : ' Quia du8e sunt personse, quibus principaliter hie regitur mundus, scilicet pontificalis auctoritas, et regia dignitas, et tanto majus est pondus pontificum quanto de ipsis etiam regibus reddituri sunt Domino rationem.' Ambrosius Theo- dosium imperatorem ab ecclesia culpis exigentibus segregavit et per pceni- tentiam revocavit."

^ Hincmar of Rheims, De Div. Loth, et Tetb. Qucest, 6, Responsio, " De eo quod dicitur. Quia Rex, si noluerit venire ad synodum, libere etiam com- pellatus dimittet: sancta Scriptura, sacrique canones monstrant, in judicio personam non debere accipere, sed causae qualitatem disoemere."

3 M. G. H. Ep., iii Codex Carolinus, 45 : *' Et si quis, quod non optamus, contra hujusmodi nostrsB adjurationis atque exhortationis seriem ag^re prse- sumserit, sciat se auctoritate domini mei, beati Petri apostolorum principis, anathematis vinculo esse innodatum et a regno Dei alienum atque cum diabolo et ejus atrocissimis pompis et ceteris impiis setemis incendiis concre- mandum deputatum."

' M. G. H. Scriptorum, vol. i. Ann. Bert. ad. a. 865.






280 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY, [pabt iv.

It must at the same time be noticed that we may find a partial explanation of the existence of such views as those which Hincmar condemns, in the tone of some letters of Pope L^JV. in reference to a threat of Hincmar to excommunicate the Emperor Lothair. He complains of the pride of Hincmar, which had led him to threaten with excommunication the emperor whom Pope Paschal had consecrated with the oil of benediction, thus violating every divine and earthly law.^ Leo IV.'s phrases are no doubt related to such a question as whether it was competent for any one except the Pope himself to excommunicate kings and emperors, and must not be con- strued as meaning that Leo would not have claimed that authority for himself: they belong to the question of the relation of the authority of bishops and metropolitans to that of the Pope. But it is easy to see that such phrases might tend to encourage the judgment that within his own dominion the ruler was not amenable to the jurisdiction of Church courts. There were clearly certain ambiguities and uncer- tainties in regard to the relation of the discipline of the Church to the monarch in the ninth century ; but no doubt, also, the Church was very clear that it had spiritual authority over even the highest in station.

No doubt these claims, that the church should exercise jurisdiction even over the most exalted persons in the State,

^ M. G. H. Ep., v. Ep. Select. Pont. Domini, quern sedis apostolica bene-

Rom. Leo IV., 36 : ** Ita ut, quern dictionis oleo publice consecravit

imperatorem princeps eacerdotum et sibique proprium fecit heredem,

primus sanctae recordationis predecessor anathematis jaculum contra omnem,

noster dominus Pascalis papa oleo bene- non solum divinam, immo mundanam

dictionis unctum consecraverat more institutionem inferre presumpsit.

predecessorum apostolicorum, una cum " Item. Unum pro culpe ause

fratre Carolo rege et uxoribus ac filiis, malicia censura sedis apostolicse com-

anathemate injurasset, nostrum et muniter mandamus, ut neque de sua

ejusdem magni imperatoris minis- unquam prsesumptione valeat gloriari,

terium parvipendens et transgressus neque contra vos, quem Deus sibi

divinas pariter et humanas constitu- principem et imperatorem elegit, et

tiones." per manus summi et apostolici pontif-

Leo rV., 87 : ** Nee iUum etiam can- icis sanctificatum benedictionis oleum

onice possumus collaudare, quod super- super vestrum caput effiidit, clam vel

stite prsssule sedem ejus invasit, qui publice audeat aliquam quocumque

etiam, cum debuerat de jactura honoris tempore anathematis vel aliam injurie

proprii valde esse perterritus, in unctum inferre jacturam. "






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 281

are to be interpreted as referring to spiritual matters. But it was not easy to draw a clear line between things which were to be regarded as spiritual and those which belouged to * the secular sphere. We have already noticed that Jonas of Orleans, in commenting on the twelfth letter of Gelasius, urges that as the priests will have to render account to God for kings as well as for private persons, it is their duty carefully to admonish them lest they depart from the will of God, or from the proper discharge of the office which was committed to them.^ The ecclesiastical order was in some measure responsible for the just administration of the State, just as we have seen that the king was responsible for the good order of the Church. It is interesting to see that this principle finds expression in some of the formal

documents of these times. Tn tbft " PraPPftpt^'r^ " ^f (Jhlnthar II.,

of about the end of the sixth century or the beginning of the

seventh, we find it provided, that if any judge should condemn

a man unjustly in the absence of the king, the bishop is to A^fAcll j

reprove him.^ Again, in the docu3ifint(w;oncerning the election

of Guido in 889 we find a provision that the common people

are to have their own laws, and are not to be burdened

further than the laws allow : the count is to see to this, but

if he neglect his duty, or allow injustice to be done, he is

to be excommunicated by the bishop of the place till he has

rendered satisfaction.^ Again, therefore, we find nothing

strictly new in the emphatic assertion of the Pseudo-Isidorian

^ Jonas of Orleans, De Instit. Reg., judicavit versatim melius discussione

cap. i. : "Ergo quia tantse auctoritatis, habeta emendare procuret." imo tanti discriminis est ministerium ' M. Q. H. Leg., sect. U. vol. ii.

sacerdotum, ut de ipsis etiam regibus No. 222, "Widonis Capitulatio Elec-

Deo sint rationem reddituri, oportet tionis," 6 : " Plebei homines et universi

et valde necesse est, ut de vestra eoclesise filii libere suis utantur legibus ;

salute semper simus sollidti, vosque ex parte publica ultra, quam legibus

ne a voluntate Dei, quod absit, aut sancitum est, ab eis non exigatur, nee

a ministerio quod vobis commisit, violenter opprimantur ; quodsi factum

erretis, vigilanter admoneamus." fuerit, legaliter per comitem ipsius loci

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. i, emendetur, si suo voluerit deinceps pot- No. 8, Chlotarii II. Praeceptio, 6 : iri honore ; si vero ipse neglexerit vel " Si judex aliquem contra legem in- fecerit aut facienti assensum prebuerit, juste damnaverit, in nostri absentia a loci episcopo usque dignam satisfactio- ab episcopo castigetur, ut quod perpere nem excommunicatus habeatur."






282 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CBNTURY. [part iv.

Decretals, that auy one who is oppressed should freely be allowed to appeal to the priest.^

The interyeiition of the .bi9bQBS_for_the protect ion^ fitJihft oppressed has, indeed, a long and complex history. As early as the time of Justinian we find the Imperial Govern- ment laying upon the bishops a great deal of responsibility for the supervision of the expenditure of money left for public charities and other public purposes; and we even find them given a considerable power of intervention, to protect the citizens against attempts on the part of the magistrates to impose improper exactions.* It may be doubted whether such powers were originally given to them on account of their spiritual authority, or because of the position occupied by the bishops as prominent citizens in their dioceses : the truth pro- bably is that both their secular and their ecclesiastical position contributed to bring about such arrangements. However this may be, it is clear that in the ninth century the Church, through the bishops, exercised a very considerable authority in the control of even the secular afifairs of society, altogether apart from that authority which the bishops possessed as being among the great men of the kingdom or empire. f The Pope and the bishops of the church exercised a con- / siderable authority in the appointment and in the deposition of kings and emperors. We do not wish to discuss the question , which in later times was often raised, as to the nature of the authority by which Charles the Great was elected to the empire. In later times men on the one side maintained that this was done by the Pope, — that he in the plenitude of his power conferred the empire on Charles; while on the other i side it was held that the action of the Pope was simply that j of one who. recognised his accession, and by consecration in- voked on it the divine blessing. We do not know that there is any reason to suppose that at the time the theory of the matter occupied men's minds to any serious extent at all.

^ Pseud. • Isidore, Anacletus Dec. his fulciatur et liberetur."

xvi. : *' OmniB enim oppressus libere ^ Cf. esp. Justinian Codex, L 3. 45,

saoerdotum, si voluerit, appellet judi- and i 4. 26. tium et a nullo prohibeatur, sed ab






i


CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 283

The Franks had come to Italy on the urgent invitation of the Popes as their protectors against the Lombard power, and later on against the Greek power. Pope Stephen II. had recog- nised Pippin as king of the Franks, and had afterwards crowned him, and finally Pope Leo III. had crowned Charles the Great as emperor. We doubt whether at the time it occurred to any one to consider what precise authority lay behind these acts. There is no doubt, however, that in the ninth century we find clear traces of the rapid development of a theory that ' the Pope had some very distinct share in the appointment of j emperors or kings, and that the consecration by him was/ regarded as something more than the mere solemn recognition of a proper election or succession, and the invocation of the divine blessing. And so also with the position of the bishops in the appointment and consecration of kings, there are very clear traces of the conception that they had a great deal to say in elections, and that their consecration was looked upon as a very important matter.

It is here again diflScult to say how much of the authority of the Pope or the bishops is to be attributed to the political j ' importance of their position among the most important magnates of the empire, and how much to their religious authority. We ! must be prepared to recognise that each has its real influence, while these two elements of their authority are often fused to such an extent that it is exceedingly difficult to separate them. When, for instance, we find that the provisions for the partition of his dominions by Charles the Great, after they had been considered and sworn to by the magnates of the * -^ empire, were sent to Pope Leo that he might subscribe them,^ we can hardly say whether this is to be taken as a recognition of some right in the head of the spiritual power as such to take his part in these arrangements, or whether it is to be interpreted as due to the sense of the great political influence

^ M. G. H. Scriptorum, vol. i., pacis conservandse causa factse atque

Einhard, " Annals " for 806 : " De hsec omnia litt«ris mandata sunt, et

hac partitione et testamentum factum, Leoni papse, ut his sua manu sub-

et jurejurando ab optimatibus Fran- scriberet, per Einhardum missa." corum confirmatum, et constitutiones






284 POUTIOAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part iv.

I which the Pope had exercised and^ was still exercising in Western Europe, and especially in Italy.

Whatever may be the exact meaning which we are to attach to such a recognition of the authority of the Pope, there is no doubt of the importance of his position later in the century.

  • In the * ChroniuuL-Salfirnitanum ' there is preserved a letter of

the Emperor Lewis II. written to the Emperor Basil of Con- stantinople in 867. It appears that Basil had expressed his in* ^ dignation that Lewis should call himself " Imperator Augustus." Lewis defends his use of the title on the ground largely that he had been anointed and consecrated by the Pope, and says that those Prankish princes were called first kings and then emperors who were anointed with the holy oil by the Pope.^ It has been suggested that this letter is spurious — that it is impossible to think that any Prankish emperor would have spoken in such terms. It seems to us that such a line of argument is exceed- ingly unsafe, for, apart from this letter, there is considerable evidence that at least in the latter part of the eighth century it was frequently recognised that the Pope had a very import- ant part in the appointment and consecration of kings and emperors. In a former chapter we have referred to the terms of the document concerning the election of Charles the Bald to the kingdom of Italy at Pavia in 876 ; we must now notice in this document the reference to the elevation of Charles, a few months earlier, to the empire as being the work of the Pope. The bishops and other magnates of Italy elect Charles as king in view of the fact that Ood had raised him to the imperial throne by means of the vicar of the blessed prince of the apostles Peter and Paul, Pope John.* It might, perhaps,

  • M. Q. H. Scriptorum, vol. iii., men provecti, et ad Bomani, princi-

'Chronicon Salemitanum,' p. 522: patus imperium, quod supemo nutu

'* Invenimus prseBertim, cum et ipsi potimur, aspicientes."

patrui nostri, gloriosi reges, absque in- P. 623. " Nam Francorum principes

yidia imperatorem nos vocitent et primo reges, deinde vero imperatores

imperatorem esse procul dubio faten- dicti sunt, hii dumtaxat, qui a Romano

tur, non profecto ad setatem, qua pontifioe ad hoc oleo sancto perfusi

nobis majores sunt, attendentes, sed ad sunt."

unctionem et sacrationem, qua per ^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. it

summi pontificis manus, impositione et Ko. 220, Kar. IL Imp. Electio :

oratione divinitus ad hoc sumus cul- " Jam quia divina pietas vos beatonua






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 285

be suggested that this is only an Italian view of the appoint- ment of Charles the Bald, but the same conception is expressed in the proceedings of the synod of Ponthion, which was held in June and July 876. We learn that at this synod the proceed- ings of the Italian magnates at Pavia were read and confirmed : the part of the Pope in the election of Charles to the empire seems as clearly recognised at Ponthion as it had been at Pavia.^ We find similar references to the influence of the Pope in the election of kings in the separate kingdoms which made up the empire, while here we also find a similar authority attributed to the bishops. In the proceedings of the synod held at Quierzy in 858 we find some very significant phrases on the subject. The synod sent a letter, which is thought to have been composed by Hincmar of Rheims, to Lewis of Grermany, pro- testing against his invasion of the territories of Charles, and addressing a special remonstrance to those archbishops and bishops who had themselves, with the consent of the people, anointed Charles to be king, while the Holy See had afterwards honoured and confirmed him, by letters, as king. The synod evidently attaches great importance to the unction, and speaks of him who faithlessly and contumaciously lifts his hand against the Lord's anointed, as of one who despises Christ, and who will, therefore, perish by the spiritual sword.^ Again,

principum apostolorum Petri et Pauli sibi protectorem ac defensorem esse,

interventione per vicarium ipeorum, ita et nos qui de Francia, Burgundia,

domnum videlicet Johannem sum- Aquitania, Septimania, Neustria ac

mum pontificem et universalem papam Provincia pridie Ealendas Julii in loco,

spiritalemque patrem vestrum, ad pro- qui dicitur Pontigonis, amio xxxvii in

fectum sanctse Dei ecclesise nostror- Francia ac imperii primo, jussu ejusdem

umque omnium incitavit et ad domni et gloriosi augusti convenimus,

imperiale culmen Sancti Spiritus pari consensu ac concordi devotione

judicio provexit, nos unanimiter vos eligimus et confirmamus."

