Materialism  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 17:34, 2 September 2007
WikiSysop (Talk | contribs)

← Previous diff
Revision as of 21:56, 29 January 2008
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Next diff →
Line 2: Line 2:
# Constant concern over material [[possession]]s and [[wealth]]; a great or excessive regard for [[worldly]] concerns. # Constant concern over material [[possession]]s and [[wealth]]; a great or excessive regard for [[worldly]] concerns.
# The philosophical belief that nothing exists beyond what is physical (also called [[physicalism]]). # The philosophical belief that nothing exists beyond what is physical (also called [[physicalism]]).
 +==History of materialism==
 +In [[Ancient India]]n [[Indian philosophy|philosophy]], materialism developed around 600 BCE with the works of [[Ajita Kesakambali]], [[Payasi]], [[Kanada]], and the proponents of the [[Cārvāka]] school of philosophy. Kanada was one of the early proponents of [[atomism]]. The [[Nyaya]]-[[Vaisesika]] school (600 BCE - 100 BCE) developed one of the earliest forms of atomism. The tradition was carried forward by [[Buddhist atomism]] and the [[Jaina]] school.
 +
 +[[Xun Zi]] developed a [[Confucian]] doctrine oriented on realism and materialism in Ancient China. Other notable Chinese materialists of this time include [[Yang Xiong (author)|Yang Xiong]] and [[Wang Chong]].
 +
 +Ancient [[Greek philosophy|Greek philosophers]] like [[Thales]], [[Parmenides]], [[Anaxagoras]], [[Democritus]], [[Epicurus]], and even [[Aristotle]] prefigure later materialists. The poem ''[[De Rerum Natura]]'' by [[Lucretius]] recounts the [[mechanism (philosophy)|mechanistic]] philosophy of [[Democritus]] and [[Epicurus]]. According to this view, all that exists is matter and void, and all phenomena are the result of different motions and conglomerations of base material particles called "atoms." ''De Rerum Natura'' provides mechanistic explanations for phenomena, like erosion, evaporation, wind, and sound, that would not become accepted for more than 1500 years. Famous principles like "nothing can come from nothing" and "nothing can touch body but body" first appeared in the works of Lucretius.
 +
 +Later Indian materialist [[Jayaraashi Bhatta]] (6th century CE) in his work ''Tattvopaplavasimha'' ("the Upsetting of all principles") refuted the [[Nyaya Sutra]] epistemology. The materialistic Cārvāka philosophy appears to have died out some time after 1400 CE.
 +
 +In early 12th-century [[al-Andalus]], the [[Early Islamic philosophy|Arabian philosopher]], [[Ibn Tufail]] (Abubacer), wrote discussions on materialism in his [[philosophical novel]], ''[[Hayy ibn Yaqdhan]]'' (''Philosophus Autodidactus''), while vaguely foreshadowing the idea of a [[historical materialism]].<ref name=Urvoy>Dominique Urvoy, "The Rationality of Everyday Life: The Andalusian Tradition? (Aropos of Hayy's First Experiences)", in Lawrence I. Conrad (1996), ''The World of Ibn Tufayl: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Ḥayy Ibn Yaqẓān'', pp. 38-46, [[Brill Publishers]], ISBN 9004093001.</ref>
 +
 +Later on, [[Thomas Hobbes]] and [[Pierre Gassendi]] represent the materialist tradition, in opposition to [[René Descartes]]' attempts to provide the [[natural sciences]] with [[dualism|dualist]] foundations. Later materialists included [[Denis Diderot]] and other French [[The Enlightenment|enlightenment]] thinkers, as well as [[Ludwig Feuerbach]], and, in England, the pedestrian traveller [[John "Walking" Stewart]], whose insistence that all matter is endowed with a [[moral]] dimension had a major impact on the philosophical poetry of [[William Wordsworth]].
 +
 +[[Schopenhauer]] wrote that "...materialism is the philosophy of the subject who forgets to take account of himself." (''[[The World as Will and Representation]]'', II, Ch. 1). He claimed that an observing subject can only know material objects through the mediation of the brain and its particular organization. The way that the brain knows determines the way that material objects are experienced. "Everything objective, extended, active, and hence everything material, is regarded by materialism as so solid a basis for its explanations that a reduction to this (especially if it should ultimately result in thrust and counter-thrust) can leave nothing to be desired. But all this is something that is given only very indirectly and conditionally, and is therefore only relatively present, for it has passed through the machinery and fabrication of the brain, and hence has entered the forms of time, space, and causality, by virtue of which it is first of all presented as extended in space and operating in time." (''ibid.'', I, §7)
 +
 +[[Karl Marx]] and [[Friedrich Engels]], turning the [[idealism|idealist]] [[dialectic]]s of [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Georg Hegel]] upside down, provided materialism with a view on processes of quantitative and qualitative change called ''[[dialectical materialism]]'', and with a materialist account of the course of history, known as ''[[historical materialism]].''
 +
 +Many current and recent philosophers &mdash; e.g. [[Daniel Dennett|Dennett]], [[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine]], [[Donald Davidson|Davidson]], [[John Rogers Searle|Searle]], [[Jerry Fodor|Fodor]] and [[Jaegwon Kim|Kim]] &mdash; operate within a broadly physicalist or materialist framework, producing rival accounts of how best to accommodate [[mind]] &mdash; [[functionalism (philosophy of mind)|functionalism]], [[anomalous monism]], [[identity theory]] and so on.
 +
 +In recent years, [[Paul Churchland|Paul]] and [[Patricia Churchland]] have advocated a more extreme position, ''[[eliminativist materialism]]'', which holds that mental phenomena simply do not exist at all -- that talk of the mental reflects a totally spurious "[[folk psychology]]" that simply has no basis in fact, something like the way that folk science speaks of demon-caused illness.
 +
== See also == == See also ==
*[[Base materialism]] *[[Base materialism]]
{{GFDL}} {{GFDL}}

Revision as of 21:56, 29 January 2008

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

  1. Constant concern over material possessions and wealth; a great or excessive regard for worldly concerns.
  2. The philosophical belief that nothing exists beyond what is physical (also called physicalism).

History of materialism

In Ancient Indian philosophy, materialism developed around 600 BCE with the works of Ajita Kesakambali, Payasi, Kanada, and the proponents of the Cārvāka school of philosophy. Kanada was one of the early proponents of atomism. The Nyaya-Vaisesika school (600 BCE - 100 BCE) developed one of the earliest forms of atomism. The tradition was carried forward by Buddhist atomism and the Jaina school.

Xun Zi developed a Confucian doctrine oriented on realism and materialism in Ancient China. Other notable Chinese materialists of this time include Yang Xiong and Wang Chong.

Ancient Greek philosophers like Thales, Parmenides, Anaxagoras, Democritus, Epicurus, and even Aristotle prefigure later materialists. The poem De Rerum Natura by Lucretius recounts the mechanistic philosophy of Democritus and Epicurus. According to this view, all that exists is matter and void, and all phenomena are the result of different motions and conglomerations of base material particles called "atoms." De Rerum Natura provides mechanistic explanations for phenomena, like erosion, evaporation, wind, and sound, that would not become accepted for more than 1500 years. Famous principles like "nothing can come from nothing" and "nothing can touch body but body" first appeared in the works of Lucretius.

Later Indian materialist Jayaraashi Bhatta (6th century CE) in his work Tattvopaplavasimha ("the Upsetting of all principles") refuted the Nyaya Sutra epistemology. The materialistic Cārvāka philosophy appears to have died out some time after 1400 CE.

In early 12th-century al-Andalus, the Arabian philosopher, Ibn Tufail (Abubacer), wrote discussions on materialism in his philosophical novel, Hayy ibn Yaqdhan (Philosophus Autodidactus), while vaguely foreshadowing the idea of a historical materialism.<ref name=Urvoy>Dominique Urvoy, "The Rationality of Everyday Life: The Andalusian Tradition? (Aropos of Hayy's First Experiences)", in Lawrence I. Conrad (1996), The World of Ibn Tufayl: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Ḥayy Ibn Yaqẓān, pp. 38-46, Brill Publishers, ISBN 9004093001.</ref>

Later on, Thomas Hobbes and Pierre Gassendi represent the materialist tradition, in opposition to René Descartes' attempts to provide the natural sciences with dualist foundations. Later materialists included Denis Diderot and other French enlightenment thinkers, as well as Ludwig Feuerbach, and, in England, the pedestrian traveller John "Walking" Stewart, whose insistence that all matter is endowed with a moral dimension had a major impact on the philosophical poetry of William Wordsworth.

Schopenhauer wrote that "...materialism is the philosophy of the subject who forgets to take account of himself." (The World as Will and Representation, II, Ch. 1). He claimed that an observing subject can only know material objects through