. . . Italici regni regem elegimus." ^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. ii.

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. voL ii. Ko. 297, "Epist. Synodi. Carisiacensis

No. 279 (B.): "Sicutdomnus Johannes ad Hlud. Beg. Qerm. Directa," 15:

apostolicus et universalis papa primo " Maxime autem nobis necesse est loqui

Bomse elegit atque sacra unctione con- cum illis archiepiscopis et episcopis,

stituit omnesque Italici regni episcopi, qui consensu et voluntate populi regni

abbatee, comites et reliqui omnes, qui istius domnum nostrum fratrem ves-

cum illis convenerunt, domnum nos- trum unxerunt in regem sacro chris-

trum gloriosum imperatorem Earolum mate divina traditione quemque sancta

augustum unanimi devotione elegerunt sedes apostolica mater nostra litteris






286 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.


we find the archbishops and the bishops of the kingdom of Aries electing Lewis, the son of Boso, to follow his father in that kingdom, and they do this partly on the ground that the Holy See had approved of such an election.^

We find the strongest and most remarkable assertion of the importance of the consecration and unction by the bishops in another document, which refers to the election of Charles the Bald as King of the Neustrian Franks. This is a proclamation issued in the name of Charles the Bald himself in 859: he recounts how, after his election by the bishops and other faithful men of the kingdom, he had been consecrated and anointed with the holy chrism, and had received the crown and sceptre, and he urges that after this consecration he cannot be cast down from the kingdom by any, at least without the judgment of the bishops by whose ministry he had been consecrated king: they are, he says, the thrones of God, among whom God is seated, and by whom he decrees his judgments, and to tbeir paternal reproofs and chastise- ments he had been and still was prepared to submit.^ We may perhaps suitably recall the phrases in which the bishops describe the deposition of Lewis the Pious,' and the words of


apostolicis ut regem honorare studuit et confirmare." The letter then cites examplee of the reverence shown to the Lord's anointed in the Old Testa- ment, and continues: "Sic et qui infideliter et contumaciter in unctum qualemcunque Domini manum mittit, dominum christorum Christum con- temnit, et in anima procul dubio spiritualis gladii animadversione perit." ^ M. Q. H. Leg., sect, ii vol. ii. No. 289, " Hludowici Regis Arelatensis Electio," 890 : " Cum igitur diligenter conperissemus, quod assensus sanctse catholicae et apostolicss matris nostrse huic faveret electioni, simul conveni- mus in civitatem Valentiam (i.e,f Arch- bishop of Lyons, Archbishop of Aries, Archbishop of Embrun, Archbishop of Vienne, with other bishops), . . . at- que secundum Dei voluntatem quse- flituri exploravimus, si hunc digne et


rationibiliter secundum monita dominii apostolici, cujus scripta prse manibus habebantur, super nos regem oon- stituere deberemus.

^ M. G. H. Leg., sect ii. voL iL No. 300, *' Libellus ProclamationiB ad- versus Wenilonem " : "A qua oonsecra- tione vel regni sublimitate subplantari vel proici a nullo debueram saltem sine audientia et judicio episcoporum, quorum ministerio in regem sum oon- secratus, et qui throni Dei sunt dicti, in quibus Deus sedit et per quos sua decemit judicia ; quorum patemis cor- reptionibus et casligatoriis judidis me subdere fui paratus et in prsesenti sum subditus." See p. 252.

' M. Q. H. Leg., sect. ii. vol. iL No. 197, *'. . . quia potestate pi- vatus erat juxta divinum condHum et ecclesiasticam auctoritatem.'* See p. 250.






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 287

Hincmar in referring to the same event, and to the restoration of Lewis by the bishops with the consent of the people.^

The importance of this conception of the authority of thev Pope and the bishops in relation to the appointment and theT^ deposition of emperors and kings is very obvious. As we haverT" said, it is very difficult, perhaps impossible, to disentangle the relative importance of their spiritual and their secular position in the matter. The fact that they are great persons in Western Europe, or in a particular kingdom, has' obviously much to do with it, but there are already clear traces of a theory that, as spiritual rulers, they have some, though it may be a somewhat indefinable, authority over the^ secular power.

We have endeavoured to bring out as clearly as possible two facts with regard to the theory of the relation of the authorities of Church and State in the ninth century. First, that in the ninth, just as in the fifth century, men believed firmly that the ' two authorities were separate and independent, each sacred and supreme in its own sphere — that the ecclesiastic owed allegiance ' to the king in secular matters, and that the king owed allegi- ance to the Church in spiritual matters. But also, secondly, that the practical experience of the ninth century made it clear that it was very difficult to distinguish the two spheres by any hard-and-fast line. Still, we think that the writers of the ninth century held to the theory of a dual authority in society ; we think that they would have repudiated any other conception.

It is true that there is one work which belongs to this period, which in the later middle ages was interpreted as expressing quite another theory — the theory, that is, of the supremacy of the spiritual power over the temporal This document is the >^ famous " Donation ".j)jL Qonstantine. We have hitherto left this document out of account for two reasons — ^first, because it is almost certain that the later interpretation of the docu-

^ Hincmar of Rheims, De Div. Loth. palis unanimitas, saniore consilio, cum

et Tetb., Qu. vi. Reap. : " Nostra setate populi consensu et Ecclesise et regno

pium Augustum Ludovicum a regno restituit." dejectum, post satisfactionem episco-






288 POLITICAL THEORY OP NINTH CENTURY, [pabt iv.

ment was incorrect ; and, secondly, because, whatever its mean- ing and purpose may have been, it exercised no appreciable infloence in the ninth century on the theory of the relations of Church and State.

From our point of view the important phrases of the " Dona- tion " are those which deal with the grant of authority to the Pope, and the transference of the seat of imperial authority from Bome to Byzantium.^ The exact meaning of these phrases has been discussed by a number of scholars, and it is generally agreed that the interpretation given to them in the later middle ages can hardly be that which was in the mind of the com- piler. In later times they were understood to signify that Constantine granted to the Popes a complete temporal au- thority over the West, and it is not disputed that the words might have this meaning ; but it is now generally agreed that they must be interpreted as referring to a grant of temporal authority in Italy. Most historical critics think that the purpose of the document was to assist the Soman See in secur- ing the reversion of the Byzantine territories in Italy, and especially of the Exarchate. It seems possible that the "Donation" was built up in part on traditions which may have been long current in Italy, and that the circumstances of the eighth century, when the Bishops of Bome came to be the actual representatives of the Soman res publica in Italy, and its principal defence against the Lombards, may have tended to give these traditions a new significance, and to sug-

^ Pseudo-Isidore, * Exemplar Domini pragmaticum constitutum decemimus

Imperatoris Oonstantini.' Unde ut disponendum, atque jursd sanctse

non pontificalis apex vilescat, sed Romanse ecclesise concedimus perman-

magis amplius quam terreni imperii sOrum. XJnde congruum prospeximus

dignitas et glorisd potentia decoretur, nostrum imperium et regni poteetatem

ecoe tarn palatium nostrum, ut prsdla- orientalibus transferri ac transmutari

tum est, quamque Romane urbis et regionibus et in Bizantisa provintia in

omnes Italise seu occidentalium re- obtimo loco nomini nostro civitatem

gionum provincias, loca et civitates sedificari et nostrum illic oonstitui

sepe fato beatissimo pontifici nostro imperium, quoniam ubi principatus

Silvestro universali pap88 contradentes sacerdotum et christiane religionis

atque relinquentes ejus vel succes- caput ab imperatore coelesti oon-

sorum ipsius pontificum potestati et stitutum est^ justum non est ut illic

dictione firma imperiali censura per imperatorterrenushabeatpotestatem." banc nostram divalem sacram et






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OF CHURCH AND STATE. 289

gest to the author their reduction to a definite and coherent form. We are not here concerned with the growth of the temporal states of the Bishop of Eome, but it seems to us that so far from looking upon this as the result of an unreasonable greed for secular power, it should be recognised that nothing was more natural than that the Popes, finding themselves to be the actual chiefs of what survived of the ancient Eoman State in Italy, should have desired to maintain and even extend their authority. Any one who studies the papal correspond- ence and the * Liber Pontificalis * in the eighth century will, we | think, feel that the leadership of the Boman res puUica in the West was forced upon them rather than deliberately sought. ^ It was only slowly and reluctantly that they drew away from the Byzantine authority, for after all, as dvilised members of ^ the Eoman State, they preferred the Byzantine to the barbarian; and when circumstances had practically destroyed the Byzan- tine power in Italy, it was natural that they should seek to hold together, or to recover from the barbarian, even though, like the Frank, he was a friendly barbarian, some fragments of ^ the ancient commonwealth of civilisation. It is of course true that once they had broken with the Byzantine power, they had l> no inclination for reunion with it, but this again, considering the history of the eighth century, was not unnatural.

It is then generally thought that the purpose of the " Donation " was to assist the Bishops of Eome in establishing a claim to the reversion of the Byzantine authority in Italy. Other conjectures, such as that of Grauert,^ that it was intended to support the Frankish empire against the criticism of the Byzantines, though they have been urged with much learning and ingenuity, seem too far •fetched. It must at the same time be recognised that the problem of the date and place of origin of the document is surrounded with perplexities. The "Donation" cannQtJt>e-4ater- iJian^ Jihe_ m century, as it is contained in a manuscript of that time, and is em Eodig d -Ja^he £aej]doJbidoriaa,^cretalSj^ How long before that it may have existed is a question of great complexity. In a letter of Pope Hadrian I. of 778 there are phrases which, it

^ * Historisches Jahrbuch der Gorresgesellschaft/ 3, 4, 5. VOL. I. T






290 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [part IV.

is urged, imply a knowledge of the " Donation," but the text cannot be said to render this certain.^ Hadrian evidently refers to some tradition of great grants of authority by the Emperor Constantino, but whether he is referring to this document is another question. In a letter of the same Pope to Constantine and Irene, of 785, he describes a vision of Constantino, which suggests the tradition which is embodied in the Donation," but this does not at all necessarily prove that he was acquainted with the "Donation" itself.^ The first jwrit^ f^ of who m it can be said with any degree of con- fidence that they are acquainted with this document are Ado o f^Vienne ^ and Hincmar^of^Bheimg.^ in the ninth cen-

■ tury. It is certainly perplexing that there should be no certain evidence that the document was known in Italy until the latter part of the tenth century.^ At the same time the more recent investigations into its phraseology, and especi- ally those of Schefifer-Boichorst,® seem to make it fairly clear

V that the work was compiled in Italy, and in the latter part of the eight! I century.

In later volumes we shall have to consider what importance this document may have had in the scholastic period. For the present it is enough to say that it produced no appreciay^fifect upon the political theory of the ninth century. The theorists of the following centuries may have tried to reduce to a com- plete unity the elements of authority in society; the ninth century writers knew nothing of this.

If we now look back over the political theory of the ninth century, we can lay down certain general propositions about its

^ M. Q. H., Epist. iii.. Codex Car- ^ Ado of Vienne, Chronicon; Migne

olinus, 60: "Et sicut temporibus Patr. Lat., vol. 123, p. 92.

beat! Silvestri Romani pontificia a ^ M. G. H. Leg., sect. ii. voL ii.

sanctse recordationis piissimo Con- Hincmar of Bheims, *^ De Ordine Pal-

stantino, magno imperatore, per ejus atii," 13.

largitatem sancta Dei catholica et '^ M. G. H., Diplomatum ii. Otto

apostolica Romana ecclesia elevata at- III., No. 389.

que exaltata est et potestatem in his ^ " Mittheilungen des Institute fiir

Hesperise partibus largiri dignatus." Oesterreichische Geschichtsforschung,"

  • Pope Hadrian I. ; Ep. Ivi. Migne 10 and 11.

Patr. Lat., voL 96, p. 1220.






CHAP. XXI.] AUTHORITIES OP CHURCH AND STATE. 291

character. It is, we think, in the first place, clear that there did not exist in this time and among these writers any general philosoph ical system of poHtical theory. Certain great and important conceptions the men of this period apprehended and developed with force ; but in the main it is true to say that they are concerned much mo re with thepractical circumstances of the life of their time than with the attempt to construct a system of political thought. We have pointed out the fact that their statemen ts are often inc ohergit. sometimes almost self-contra- dic£biy Jttiis is_ the direct conseq[uence of the fact that they are not conscio us of any systematic theory as lying behind their pr actical judg ments. We think that when we have recognised this, and if we very carefully keep it in mind, we may still with justice say that their treatment of the character and the founda- tion of the organised life of society turns upon three great conceptions.

In the first place, they clearly held, and in some measure understood, that conception of the equality of human^nature, -^ \ whose history we have studied from the time of Cicero. They * not only reproduced the phrases of the Fathers, but they clearly also understood their point of view. This implies, indeed, something more than the fact that they held to the theory of equality ; it also means that they understood and approved the conception of the difiference between the primitive condition of * man and the actual condition of human society. They held that it was not nature but man's faults which had brought into . existence the conventional institutions of society. It is quite true that, except with regard to the institution of slavery, the J * subject does not greatly occupy their minds ; but it is import- ant, especially with reference to the developed mediaeval theory of society, to recognise that this conception was always alive.

Secondly, they held very firmly to the conviction of the \ ^ ^^ sacred character of the organised structure of society in ^ , government. They follow the New Testament and the Fathers intEe doctrine that the civil order of society is necessary, and , that it is sacred. Indeed it is the very firmness with which they hold this that causes them to adopt the extreme language in which St Gregory the Great had expressed the conception,






y


292 POLITICAL THEORY OF NINTH CENTURY. [PART IV.


and sometimes to speak as though any resistance to the actions of those who represented the sacred authority were a thing unlawful and irreligious. The disorders of the time were so / great, the necessity of delivering western Europe from the ^ I confusions which followed the downfall of the ancient empire in the West was so obvious, that we cannot wonder if at times they exaggerate the principle of obedience to authority. But, in the third place, the theory of the ninth century \^ recognised with equal clearness the necessit;^ of checking^fehe

unjust and tyrannical use of autKoH^^T^f the Fathers like St Ambrose and St Isidore lay much stress on the limitation of authority by its end — namely, the establishment and main- tenance of justice — the ninth-century writers assert this con- ception with even greater clearness, and, under the influence of the traditions of the Teutonic races, find a practical applica- tion of the theory of justice in the conception of thft ffnpr^^ary jpf law, and of the limited and conditioned character of the authority of the ruler. The emperor or king is bound by the national law, and derives his authority, ultimately no doubt from God, but immediately from the nation, and holds this authority on the condition of his setting forward righteousness and justice in the State.


\






INDEX.


^^..-Aml


Acacius, Patriarch of Constantinople, 186. Ado of Vienne, 290. Agobard of Lyons —

Equality of human nature, 200. Condemns restrictions on baptism of

slaves of Jews, 200, 202. The soul of the slave belongs to Gk)d,

202. Low social position of inferior clergy

in ninth century, 207. Source and authority of canons, 276, 277. Alcuin —

Men in primitive times the lords of cattle, not of their fellow-men, 203. Slavery a consequence of iniquity or

adversity, 203. Origin of society and States, 211. Urges on rulers duty of doing justice,

224. Priests to declare the Word of Gk)d, princes to obey them, 274. Alexander of Hales, interprets St Isi- dore's phrase, "Communis omnium possessio," 143, note 1. Alexandrian and Antiochene schools of theology, 185. ibrose, St — Interpretation of St Paul on natural

law, 83, 105. Natural law and the Mosaic law,

105. Definitions of natural law, 106. The slave is the equal of his master by nature, and may be his superior in virtue, 115. Freedom and slavery of the soul, 115. Sin the real slavery; better for

vicious man to be a slave, 118. Slaves should patiently accept their

condition, 121. Ctovemment a remedy for foolish- ness, 130. His theory of property, 136-142.


By nature there is no private prop- erty, 136, 137.

Private property the result of avarice, 137.

Almsgiving an act of justice, not charity, 137.

Relation of this conception to St Thomas Aquinas's distinction be- tween property as a right of distri- bution ana a right of use, 139.

Relation of St Ambrose's conception of this to conception of St Augus- tine, 142.

Justice the "ratio" of the State — contrast with St Augustine, 162.

The ui^ust ruler is not properly God's representative, 162.

The ruler and liberty, 163.

The ruler bound to observe the laws, 163, 164.

But also legibu8 abaolutua, 164.

Differs materially in political theory from St Augustine, 170.

Theory of remtion between Church and State clearly drawn out, 180- 184.

The priest should show respect to the civil ruler, 180.

The priest must rebuke civil ruler if he transgress, 180.

The Emperor the son of the Church, 180.

Exclusion of Theodosius from the Eucharist for massacre of Thes- salonians, 180, 181.

Threatened exclusion of Theodosius for a smaller matter : St Ambrose's account of this, 181, 182.

The Church exercises jurisdiction over all Christians, even the most exalted in rank, 182,

Secular law inferior to the law of God, 182.

Question of secular authority and Church property, 182-184.






294


INDEX.


Distinction between churches and

other property of the Church, 184. Possible relation between his view

of independence of Church and his

concepuon of limitations of secular

authority of civil ruler, 184. Ambrosiaster —

Relation of law of nature to law of

Moses, 104. Question of identity with author of

  • Quaestiones Veteris et Novi Testa-

menti/ 104, note 4. Full discussion of origin of slavery

and its relation to equality of

human niture, 118. God made men free, 118. Slavery a consequence of sin, 113. Slavery extends to body only : G

alone is master of the soul, 113. Masters must be just to their slaves,

who are also their equals, 113. Almsgiving an act of justice, for God

gives all things in common to all

men, 187. The king the Vicar of God, 149,

179, 216. The kin^ has the image of God, as

the bishop has that of Christ,

149, 179, 216. Relation of David to Saul : the divine

character of royal office cannot be

lost by misconduct, 160. ' Obscure passage as to evil form of

government, which is not from God,

His writings the possible source of the phrase " Vicar of God," spoken of the king, in ninth century, 216, 216. Anarchism in primitive Church, 98-97. Anthemius, Emperor, 189. Antoninus Pius, rescript for protection

of slaves, 49. Apocalypse, its evidence in regard to relation of Christians to Roman Gov- ernment, 98. Aristotle —

Di£ferenoe between his ideas and

those of Roman Lawyers, 2. His t heory of inequality of human

natuMr. Relation of inequality to govern- ment and slavery, 7. His conceptions related to circum- stances of Greek civilisation, 7, 8, 46. Contrast between his view and that

of Cicero and Seneca, 8, 46. Influence on Cicero's view of slavery,

12. Conception of just form of govern- ment in relation to Cicero's, 16. Relation of this to views of Stoics,

80. Relation of his theory of inequality to the theory of Lawyers, 46, 46.


GkwK


His theory of political society as related to St Paul's, 98.

Contrast of his view of slavery with that of Fathers', 146. Athanasius, St, Quotes letter of Hosius of Cordova in wnich he warns £mperor Constantine that he has no rignt to interfere in Church affairs, 177. Augustine, Pseudo- Protests against severity to Christian slaves, 116.

Slave a brother, in grace, of master, 116.

Slaves should love and obey masters, 121.

G^ made masters and slaves, 121. Lugustine, St —

Interpretation of St Paul on natural law, 88, 106.

Definition of natural law, 106.

God made men free, 114.

Slavery a consequence of, a punish- ment or remedy for sin, imposed by just sentence of God, 118.

Christ makes men good slaves, 121.

Christian slaves must not claim eman- cipation on precedent of Jewish slaves, 121.

Masters should treat slaves like chil- dren with respect to their spiritual wellbeing, 123.

Man is by nature sociable, 126, 166.

Government of man over man not natural and primitive, 126, 128.

Government made necessary by sin, a divine remedy, 130.

Community of goods the more perfect way, 136.

Private property lawful, 136.

His theory of property, 139-142.

A defence of confiscation of Dona- tists* property by Imperial (Jovem- ment, 139, 140.

By divine law all things belong to God or the saints, 1^.

Private property an institution of human and positive law, 140, 141.

Contrast between his theory of prop- erty and that of Roman Lawyers, 141.

Refuses to recognise Donatist argu- ment that their property should not be confiscated because it was the result of their labour, 141.

Right of property limited by its just use, 140-142.

Relation of this theory to that of Ambrose and other Fathers and the medieval theory of right of private property, 142.

Authority of wicked as of good rulers drawn from God, 161.

His view on this drawn from Old Testament, 169.

Contrast between his conception of the State and St Ambrose's, 162.






INDEX.


295


St Augustine understood in ninth century as agreeing with St Am- ' brose that the ruler is bound by the laws, 164.

His theory of the State and the place of justice in it, 164-170.

Original equality of men, slavery and government the result of sin, 164, 166.

Organised society of the State with its coercive character a conven- tional institution, 165.

Discusses Cicero's definition of the State, 165.

Objects to it that there can be no justice when men do not serve God, and thus Cicero's definition would not apply to Boman re- public, 165, 166.

His own definition of the State, 166.

The same as Cicero's,'with the element of law and justice omitted, 166.

This definition seems to represent his normal judgment, 167.

Two passages which seem to point in another direction, 167.

Doubtful if St Augustine's definition exercised any influence on mediae- val thought, 168, 169, 176.

Relation of his definition to theory of the unlimited authority of the ruler, 169.

His view that the worst as well as the best kings represent Gk>d, 169, 173.

Relation of his definition to general Patristic view of State, 174.

His omission of justice from defini- tion of the State has no influence in ninth century, 220, 221.

Barnabas: Christian men should share all things with their brethren, 132, 134. Basil, Emperor: letter to him of Em- peror Lewis II. claiming title of Em- peror on ground that he had been anointed by Pope, 284. Basiliscus, 189. Bishops —

Have the image of Christ, as king

has image of God, 149, 179, 216. The judges of all, and cannot be

judged by any, 177, 274. Stand "in secundo loco, in vice

Christi tantum," 215, 260. The Vicars of God, 273, 274. Are to rule over and correct kings,

274,275. To protect people against injustice,

281, 282. Their authority in appointment and deposition of kings, 282-287. Bosanquet, Bernard, on '* General Will," 62.


Canon Law- Derives theory of natural law from St

Isidore of Seville, 106, 107. Apostolical canons on ordination of

slaves, 122, note 1. St Gregory protests against violation

of canons by the Emperor, 154. f Emperor Maurice: action contrary

to canons, 156. Church has laws independent of

State, 175. Stands alongside of secular law,

253. Kings subject to Canon Law, 257,

275-277. Canons enacted by bishops, but king

gives his consent and authority,

259, 260. Relation of kings and emperors to

synods and their canons, 265-267. Conception of source and authority of

canons in ninth century, 275-277. Secular law must be brought into

harmony with divine law, 277,

278. Cameades, his conception of justice, 5. Cassiodorus —

Quotes Trajan's saying, exhorting

his ministers to freedom of speech

and to rebuke even the Emperor,

163, 170. Definition of justice in terms similar

to Ulpian's, 170. Justice magnifies the ruler and

makes the State prosper, 170. Law the instrument of social pro- gress, because it represents justice.

Explains St Paul's saying on divine authority of ruler as meaning that it is the just ruler who is to be obeyed, 1/0.

The true king, one who can control himself, 171.

King normally above the law, 171.

King only accountable to God, 171. Cathulfus—

Uses phrases with regard to king and bishop similar to those of Ambrosiaster, 149.

Divine authority of King, 214.

Kmg stands "in vice Dei," 216,

Bishop stands " in secundo loco, in vice Christi tantum," 215, 260.

Possible dependence of Cathulfus on Ambrosiaster, 216, 216.

Repeats St Isidore's definition of the king, 221.

The eight columns which support thejustking, 224, 225.

Duty of king to watch over and govern all God's members, 260.

Duty of king to superintend the lives of churchmen, but through ecclesi- astics, not laymen, 260.






296


INDEX.


Daty of king to maintain order and

piety in Church, 261. 267. Cato, 80.

Celsns, his theory of law, 103. Charity- Great development of almsgiving in

early Christian Church, 98-101. Almsgiving an act of justice, not

charity,137-142. Charles the Bald—

Election as King of Italy, 242. Promises justice in "Capitula

Pistensia,*^ 247. His subjects declare that they will,

if necessary, compel him to keep

his promises of good government,

248-250. Asserts that he cannot be deposed

without consent of the bishops by

whom he had been anointed, 251,

252, 286. Considers it his duty to superintend

the conduct of the clergy even in

religious matters, 262, 268. With the Pope summons Synod

of Ponthion and presides at it,

267. His quarrel with Hincmar of Laon,

275, 276. His appointment to empire by Pope,

284,1585. Importance of his unction asserted

by bishops, 285. Iniportance of this urged by himself,

Charles the Great—

A great ruler, but still a barbarian,

196. Form of promulgation of "Cap-

itula," m, 287. No evidence that he claimed to be

sole legislator, 239. Issues laws in Lombardy as con-

Sueror, 289. ^ivisio Regnorum,'* its relation to elective character of Frankish rulers, 241.

Considers it his duty to superintend the conduct of the clergy even in religious matters, 262.

Is gravely concerned about charges brought against Leo III., and goes to Home to inquire into them. 268.

His Capitularies illustrate the authonty of the king in calling synods and issuing canons, 265, 266.

Letter addressed to him by Sieg- wald, Bishop of Aquileia, on du^ of obeying canons, 277.

Pope Stephen III. threatens to ex- communicate him and Carloman if they should neglect his injunc- tions against marriage with daughter of Desiderius, 279.


Interpretations of his coronation as

Emperor, 288, 284. Chlothar II. : " Praeceptio," bishops in absence of king to reprove unjust judges, 281. Christian conceptions, general —

Relation of Christian conception of

human equality to that of Cicero, 9. Relation of Christian conception of

human corruption to that of Cicero

and Seneca, 13. Theory of state of nature in relation

to Seneca, 25. In relation to Lawyers, 44. Relation of Christian theory of

equality to that of Lawyers, 50. New Testament theory of equality

and slavery, 88-89. New Testament conception of gov- ernment, 89-98. Christians and Roman Gk>vemment,

92. Theory of property in New Testa- ment, 98-101. Natural law, 102-110. Identification of state of nature

with state before Fall, 110. Men passed from this state by sin,

117. Chrysippus—

His services to mankind, 28.

Law rules human and divine things,

56. Law the norm of the just and the

unjust, 56. Law belongs to all living creatures

which are by nature political,

56. Church and State—

The Church is in the Empire, not

the Empire in the Church (St

Optatus), 148. No one over the Emperor, save (rod

(St Optatus), 148, 179. Donatus says Emperor has nothing

to do with Church affairs, 148 (note

3), 158, 179. Emperor interferes with Canon Law,

iH. ^^St Gregory protests against such ^^^^ action, 154.

St Gregory calls such interference

null and void, 156. Persecution involves admission of

authority of State in Church

matters, 158, 179. Patristic theory of relation of

Church and State, 175-198. Spiritual authority of Church in- dependent of State, 175, 177. Relation of Church and State before

Constantine's conversion, 176. Changes owing to conversion of

Constantine, 176. Ambrosiaster speaks of king as God's Vicar, 149, 179, 215. .






INDEX.


297


The king has God's image, the

bishop Christ's, 149, 179. St Ambrose's treatment of Church

and State, 180-184. Church discipline and Emperor, 18()-

182,186. Imperial law on ecclesiastics and

secular courts, 182. The State and Church property, 188,

184. Treatment of the relations of Church

and State by Gelasius I. and Felix

II., 184-193. A strict dualism in society, 185. Authority of Church even over

Emperor, 186-189. Cases of resistance by ecclesiastics

to secular rulers, 188, 189. Ecclesiastics and secular courts, 189,

190. Definition of relation of the two

Jowers, 190, 192. uence of independence of Church on theory of limitation of authority of rulers, 192, 193.

Theory of relations of Church and State in ninth centurv, 253-292.

Influence of theoretical and actual relations of Church and State on political theory of Middle Ages, 253.

Theory of ninth centurv founded on the definitions of Gelasius I., the two powers are independent of each other, 253-257, 261, 287- 290.

Modifications of these definitions in ninth century, 255, 256.

Complexity of actual ]^elations in ninth century, 257.

Illustrations of this complexity in the writings of Sedulius Scotus and Cathulfus, 258-261.

King the Vicar of God in govern- ment of the Church, 259-262.

Illustrations of responsibility of king for good order of Church, 262-273.

This responsibility extends even to condition of papacy, 263, 264.

Relation of king to synods and legislation of Church, 265-267.

Authority of king in appointment of ecclesiastics to spintual offices, 267-270.

Relation of Emperor to papal elec- tions, 271, 272.

Illustrations of ecclesiastical author- ity in secular matters, 273-287.

The bishops the Vicars of God, 273, 274.

Ecclesiastics have spiritual authority over all ranks and classes of men, 274, 275.

Kings and rulers must obey the canons, 275-278.


Secular laws must be made to agree with divine laws, 277.

Emperor and kings may be excom- municated, 278-282.

Pope Leo IV. seems to condemn ex- communication of Emperor by the bishops of the Empire, 280.

Authonty of popes and bishops in appointment and deposition of secular rulers, 282-287.

Consecration of Charles the Great, 282,283.

Consecration of Lewis II., 284.

Consecration of Charles the Bald, 284, 285.

Importance attached by Charles the Bald to his consecration as King of the Western Franks, 286, 287.

The * * Donation of Constantine," 287- 290. Cicero- Cicero, with Seueca, represents the atmosphere out of which the polit- ical theory of the Fathers and Roman Lawyers grew, 3.

Cicero an eclectic philosopher, 3.

Justice the essential quality of the State, 4.

Definition of the State, 4.

Justice independent of man's con- sent, 5.

Cicero in opposition to Cameades and Epicurus, 5.

Nature, not utility, the source of justice, 5.

In agreement with Stoics on justice, 5.

Justice lies behind all law, 5.

Justice, the law of nature, the same as reason, 5, 6.

Law of nature is from God, 5, 6.

Law of nature and theory of justice in society, 6.

All true law is derived from law of nature, 6.

Human society an institution of nature, 6.

Cicero's conception of equality of human nature, 8.

Conception of natural love between men, 9.

Parallel between his views and those of French Revolution, 9.

Break in political theory between Aristotle and Cicero, 9.

Relation of Cicero's conception of eouality to Christian, 9.

Moaem character of Cicero's views of human nature, 10.

Historic circumstances producing changes, 10.

Influence of theory of equality on Cicero's theory of government, 11, 16.

Relation of his theory of equality to slavery, 11, 88.






298


INDEX.


SUvea to be treated as hired labour- ers, 11.

Some men may justly be alterius: Cicero influenced by Aristotle, 11, 12.

Cicero's theory of corruption or defect in human nature, 12.

Relation of his conception to that of Seneca and the Christian Fathers, 12, 13.

Theory of the origin of the State, 13.

The State grows out of the family, 14.

Conception of organic development of State, 14.

Anticipates Burke, 14.

State founded on law and justice, 14.

All govemmentfl, existing for the sake of all, legitimate, 14.

If government be unjust, then there is no State, 15.

All just governments are tolerable, not necessarily satisfactory, 16.

No liberty under monarchy or aris- tocracy, 15.

Modem character of Cicero's con- ception of liberty as share in gov- ernment, 15, 16.

Relation of his view of liberty to theory of equality, 16.

Preference for mixed governments, 16.

Theory of social contract, 17, 63.

Agreement with Lawyers on theory of law, 55, 57, 61.

Agrees with Lawyers on source of authority, 63.

Agrees with St Paul on natural law, 83, 103.

Comparison of his view of slavery with St Paul's, 88.

His theory of natural law and that of Fathers, 102-106.

Phrase about property, 137.

St Augustine and Cicero's definition of State, 165-170.

St Isidore's definition of State agrees with Cicero's, 172. Claudius, Emperor, edict providing that slaves deserted by their masters on account of illness should be free, 49. Clement of Alexandria —

Treats our Lord's command to young rich ruler as metaphorical, 133, 134.

Recognises no advantage in poverty in Itself, 133, 134.

The king is a ruler who governs ac- cording to laws, and reigns over willing subjects, 162. Clement of Rome: authority of rulers derived from Grod, prays that God will give them wisdom, 128. Coblentz, Declarations of, 230, 247.


Consecration of kings—

Symbolises the divine source of

authority of king, 214. Early history of consecration, 214,

note 4. Great importance attributed to this

by Charles the Bald, 252, 286. Importance of consecration and unction in ninth century, 282-287. Emperor Lewis IT. claims title of imiperor on ground that he had been anointed by Pope, 284. Frankish princes called kings and emperors when anointed by Pope, 284. Constantine —

Influence of his conversion on rela« 

tions of Church and State, 176. Recognises, according to Rufinus, the jurisdiction of bishop over himself in spiritual matters, 177. Constantius reproved severely by Lucifer of Cagliari for interference in Church matters, 178. Councils —

Council of Gangrse excommunicates any one who persuades a slave to fly from his master, 121. Council of Toledo on ordination of slaves, 122, note 1. Cyprian, Pseudo: "De Duodecim Abu- sivis Seeculi," its influence in the ninth century, 222-224. Cyprian, St —

Comments on community of goods as in the Acts : such conduct that of the true sons of God, 133. Does not say this is necessary, but the perfect way, 133. Cyrus, his just monarchy, 15.

David and Nathan, 188, 260. David and Saul, 152, 216, 217. Democracy, theory of : Relation to this of Cicero and Roman Lawyers, 16, 79. Demosthenes —

Definition of law, 56.

Law a discovery and gift of G^, 56.

Law intended for correction of

offences, 56. Civil law set forth by the wise, 56,

68. The expression of an agreement on the part of the whole State, 56, 68. Devil, his claim to the kingdoms of the world false, according to Irenaus, 128, 129. 'Didache, or Teaching of the Twelve Apostles ' : Christian men should share all things with their brethren, 132, 134. Divine source of authority of govern- ment — Seneca and PUnj, 81. Justinian, 69, 70.






INDEX.


299


New Testament, 89-98.

Divine authority of rulers in the

Fathers, 125-131, 147-160, 177,

187, 190-192. Coercive government a divine remedy

for sin, 128-131. Irenaeus, government from God,

129. Ruler the representative of Ood,

148-150. Ruler, the Vicar of God, has the

image of Gk)d ; bishop, image of

ChiMt. 149, 215, 259, 260. Wicked and good rulers alike repre- sent God, 151, 152. Ruler must be obeyed, lest God be

resisted (Gregory the Great), 152,

153. Influence on Gregorv's practical

action of theory of oivine author- ity of ruler, 153-157. Antecedents of this theory^ 157-159. Anarchical tendencies m early

Christian societies, 157, 158. Christian emperors patrons of

Church, 158. Tradition of Jewish monarchy in Old

Testament, 159. Theory of Gregory contrasted with

Roman Lawyers, 159. Relation of this theory to theory of

justice, 161-174. Relation of Augustine's theory of

State and that of Divine Right,

169,170. Treatment of subject in ninth cen- tury, 210-218. Significance of such phrases as ** king

by divine grace," 214. Significance of consecration of kings

and emperors, 214. Rebellion agaiost king is rebellion

against God, 215, 216. " Donation of Constantine," 287-290. Donatists —

Confiscation of their property by the

Imperial Government, 140. Their theory of property, 140, 141.

"Edictum Pistense," 288, 248.

Emptio, 52.

Epicureans—

Their view of justice, contrast with

Stoics, 5. View of origin of State, 18. On relation of wise man to the State,

27,28. Relation of their theory of State to

St Paul's, 98. Doubt as to relation of human nature to political life, 126. Equality of human nature —

Contrast between views of Aristotle

and Cicero, 8, 45. Circumstances of Aristotle's view, 7, 8.


Equality afltoned bv Cicero, Seneca, and Lawyers, 9, 48.

Continuity of theory to time of French Revolution, 9.

This theory constitutes the most im- portant difference between ancient and modem political philosophy, 9.

Theory of equality arises from ex- perience of Macedonian and Roman empires, 10.

The mind of every man ia free {sui iu/ri8)i 21.

All men are equal by natural law (Ulpian),40,47.

New phrases about human nature in Lawyers, 45, 46.

Influence of theory of equality on theory and condition of slavery, 48,49.

This theory helps towards disappear- ance of slavery, 50.

Relation of theory of Lawyers to that of Christianity, 50.

This conception in New Testament, 83-89.

Teaching of Jesus Christ on the sub- ject, 84.

Teaching of St Paul, 84, 85.

Treatment in New Testament of equality in relation to slavery, 86-

Natural equality and slavery in the

Fathers, 111-124. Conception of Fathers similar to that

of later philosophers and lawyers,

111-114. Natural equality and government in

the Fathers, 125-131. Natural equality and state before

the Fall m the Fathers, 144-146. Treatment of equality of human

nature in ninth century, 195-209. Ninth century continues theory of

Fathers, 199. Eugenius, Pope, oath on his election,

Eusebius of Csesarea, attitude to Em- peror, 177.

Fall, the, and the state of nature, 117,

144-146. Felix II.—

Historical circumstances of treat- ment of relation of Church and State by Felix II. and Gelasius I., 185, 186.

Felix anathematises Acacius, 186.

The king should learn from the priest in regard to the things of God, rather than presume to teach, 186, 187.

Felix gives Emperor Zeno choice be- tween communion with St Peter or with Peter of Alexandria, 188.

Action of Felix against Basiliscus and Zeno, 189.






300


INDEX.


Jlorentinus—

Distinguishes jtu gerUiwn from natura, 39.

Slavery an institution of jus gentium, 89, l7. 76.

Does not define /u« naturale, 41.

Derivation of aervuSf 47.

Relation of his theory of slavery to theory of state of nature, 43, 44, 64. 59, 60.

Some modes of acquiring private property are primitive, 53.

His distinction of jus gentium and natura and St Isidore, 106. Florus Diaconus—

Treatise ** De Electionibus Episco- porum," 269, 270.

Denies need of royal assent to Epis- copal election, 269, 270.

Admits propriety of this in king- doms where the custom had grown u^, 269, 270.

Denies that Emperor was consulted with regard to papal election, 271.

Gaius —

His theory of the jus gentium, 87,

38. No opi>osition between jus gentium

Ana jus naturcUe, 38. Jus gentium of Gaius has same

character aajus naturale in Cicero,

38, 76. Gaius holds same view of law and

justice as Stoics, 38. Distinction between slave and free

man, 46. Slavery an institution of jus gen- tium, 46. Master has power of life and death,

46. Slavery arises from capture in war,

46. Gaius looked on slavery as natural

and just, 46. Does not assert natural inequality,

46. Limitation of rights of master over

slave, 48, 49. Property arises from jus gentium,

Origin of property, capture, occu- pation, tradition, 51, 52.

Property primitive, rational, and just, 52-54.

Civil law founded on reason, not caprice, 55.

Definition of civil law, 65, 66.

Legislative authority derived from people, 65, 66,

Treatment of Senatus consultum, 66.

Definition of jus gentium quoted in Institutes, 72.

Altered quotation from Gaius in In- stitutes, 73.


Gaius's definition of jus civile re- produced by Isidore, 109.

Limit of rights of property, 142. Gelasius I., St —

Slave who had been ordained to in- ferior orders to be restored to his mistress, 122.

Slave, ordained priest, to be sent back to his mistress, but as priest on her estates, 122.

Relations of Church and State, 184- 193.

His definitions of this relation go to establish a theory of dualism in society, 184, 185.

Relation of this to mediaeval view, 185.

Historical circumstances of theory of Felix IL and Gelasius I., 185, 186.

No clear evidence that Gelasius ex- communicated any emperor, 186- 188.

Emperor has received his authority from God, 187.

Civil power has no jurisdiction in spintual matters, 187, 189.

Occasions when ecclesiastics had re- sisted secular rulers, 188, 189.

Definitions of relations of the two authorities, 190-192.

These definitions the starting-point of theory of ninth century, 192.

Difficulties of dualistic theory already apparent, 192.

Influence of theory of Church and State on theory of authority of civU rulers, 192, 193, 253.

Ninth-century theory of Church and State founded upon Gelasius* def- initions, 253-257.

Modifications of these in ninth cen- tury, 255, 256. (Jospels, the : Treatment of poverty and

riches, 100. Government and authority- Aristotle's view that government is founded on the inequality of human nature, 7.

Government is good if for the benefit of all, 15.

Agreement of Cicero and Aristotle,

Liberty a share in government, ac- cording to Cicero, 15.

Cicero's dissatisfaction with the three forms-of government, 16.

Gk)vemment in Golden Age, 23.

Coercive government made necessary by the corruption of human nature,

«4, Zo»

Seneca and Stoics hold the form of

Sovernment to be indifferent, 30. itical authority derived from the ioptdus, according to Roman ■ iwyers, 63-70.


pop\ Laiii






IKDEX.


301


■^t


Theory of government in New Testa- ment: All political authority is from God, S9-98.

Political authority is from God be- cause its end is justice, 90. 91.

The Christian Church and Judaism in relation to Roman Goyemment, 91-98.

Tendency of Christian societies to anarchism. 93-97.

Wycliffe's theory of civil lordship,

Relation of New Testament theory

of government to that of the

philosophers, 97, 98. Coercive government not natural or

primitive, according to the Fathers,

126, 127, 144. 3t Gregory maintains the existence

of order and authority in state of

innocence (cp. Seneca and Posidon-

ius). 127, 128. Coercive government a divine remedy

for sin in the Fathers, 128, 181,

144. There is no one above the Emperor X save God, who made him Emperor X (Optatus), 148, 179.

St Gregory's theory of source of

government contrasted with that

of Roman Lawyers, 159. History of medireval political theory

largely that of struggle between

these two views, 159. Authority of government, and justice ^in Fathers, 161-174. The State the instrument of justice,

this the normal view of the

^^ Fathers, 161.

"^~" Justice and beneficence the ratio of

the State (Ambrose), 162. —Importance of liberty in State (St

Anselm, Cassiodorus, and Gregory

the Great), 163. Divine source of authority in ninth

century, 210-218. Justice as the proper end of govern- ment in nintn century, 219-228. Theory of source and conditions of

authority in ninth century, 240-

262. Gratian —

St Isidore's definition of natural law

embodied in the Decretum, 106. Interpretation of St Isidore's phrase,

"Communis omnium possessio,"

143, note 1. Green, T. H., on "General Will," 62. ^^> — Gregory the Great, St —

The Roman Emperors rule over free

men, the barbarians over slaves,

8, 163. All men by nature equal ; masters

to remember this, 114. Masters must give account to God

for slaves, 1^.


Men are equal ; no coercive govern- ment in the beginning, 127, 128.

Order and authority in state of in- nocence and among angels, 127, 128.

Comnare with Seneca and Posidonius,

Coercive government a divine institu- tion, 128. Divine character and authority of

government, 180, 181. Almsgiving an act of justice, 138. Unjust to use property for persona)

benefit beyond what is necessary,

188. Compare theory <>f property of St

Thomas Aquinas, 189. First writer to state fully theory of

Divine Right of ruler, 147. The wicked and the good ruler alike

represent God, 152. Conduct of David and Saul proves

that subjects must not criticise

their rulers, 152. To resist the ruler is to resist God^ .

152. St Gregory's attitude to Emperors-

153-157. Canonical law and the Emperor, 154-

156. Reaction of ecclesiastical theory

against St Gregory, 159. Influence on theory of equality in

ninth century, 199, 200. Influence on theory of divine author- ity of rulers in tne ninth century^

213, 218, 219, 220. Nature of the true king, 226, 227. Gregory IV. (Pope) elected but not consecrated till Emperor's ambassa- dor had enquired into his election, 272. Guido, King of Italy —

In documents concerning his election,

it is provided that people are to-

have their own laws, 245. The bishop is to protect people

against the count, 281.

Hadrian, Emperor : Severe punishment of lady who had ill-treated her slave- women, 49. Hellenism, its influence on Judaism, 82,^

85, 103. Hermogenianus —

His relation to distinction between^ jus naturale and jus geniivm, 42, 63,72. Domvnia distincta belongs to jv8

gentiumy 53. His position in regard to primitive character of property uncertain, 53,54. Hilary, St, of Poictiers —

St Paul and natural law, 83, 105, 106. On the scope of natural law, 105, 106..






302


INDEX.


Hincmar of Laon : Treatise by Hincmar of Blieims on quarrel between him and Charles the Bald, 275. Hincmar of Rheims —

Equality of human nature, 200.

Divine authority of government, 212- 214.

Religious oblic^ation of submission to kings, whether just or unjust, 217| 218.

Influenced by St Isidore's definitions of king and tyrant, 222.

Influenced by *De Duodecim Abu- sivis Saeculi,' 224.

Very strongly asserts need of justice for legitimate rule, 227, 228.

Relation of king to law, 230-234.

King bound to obey the law, 232- 234.

Laws {capitula) made generali con- sensu Jidelium, 234.

Reminds Lewis III. that he had elected him, 244.

Treats deposition of Lewis the Pious as not in itself improper, 261, 287.

Quotes Gelasius' definition of rela- tions of Church and State, 264.

Urges that dignity of bishop is greater than that of kings, for bishops consecrate them, 256.

Recognises, but limits authority of the king in appointing bishops, 267-270.

Canon Law binding upon king, 276, 276.

Secular law must be brought into harmony with divine law, 277.

Kings subject to ecclesiastical juris- diction, 278, 279.

Threatens to excommunicate Em- peror Lothair, 280.

Letter of Synod of Quierzy, probably composea by Hincmar, attributes great importance to unction of king by bishops, 286. fiosius of Cordova: Letter to Constan- tine warning him not to interfere in Church affairs, 177. , Hrabanus Maurus—

  • De Universe, ' an encyclopaedic

work on pattern of St Isidore's

  • Etymologies,' 107.

Equality of human nature, 200.

Men in primitive times the lords of cattle, not of their fellow-men, 203.

Slavery a consequence of iniquity or adversity, 203.

Traces of view that slavery was a justifiable result of supenority of some men to others, 204.

Attempt on part of a slave to escape is sinftil, 204-206.

Origin of the State, 212.

Divine authority of the king, 214.

Condemns rebellion as sinfal, 216.


Condemns strongly revolt against

Lewis the Pious, 217, 261. Quotes St Isidore's definitions of

kine and tyrant, 221, 222. Calls bishops the Vicars of the prince

of shepherds in the Church of God,

273, m. Human nature —

Inequality maintained by Aristotle,

8. Equality held by Cicero, Seneca,

Lawyers, and Fathers, 8, 9. Corruption of human nature, in

Cicero, 12. Relation of this conception to human

institutions, 12, 13. Greneral resembUmce of conceptions

of Seneca and Cicero, 19, 20. Corruption the cause of change from

state of nature, 24, 26. Seneca's description of human nature,

24,26. Equality under natural law (Ulpian),

40. Equality in relation to slavery in the

Roman Lawyers, 45-51. Equality in New Testament, 83-89. Equality in Fathers, 111-131. Man by nature sociable (St Augus- tine), 126, 126. Equality of human nature in ninth

century, 199-209.

Inequality of man —

Aristotle's theory of inequality, 7.

Origin of this theory, 7, 8.

Relations of theory to government and slavery, 7.

Ulpian on slaves and civil law, 40.

Inequality not asserted by any Lawyer, 46.

Theory of inequality of man con- demned by Fathers, 113-124. Institutes of Justinian —

Represent le^ theory of sixth cen- tury, 36.

On jiis gentium and Jus ncUuraUt

Relation of their view to theory of

state of nature, 42, 44, 76, 76. Their evidence as to development of

legal views, 71. Definition of law of nature, from

Ulpian, 73, 74. Natural laws divine and permanent,

74. Civil law controlled by natural equity

and humanity, 74. Treatment of slavery same as Ulpian,

76. Theory of property same as in

Digest, 76, 77. Theory of nature of civil law, same

as Digest, 77. Source of authority, same as Digest,

77.






INDEX.


303


Theory of InstitTites and of Isidore on jus naturale, gentium, and civUe, 106-110.

Limitation of rights of property, 142. Irenseus, St—

Origin of coercive govemment, 128,

Authority derived from God, 129.

Coercive government made necessary bvsin, 128, 130.

Evil rulers sent by Gk)d as a punish- ment on their people, 148.

Threatens unjust rulers with God's judgment, 162. Isaiah, his universalism, 85. Isidore, St, of Seville- Defines jus naturcUe and jus gentium, 42.

On law of nature, 106.

His position in development of pol- itical theory, 107.

Character of * Etymologies,' 107.

On tripartite character of law, 108.

Distinguishes jus naturale finom jus gentium, 108.

Natural law common to all nations, 108.

Defines jus gentium and jus civile, 109.

Distinction between 9W naturale and jtis gentium and theory of state of nature, 109, 110.

Under natural law, "omnium una libertas," 114.

Slavery a punishment and remedy for sin, 118, 119.

Slavery a discipline, 119.

Gk)vernment a remedy for wicked- ness, 130, 131.

'* Communis omnium possessio" be- longs to jus natwale, 142-144.

Uncertainty as to meaning of phrase, 143.

Interpretation of phrase in Middle Ages, 143.

Comparison of Isidore's statement with those of Roman Lawyers, 143.

Wicked and good rulers alike derive authority from God, 151.

Wicked ruler a divine punishment, 151.

Urges princes to respect their own laws, 164, 173.

On beginnings of social life, 171, 172.

Defines civitas SLnd popidus, 172. /Agrees with Cicero, not with Augus- ^ tine, in definitioD of State, 172. /Defines king and tyrant, 172, 173. ^ yCivil authority must promote justice,

Hrabanus Maurus's definition of oppidum taken from Isidore, 212.

Influence of his definition of State in ninth century, 221.


Influence of his definitions of king and tyrant in ninth century, 221, 222. Isidore, Pseudo- Possible to maintain that the ninth- century theory of authority of the Church culminates in these writ- ings, but doubtful whether this is •correct, 257. All princes must submit to bishops,

275. No emperor or ruler may decree any- thing which is contrary to the divine commands, 278. Any one who is oppressed may appeal

to the priest, 282. "Donation of Constantine" embodied in Pseudo-Isidore, 289.

James, St —

Freedom, 94.

The poor and the rich, 100, 101. Jerome, St —

On natural law, 105.

Community of goods belongs to the

perfect life, 135. Jerusalem, communism in Church of, 98-

101. Jesus Christ —

Universalism and its relation to the

idea of equality, 83, 84. Teaching of Christ on relation

of Jews to Roman Government,

92. Contrast of spirit of worldly rule

with spirit of disciples, 96, 97. Justin Martyr holds that Christ

teaches Christians to serve their

rulers, 129. Christ alone is truly Eling and Priest,

according to G^lasius, 190. Jonas of Orleans —

Equality of human nature, 199. Low social position of inferior clergy

in ninth century, 207. Divine authority of the king, 214. Influenced by St Isidore^s defini- tion of king and tyrant, 221,

222. Quotes "De Duodecim Abusivis

Sseculi" on justice in king, 225. Chief duty of king is to do justice,

225. Jonas' statements reproduced by

bishops in address to Lewis the

Pious, 226, 227. Quotes Gelasius on Church and State,

254. Comments on theory of Gelasius,

255, 256. Priests must urge king to discharge

hisduty, 255, 256, 281. Quotes from Rufinus the report that

Constantine said Grod made bishops

judges of all, and that they cannot

be judged by any, 274.






304


INDEX,


Judaism—

Contact between Judaic and Hellenic

ideas, influenoe of latter, 82, 85. Relation to nniversalism and human

equality, 84, 85. Relation of Jews to Roman Govern- ment, 91-93. Jewish slavery limited, 121. Possible theories of communism in

later Judaism, 134, 135. Influence on the Fathers of Jewish

conception of the divine authority

ofkings, 160-153, 157-159. Julianus —

Custom makes and unmakes law, 64,

65. Authority of law derived from people,

64,65. Relation of his view to that of Qaius,

65. Jus civile —

Cicero and Roman Lawyers hold that

civil law embodies principle of

justice, 6, 61. By it slaves are held "pro nullis,"

40. All civil law directed by natural

reason (Gains), 55. Marcianus quotes Demosthenes and

Chrysippus on civil law, 56. Ulpian's theory of civil law, 57-59. Ambiguity of Ulpian's statements,

58. Discussion of Ulpian's theory, 59, 60. Ambiguous phrase of Paulus, 60. Laws ought to be just, yet must be

amended, 61. Isidore's definition of civil law, 109. Jus divmum and Jus huirnanum, phrases used by Augustine parallel to jv^ tkU- vrale and civilef 141. Jus edicendi, 66. Jus gentium —

Two views in Digest of relation of

Jus gentium and naturaUf 36. Jics gentium in Gains, 37. No opposition in Gains between /iw

gentium and natv/raley 38. A^eement between Gains and Cicero,

Ulpian, Florentinus, and Tryphoni-

nus otijus gentium, 39. Origin of Jus gentium in Institutes,

Relation of conception in Institutes

to that of Seneca, 43, 44. Private property an institution of

Jus gentium, according to Lawyers,

51-54. Relation of property to Jus naturcUe

in Institutes, 71-76. Distinction between the Jus ruUurale

ajidjtts gentium in Isidore, 108-110. Isidore defines ^2*5 gentium, 109. Isidore does not say private property

originates in Jus gentium, 144.


Jus naturcUe, See Nature. Justice —

Cicero's theory of justice, 4-6. Justice essential to the idea of the

State, 4, 5. Relation to natural law, 5. Contrast between theory of Cicero

and the Stoics and that of the

Epicureans, 5. Justice a proper quality of relations

between master and slave, 11. Justice the test of legitimate govern- ment, 15, 16. Study of justice the duty of Lawyers,

accordmg to Ulpian, 34. A quality of the^z^^ gentium, accord*

ing to Gains, 37. Relation of civil law to justice, 55-

62. Ulpian defines justice, 58. Jtis naturale represents what is just,

60. Lawyers and Cicero agree on justice,

61, 79. Justice belongs to the future, 62. Jus natureUe the expression of the

principle of justice, 75. Augustine on law and justice, 79. Masters should render justice to

slaves, 87, 88. Gk>vemment divine because its object

is to maintain justice, 89-98. Justice, according to Lactantius, con- sists of pietcLS and cequitas, 112,

113. Ambrosiaster urges duty of justice

between master and slave, 113. Irenaeus holds the end of government

to be the preservation of justice,

129. Almsgiving an act of justice, not

charity, 136-139. Relation of theory of natural law

and natural state to justice, 144-

146. Doubt as to Ambrosiaster's theory of

justice and government, 150. Wicked rulers represent Otod, 150-

152. Authority and justice in the Fathers,

161-174. Normal view of Fathers is that jus- tice is the ^d of government, 161,

162. Irenaeus threatens unjust rulers with

punishment from God, 162. Clement defines a king as one who

rules by law, 162. Justice with beneficence the "ratio"

of the State, 162. St Ambrose says ruler is bound by

laws, 163, 164. Augustine's definition of State omits

justice, 165-168. Justice essential element in law, ac- cording to Augustine, 167, 168.






INDEX.


305


Relation of Aagustine's omission of justice from the definition of the State and the " divine right," 169.

€assiodoru8' definition of justice sim- ilar to Ulpian's, 170.

Importance of justice in State ac- cording to Cassiodorus, 170.

Isidore defines chief virtues of king to be justice andpietas, 172.

Fathers, save Augustine, hold justice essential to State, 174.

Justice independent of State, 175.

Relation of this conception to author- ity of Church, 176.

Ninth-century theory of king and justice, 219-228.

In ninth century justice means main- tenance of the law, 229, 230.

Promises of justice b^ Emperor and kings on their election, relation to social contract, 242-252.

Theory of justice has in ninth cen- tury a practical significance, 252. Justinian —

Digest best guide to political theory of Empire, 34, 35.

Imperial authority derived from popvlus through lex regia, 69.

Imperial authority from God (cp. Seneca, Pliny, and Fathers), 69.

Emperor a "living law," 69.

Emperor the sole legis tator^ 70, 229.

On reception of slaves into monas- teries, 122.

Makes bishops responsible for the proper expenditure of money left for public charities, 282.

Gives bishop considerable jjowers to protect citizens against improper exactions of money, 282. Justin Martyr —

Christians taught by Christ to pay taxes, 129.

Christians serve their rulers gladly, 129.

Liberality of Christians, 133.

Community of goods, 133.

Karlmann calls synod and issues its

decrees, 265. Kingor ruler, tyrant- King has the image of God and is

God's Vicar (Ambrosiaster and

Cathulfus), 149, 215. Justice the duty of rulers, this the

normal theory of Fathers, 161, 162, Clement of Alexandria, definition of

the king, 162. The king should be a lover of liberty

(St Ambrose, Cassiodorus, and St

Gregpry), 163. The king bound by his laws (St

Ambrose), 164. "Rex legions absolutus" (St Am- brose and Ulpian), 164, 171, 229,

234.

VOL. L



Ruler is God's minister for justice

(Cassiodorus), 170. King above the law (Cassiodorus),

171. Definition of king and tyrant (St

Isidore), 172, 178. Prince should obey his own laws, 173. Relation of civil ruler to Church,

175-198. His divine authority recognlBed in

ninth century, 210-218. King the vicar of God (Sedulius and

Cathulfus), 215, 216. Good king reigns by God's appoint- ment, evil kmg by His permission,

according to Hincmar of Rheims,

217, 218. f Eling and justice in ninth century,

219-228. Emphasis on distinction between

king and tyrant, 221, 222. Impious king compared to wild

beast, 228. King and law in ninth century, 229-

Contrast between ninth - century theory and that of ancient Em- pire, 229, 230, 234.

Justice in ninth century means carrying out of national law, 230.

King must obey the law, 230-234.*

Eling not the sole source of law, 284.

Constitutional relation of king to law, 234-239.

Theory of source of authority of ruler in ninth century, 240-252.

Importance of elective character of kingship, 240 et seq*

Importance of mutual promises of king and subjects at election, 242 et seq.

These almost assume character of a contract, 245.

A contract which may be enforced by either party, 248-250.

Deposition of king in ninth century, its legitimacy, 250-252.

Practical consequences in ninth cen- tury of theory of difference be- tween king and tyrant, 252.

Labeo : Origin of property in occupation,

51. Lactantius —

life according to nature, 104. God made all men equal, 112. Condemns ancient institutions, and

their temper, 112. Misrepresents ancient thought, 112. Denies that men were ever apart,

125. Condemns Plato's theory of property,

134. No such thing in Gtolden Age, 134. Assumes truth of conception of

Golden Age, 134.

U






306


INDEX.


Latin Empire continues work of Mace- donian, 10. Law- Place of law in Cicero's definition of

SUte,4. Cameaaes and Epicurus held law

was founded on utility, 5. Cicero and Stoics derive law from

nature, 5, 6. Uigust Uws may have formal, but

have not real cnaracter of law, 6. Laws invented to control the ruler

(Seneca), 24. The Emperor the source of law

(Seneca). 81. Ulpian defines private law as tripar- tite, S9.

    • QugkI principi placuit, legis habet

vigorem," 64. Authority of law derived from popu-

lu8, 64-70, 77, 79. Justinian treats the Emperor as sole

"legislator," 70, 229. Mosaic, 104, 105. Law tripartite (Isidore), 108-110. Ruler bound by law (Ambrose and

Augustine), 163, 164. King ;^iM toluttu, 164, 171, 229,

St Isidore holds prince must obey • Uw, 164-173. St Augustine's definition omits law

from the State, 165. Contrast with Cicero, 166. St Aug^ine's definition of /m and

jwra, 167, 168. Law the true instrnment of progress

and happiness (Cassiodorus), 170. Divine law greater than Imperial

(Ambrose), 182. Relation of king to law in theory of

ninth century, 229-239.

not the sole source of law, 284-


Character of conception of law in

ninth century, 235. Different kindis of law known in

ninth century, 235. Method of promulgating laws, 236. Consent and counsel of bishops,

counts, &c., in issuing laws, ^7,

238. Law made "consensu populi et con-

stitutione regis," 238. Lombard laws issued by Charles the

Great and Pippin as conquerors,

239. Conception of Canon Law as standing

alongside of secular law, 253. Secular law must be brought into

harmony with Canon Law, 277. Legibua solutus, 164, 171, 229, 280, 234. Lmis latar, 70, 229. Leo I., St—

Forbids ordination of slaves, 122. Description of origin of canons, 276.


Leo III., Pope —

Relation to "Divisio Regnorum,"'

241, 283. Oath of puiigation, 263, 264. Crowns Charles the Great as Em- peror, 288. Leo IV., Pope- Willing that Emperor's "missi" should inquire into charges brought against him, 264. Complains of Hincmar's threat ta excommunicate Emperor, 280. Lewis the Pious, Emperor —

Equality of human nature, 201. Recognition in 'Ordinatio Imperii' of the authority of the assembly of the "people," 287, 242. Illustrations of same principle ii^

other legislative documents, 238. His deposition, 250, 251, 286, 287. Considers it to be his duty to- superintend the conduct of the- clergy even in religions matters,. 262. Some "Capitula" on ecclesiastical

matters, 266. His authority in appointing ecclesi- astics, 267. His "constitution" with respect to- papal elections, 271. Authority of clergy in his deposition- and restoration, 286, 287. Lex, its technical meaning, 65-67. Lex regia, 64, 69. Locatio et conductio, 52. Locke, his theory of property antici- pated by Donatists, 141. Lothair and Tetburni, Hincmar's treatise- on divorce of, 2^ 230, 232, 251, 278, 287. Lothair, Emperor: "ConstitutioRomana"^

on papal elections, 271. Lewis II., Emperor, claims the title of Emperor on ground that he had been anointed by Pope, 284. Lucifer of Cagliari: Emperor has no- jurisdiction over bishops in spiritual matters, 178.

Maccabees' resistance to Hellenism, 85. Macedonian Empire —

Extends Hellenic culture to the

world, 10. A cause of recognition of homogeneity of human nature, 10, 11. Manichseans maintain that private prop- erty is unlawful, 135. Manumission —

An institution of Jus gentium, 47^

note 2. Of Hebrew slave in seventh year not to be claimed as precedent by CSiristian slaves, 121. An act pleasing to God, 124. Muht be performed in Christian. Churches, 124.






INDEX.


307


Marcianns—

Does not distinguish between jus

naturale axidjus gentium^ 41. Slaves are made so by war, or are

bom of slave women, 46. Slavery an institution of jus gentium,

46. Marcianus does not maintain human

inequality, 46. By natural law some things common,

some private property, 62. Definition of civil law taken from Demosthenes and Chrysippus, 66. All law set out by the wise, agreed

to by State, 66, 68. Civil law the application to particu- lar circumstances of principles of reason and justice, 67. Marcianus' agreement ¥rith Stoics,

67. Contrast with Epicurus and later Academics, 67. Marculfus: Manumission of slaves a

pious work, 124. Martianus Capella, <De Nuptiis Philo-

logiffi,' 107. Massilian aristocracy, 16. Mediaeval political theory founded on Roman Lawyers and Christian Fathers and Teutonic traditions, 3. Melchizedek, priest and king, 190. Mersen, declaration of, 230, 246. Minucius Felix—

Equality of human nature. 111. All men have power of reason, 111. Modestinus —

Limits of rights of masters over slaves, 49. Monasteries —

Slaves allowed to enter them without master's permission by Justinian, 122, 123. Slaves prohibited from entering them without master's permission by Gelasius I., 122. Gregory the Great protests against law prohibiting the entrance into them of soldiers and other persons who had public duties, 164. Mosaic law : its relation to natural law, 104, 105.

Nature and natural law —

Natural law andjustice, 6, 6. Cameades and Epicurus sceptics in

regard to it, 6. The source of idl law, 6. Importance of this conception in

Cicero, 4-6. Ambiguity in Cicero's conception of

nature, 17. Seneca rarely refers to natural law,

only to nature, 19, 20. Nature the test of truth, the guide

of life, 20.


Seneca b^ *^ nature" means the fidl perfection of a thin^, but occasion- ally also the primitive form, 20.

The state of nature, the Golden Age (Seneca), 23.

The law of nature in the Digest, 36- 44.

In Digest two views of relation of jus naturale to jus gentium, 36.

No opposition in Gains between the . two laws, 38.

In Gains, jus gentium same as jus naturale in Cicero, 38.

Jus naturale in Paulus, 38, 60.

Ulpian, Florentinus, and Tryphon- mus distinguish between the two laws, 39.

Ulpian's definition of jus naturale,

" History of law of nature " (Pollock), 39, note 1.

Ulpian's use of phrase, 40.

Ambiguity of Ulpian's phrases, 41.

No dear explanation of the distinc- tion between jus gentium and jv^ naturale in Lawyers of second and third centuries, 42.

Hermogenianus, St Isidore, and In- stitutes, and the state of nature, 42-44.

Aelation of their conception to Seneca's, 43, 44.

Slavery contrary to jus naturtUe and natura in Ulpian, Florentinus, and Tryphoninus, 46.


JUS


te property an ncUurale, 62-64.


Natural law the source of civil law,

66-62. Theory of natural law in Institutes,

71-76. St Paul and Cicero on natural law,

83. Natural law in the Fathers, 102-110. Identified with law of God, 103-106. St Paul interpreted as referring to

natural law, 106, 106. St Isidore introduces into Christian

theory the distinction hetween jus

naiurale and^iM gentium, 106-110. Differences between his definition

and Ulpian's, 108-110. Relation of distinction between the

two laws to theory of state of

nature and Fall in the Fathers,

110. By nature all men equal (Gregory the

Great), 114. All men by nature free (Isidore),

114. All men by nature made for society

(St AugustineX 126. Man is not by nature the ruler of

his fellows, 126. Order and authority in state of in- nocence (Gregory), 127, 128.






308


INDEX.


By nature all things common, accord- ing to the Fathers, 136-146.

Isidore on relation of law of nature to property, 142-144.

Summary of patristic theory of re- lation of nature to conventional institutions, 144-146.

Theory of natural equality in ninth century, 199 et aeq. Nature, the state of—

Seneca's conception of it, 23-25.

No coercive goyemment or property, 23, 126, 181.

Men passed fh)m state of nature by corruption, 24, 25, 117.

A state of nature implied in Lawyers' distinction between Jiia noUuraie taid jus gentium, 42-44.

Belation of legal theory of slavery to state of nature, 50, 51.

Relation of this theory to jus gentium and civil hiw, 59, 60.

Institutes deal mth state of nature, 75, 76.

Fathers conceive of state of nature as state of man before the Fall, 117.

Order and authority in state of inno- cence (Gregory), 127, 128.

Lactantius assumes reality of Gtolden Age, 184.

Importance of theory of state of nature in patristic theory of insti- tutions, 144-146. Neratius : Origin of property in capture,

51. Nerva Filius : Origin of property in cap- ture, 51. New Testament —

Political theory of New Testament, relation to the Old Testament, 82.

Natural law in New Testament, 82, 88.

New Testament conception of equal- ity very close to that of philos- ophers, 83-89.

New Testament conception of slav- ery, 85-89.

Conception of government, 89-98.

Theory of property, 98-101. Nicholas, Pope, threatens to excommuni- cate the Emperor Lothair unless he takes back Tetburga, 279. Ninth century, political theory of—

Comparison of its general character- istics with those of the Fathers and schoolmen, 195-199.

Importance of Teutonic influence on this, 197, 220.

Influence on it of iconoclastic dis- putes, 219.

Influence on it of transference of empire from Byzantine to Frank,

Onesimus, 86.


Optatus, St, of Milevis—

The ruler the representative of God,

148. The Church is in the Empire, not

the Empire in the Church, 148,

178. God alone is over the Emperor, 148-

178. Origen—

Relation of Christians and the State,

28, 29. Relation to Stoic theory of a uni- versal Commonwealth, 28, 29. Natural law the same as the law of

God, 103.

Papacy —

Purgation of Leo III., 263.

Leo IV. and imperial inquiry into

chaises against him, 264. Popes summon synods with Charles

the Great and Charles the Bald,

266, 267. Florus Diaconus denies that Emperor

was ever consulted about papal

elections, 271. "Pactum Hludowici" on papal

elections, 271. '* Constitutio Romana" of Lothair

on papal elections, 271. Oath of allegiance to Emperor taken

by electors to papacy, 272. Oath taken in presence of imperial

" missi " by Pope Eugenius, 272. Gregory IV. 's appointment not com- pleted till imperial ambassador

had inquired into election, 272. Popes and excommunication of

Frankish rulers, 279. Leo IV. condemns Hincmar of

Rheims' threats to excommunicate

Emperor, 280. Authority of Popes in appointment

of emperors and kings, ^2-287. The " Donation " of Constantino and

papal authority in ninth century,

287-290. Temporal States of Papacy, 288-290. Papinian —

Definition of law derived from Dem- osthenes, 68. Civil law, set forth by the wise,

agreed to by State, 68. Description of parts of civil law

same as Gains, 68, Paul, St—

Theory of natural law analogous to

Cicero's, 82, 83. Fourth and fifth century Fathers on

this theory of St Paul, 83, 105,

106. Equality of human nature in re- lation to Cicero and Stoics, 84, 85. Equality and slavery, 84-89. All men equal before God, 84-89. Slave capable of religious life, 86.






INDEX.


309


Slavery not unlaT^-ful, 86.

Enjoins upon Philemon to treat Onesimus as a brother, 86.

Does St Paul advise a slave to get freedom ? 86, 87.

Commands slave to obey and serve master, 87.

Christian master must be just to slave, 87, 88.

Theory of slavery compared with that of Seneca and Cicero, 88.

Treatment of slavery in Pastoral epistles, 89.

Divine source of authority of govern- ment, 89-98.

Authority divine, because its end is justice, 90.

Why does St Paul insist on this? 91-97.

Eelation of the Christian Church to Boman Government, 91-93.

St Paul and anarchism in Christian Churches, 93-97.

Relation of Christians to law courts, 97.

Belation of St Paul's theory of gov- ernment to that of philosophers, 97,98.

His evidence with regard to property in early Church, 101.

Influence of St Paul's view of politi- cal authority on the Fathers, 128- 131.

Influence of his idea of justice as end of Government on the Fathers, 161, 162, 170. Paulus —

Definition of jiis naturale and jus dvUey 38, 39.

Does not distinguish Jtis naturale from Jus gentiuMf 41.

Quotes Labeo and Nerva Filius on origin of property in capture, 51.

Certain methods of acquiring prop- erty are in accordance with jus naturale^ 62.

Jus naturale, that which is always just and good, 60.

Jtcs civiUy that which is useful to all or some in a State, 60.

Discussion of this definition, 60, 61. Persecution practically involved admis- sion of authority of State in Church matters, 158. Peter, St—

Divine source of authority of govern- ment, 91.

The end of government is justice,

Peter, Patriarch of Alexandria, 186.

PhUemon, 86.

Plato: Theory of social contract, 17,

63. Plebisdtumf 66, 67. Pliny, Panegyricus, 31.


Political liberty- Cicero identifies liberty with share

in political power, 15, 16. Seneca's conception of liberty, 29,

30. Relation of conception of political

liberty to theory of source of

political authority in Lawyers,

St Ambrose's conception of import- ance of liberty, 168. Cassiodorus and Gregory the Great on liberty, 163. Pollock, Sir F., "History of the Law of Nature; a preliminary study," 39, note 1. Pomponius-

History of origin and growth of

Roman law, 66, 67. All legislative authority derived from

the zH^nUtiSt 66, 67. Relation of law of Twelve Tables to

Greece, 66. Treatment of Senatus consultuSf 67. Pontifex Mazimus, 190. Poole, R. L., * Illustrations of Mediaeval

Thought,' 1. Posidonius: Primitive state and govern- ment, 128. Prima Justiniana, Bishop of : Emperor wishes to depose him, St Gregory the Great protests, 154. Property- No property in state of nature, ac- cording to Seneca, 23. 24. Property the result of human cor- ruption, growth of avarice, 24, ^ Theory of Roman Lawyers, 51-64, Theory of Institutes the same as of Digest, 76, ^ Theory of property in New Testa- ment, 98-100. In the Fathers, 132-146. A Community of goods in early Fathers, 132-135. Community of goods the more per- fect way, 133-135. ^This view not shared by Clement

and Lactantius, 133-135. J Possible relation of primitive Chris- tian view to some later Judaic, Essene, conception, 134, 135. ^ Manichseans seem to maintain that private property is unlawful, 135. Private property lawful, the normal view of the Fathers, 135, 136. ^ By nature all things common, their

normal view, 136-142. A Cicero's phrase, **Sunt autem privata nulla natura," 137. Private property limited by need of maintaining needy ; almsgiving justice, not charity, in the Fathers, 137-139. Relation of this view to St Thomas Aquinas' theory of property, 139.






310


D9DEX.


Property a right of distribution, not a right of unlimited use (St Thomas), 139.

Private property an institution of positive human law, 140-142. ^ Donatist argument for property,

Theory of Fathers in general belongs

to same tradition as that of Seneca

and Stoics, 142-144. Limitati ^n of property by its right

use recognised by Lawyers as well

as Fathers, 142. Theory of property in St Isidore,

142-144. Private property not a natural but a

disciplinary institution, 144-146. Church property and the State, 182-

184. Pseudo - Ambrose. See Ambrosi-

aster. Pseudo- Augustine. See Augustine. Pseudo-Cyprian. See Cyprian. Pseudo-Isidore. See Isidore.

RfUio naiuralis : Its relation to jus gen- tium and fu8 naturale in Gaius, 37, 38. Res nulliuSt 52, 53. Responsa Prudeiiiium^ 66, 67. Bichter and Kohl, '* Annalen des Frank-

ischen Reiches," 236. Roman Lawyers- Continuity of political theory from

them to French Revolution, 2. Theory of e<}uality and liberty, 9. Authority m State derived from

the people, 16. Relation of Lawyers to medieval

political theory, 3, 33. Relation to philosophv and the

Stoics, 34, 35. On justice and law agree with Stoics,

35. Opposed to Epicurus and later

Academics, 35. Theory of natural law, 86-44. Two views on relation oljtLS naturale

Kadjus gentium^ 36, 37. Gaius and Ulpian held opposite

views, 38, 39. No direct reference to state of nature,

but this is implied in distinction

between jus naturale and jus

gentium. 43, 44. Theory or equality and liberty, 45-

50. Influence of this on slavery, 50. JjCgal view of slavery as related to

Christian, 50. Lawyers' position with regard to

property, 51-54. Civil law the application of principles

of justice, 55-62 Authority of law and emperor de- rived from people, 63-70, 77.


Relation of this theory to that of social contract, 63, 64, 70.

Legal theory of political authority as related to Cicero's, 63.

Most important elements in legal political theory, 77-79. Rousseau, J. J. —

"Contrat Social" as representing a return to Aristotelian conception of the State, 13.

Theory of the ** General Will," 62. . Rufinus —

Reports Constantine as acknow- ledging the independence of Church courts, and their authority even over himself in spiritual matters, 177.

This report quoted by Jonas of Or- leans, and bishops in address to Lewis the Pious, 274. Ruler, the young rich, and the theory of pro^rty, 100.

Patristic interpretations of this, 133- 135.

oalvian —

Master and slave equal in respect of human nature, 114.

Private property lawful, 136, note 2. Sedulius Sootus —

Divine authority of the king, 214.

King is the View of (Jod in govern- ment of Church, has authority over both orders, 215, 259-262.

Influenced by St Isidore's definitions of the king, 221.

Urges the duty of maintaining justice on rulers, 224.

The eight columns which support the just king, 224, 225.

Compares impious kings to wild beasts, 228.

Blustrates complexity of relations of Church and State in ninth cen- tury, 258-261.

Secular ruler must set forward the wellbeing of Church, 258.

Secular ruler should provide for meeting of synods, 259.

Secular ruler must not judge ecclesi- astical afifairs, but must hear the judgment of the bishops and then

five his consent and authoril^, 59. Secular ruler should submit to re- proof of wise men, i60. Duty of secular ruler to maintain order and piety in Church, 261, 267. Senatus consuUumf 66, 67. Seneca —

Helps us to understand political con- ceptions which influenced Lawyers and Fathers, 3. Human equality, 9. Seneca a professed Stoic, 19. His conception of nature, 19, 20.






INDEX.


311


Nature the guide of life, 20. Nature the perfection, occasionally

the primitive character, of a thing,

20. General conception of human nature

similar to Cicero's, 20. Equality of human nature and

slavery, 20-23. Relations of master and slave, 22. Theory of Golden Age, 23-26. An age of innocence not perfection,

23. Virtue only belongs to developed

human nature^ 23. No coercive ^ovdmment in Golden

Age, 23. No property in Golden Age, 23. Importance of conception of the

theory of state of nature, 23. Men passed from state of nature

throu^I) growth of vice, 24. Conception of human nature as it

actually is, 24. Agreement with Christian Fathers,

25. Conventional institutions of society

the remedies for vices, 26. Proper relation of man to organised

state, 26-29. Self-sufficiency of wise man, 26. Epicurean view destroyed respon- sibility of wise man to the State,

26, 27. Seneca and Stoics repudiate view of

Epicurus, 26, 29. Meditation the highest life, 26, 27. Man by nature loves and serves

his fellows, 27. Definition of blessed life includes

helpful temper, 27. Wise man will help State, though

hindered from holding office, 27,

28. Example of Socrates, 28, The universal Commonwealth, 28. A man can always serve universal

Commonwealth : Example of Zeno

and Chrysippus, 28, 29. Relation of Seneca's view to Chris- tian, 28, 29. Conception of liberty varies in differ- ent works, 29, 30. Treatment of place and authority

of emperor, 30, 31. View of divine source of authority

compared with Pliny and Fathers,

Comparison of this theory with

Justinian's, 69. His theory of equality compared

with that of New Testament, 84. Comparison of theory of slavery with

St Paul's, 88. His state of nature the same as state

before the Fall, according to

Fathers, 110, 117.


Conception of origin of government

same as Fathers, 127, 128. Patristic theory of property same as

that of Seneca, 137. * Comparison of nis theory of divine

source of authority with that of

the Fathers, 157. Siegwald, Bishop of Aquileia: Canons

binding on Charles the Great, 277. Simplicius, Pope, 189. Slavery —

Relation to human inequality, 7. Cicero holds necessity of justice to

the slave, 11. Slave should be treated as hired

labourer, 11. Contrast of views of Aristotle and *"

Cicero on this, 11. Ambiguous phrases as to slavery in «^

Cicero, 11. Relation of Cicero's theory to his ^

conception of corruption of human

nature, 12. Equality and slavery in Seneca, 20- -^


The slave of the same nature as master, 20.

Relations of master and slave in Seneca, 22.

Slavery contrary to jus naturale and naturay 39, 46, 47.

Tryphoninus, Ulpian, and Floren- tinus on slavery, 39.

Slaves pro mUlis by Jus civile (Ulpian), 40, 47.

Slaves equal to other men by nature (Ulpian), 40, 47.

Slavery arises from Jus gentium, 42, 46, 47.

Assertion of natural liberty coin- cident with appearance of distinc- tion between^ naturale and^'u^ gentium, 45, 46.

Limitation of |X)wer of masters in Roman law, 48-50.

Change in condition, and final dis- appearance of slavery, 50.

Relation of new theory to Christian- ity, 50.

Theory of Institutes the same as Ulpian's, 76.

St Paul's theory of slavery and equality, 84-89.

No difference between slaves and masters before God, 86.

Slaves capable of religious life, 86.

Slavery not unlawful in St Paul's view, 86.

Doubtful attitude of St Paul to advantage of liberty, 86, 87.

Slave bound to serve master honestly, 87.

Masters owe slaves justice, 87, 88. ,

St Paul on slavery compared to Seneca and Cicero, 88.









312


INDEX.


Natural equality and slavery in the

Fathers, 111-124. Ambrosiaster on slavery, full treat- ment of this subject, 113. Fathers hold that men by nature are

free, 113, 114. The soul is always free^ 115, 116. Slavery a remedy for sm, 116-119. Slavery lawful, as discipline, 116-

124. Slaves bound to render service to

masters, 120, 121. Council of Gangrae anathematises

any one who taught slaves to escape

frt>m their masters, 121. Prohibition of ordination of slaves,

122. Masters bound to care for spiritual

welfare of slaves, 123. Disappearance of slavery: causes,

128, 124. Mitigation of hardships of slaves,

^ Manumission in Christian Churches,

124. ^ Slavery made necessary by the Fall, 144-146.

Treatment of the subject in ninth century, 199-209.

Human nature equal: slavery the consequence of sin, 199-202.

Inner man remains free, subject only to God, 202.

Traces of theory that slavery is a just consequence of inferiority of some men to others, 203, 204.

Sanction of slavery by Church in ninth century, 204.

Attempt of slave to escape con- sidered by some a mortal sin, 204- 206.

Hrabanus Manus qualifies this view, but regards such attempts as sinful, 204-206.

Ninth-century legislation on ordina- tion of slaves, 206,

Belation of this to trouble caused by the low social condition of the inferior clergy, 207.

Mitigation of condition of slavery by Church, 208.

Smaragdus Abbas urges emancipa- tion of all slaves, 208, 209. Smaragdus Abbas —

Condemns institution of slavery, 201, 208,209.

Exhorts the king to prevent enslave- ment in his country, 209.

Urges Christian men to emancipate ^1 their slaves, 209.

His view of slavery isolated in ninth century, 209.

Divine authority of the king, 214.

King stands "pro vice Christi,** 216, 262.


Urges the king to love justice and

judgment, 224. Duty of king to maintain order and

piety in Church, 261, 262, 267. Social contract or consent —

Authority of government derived

from people (in Cicero), 16. Government founded on agreement

(in Plato and Cicero), 17. Theory of contract put forward in

eleventh century, 62. Its relation to traditional Teutonic

idea of government, 63. Eelation of theory of Lawyers to

this, 63. Relation to this of mutual promises

of rulers and subjects in the ninth

century, 242-252. State- Cicero's definition of State and its

foundations, 4, 5, 14* Cicero's view of origin and character

of State, 13. Agreement with Stoics on this, differs

from Epicureans, 13. State a natural institution, according

to Cicero, 13. Creation of a State the greatest work

possible, 13, 14. State grows out of the family (Cicero

and Aristotle), 14. Organic growth, not mechanical con- struction, 14. Cicero anticipates Burke's view, 14. Unjust government destructive of

State. 14. Three legitimate forms of govern- ment, 15. Cicero dissatisfied with the three

forms of government, 16, 16. Cicero's conflteption of liberty in

State, 16, 16. Modem character of Cicero's ideas,

16, 16. Government founded on agreement

between popultis and great men,

17. No coercive State in Gk>lden Age, 23. Relation of wise man to State, 26-

29. The State and justice in Fathers,

161-174. Justice and beneficence the "ratio"

of the State, 162. St Augustine and the State, 164-

170. Augustine's definition of State con- trasted with Cicero's, 166-170. Omission of law and justice by Angus-

tine in his definition, 166, 167. Question of real influence of Augus- tine's theory, 168, 169. , ^^ Connection between Augustine's

theory and Divine Rig;ht, 169, 170. Cassiodorus on justice in the State,

170.






INDEX.


313


St Isidore's conception of State founded on Cicero^s, 172.

BelatioDs of Charch and State in the Fathers (see Church), 175-193.

Theory of origin of State in ninth century, 211, 212.

Definition of the State in ninth century drawn from St Isidore, 221.

Relation of Church and State in ninth century (see Church), 253- 292. Stephen II., Pope —

Threatens to excommunicate Charles and Carloman, 279.

Crowns Pippin as Eling of the Franks, 283. Stoics —

Theory of justice, 5.

View of origin of State, 13.

Agreement of Stoic conception of law and justice with that of Cicero and the Lawyers, 57.

Eelation of their theory of the State to that of St Paul, 98.

Human nature social, 27, 126.

Stoic theory of primitive state with- out coercive government and prop- erty, 127.

Relation of their theory of property to that of Fathers, 144. Stubbs, * Constitutional History of Eng- land,' 236.

Tertullian: Nature, the first teacher of

mankind, 104. Theodosian Code: diflferent editions of this in force in various parts of Prank- ish Empire, 235. Theodosius —

His exclusion from the Eucharist by St Ambrose, 180, 181. . Threatened by St Ambrose with ex- clusion on another occasion, 181, 182. Theodosius the younger rebuked by St

Leo. 188. Theodosius and Valentinian —

Authority of Emperor derived from

the law, 69. Emperor bound by the law, 69. Theophilus of Antioch : Honour to be shown to the king, his authority from God, 129, 148. '"^^homas Aquinas, St—

His theory of property, 139. His view that the ruler is not under the law, 230. TraditiOy 52. ' Tryphoninus —

Distinguishes between jus gentium

and ncUuralef 89. Liberty belongs to Jiu natwmUf slavery to jus gentiumy 39, 43, 44, 47, 76. Does not define /im naturdle, 41.


Relation of his theory of slavery to that of state of nature, 43, 44, 51. Twelve Tables, law of the, 67.

Ulpian —

Distin^ishes between j%a naturaU

Budjus gentium f 39. Tripartite character of private law.

Definition of jus naturcUej 39, 40,

41. Definition of ^t^ gentium, 39. Slavery arises from jus gentium, 39,

43, 47. Use of phrases Natural Law and

Nature, 40, 41. Distinction between yus gentium and

n<Uurale related to theory of state

of nature, 41, 51. Slaves by civil law are held pro

nullis, 40, 47. Men are equal by jus naturcUe, 40,

47. Men are free by jus naturale, 39,

47. Limitation of power of master over

slave, 49.

    • Precarium " belongs iojus gentium,

52. No information as to Ulpian's theory

of property, 53, 54. Definition of nature of law, 57,

58. Defines true character of juris- prudence, 58. Ambiguity of phrases on jus civile,

58. Explanation may be found in con- trast between state of nature and

state of convention, 59, 60. Authority of Emperor derived from

Roman people, 64, 69. His theorv^ represcDts that of the

Digest, 64, 69. Institutes follow his theory of jv4

naturale, 72. His tripartite definition also in St

Isidore, 106-110. St Gregory the Great's phrases on

human equality parallel to Ulpian,

114. His phrase "legibus solutus," 229,

234.

Valentinian I. : Law on ecclesiastics and

secular courts, 182. Valentinian U. See Theodosius. Valentinian? refuses to take part in

bishops' deliberations on doctrine,

259. Vespasian : Edict liberating slave women

wnose masters had prostituted them,

when they had been sold under the

condition that they should not be

prostituted, 49.






314


INDEX.


Vicar of God- Title applied to emperors and kings,

149, 215, 216, 259-262. Title applied to bishops, 273, 274. Viollet, P., "Histoire des Institutions Politiqnes et Administratives de la Prance," 286. Virgilius, Bishop of Aries : Letter of Gregory the Great to him, 127.


Waitz, Deutsche Verfassung's Ges- chichte," 236.

Zeno, Emperor: The "Henoticon," and relation to bishops of Rome, 185-189. ;

Zeno, philosopher, 28, 104.

Zeno, St : Comments on Acts iv. 32, using language almost dogmatically com- munistic, 138.




Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "History of Medieval Political Theory in the West" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools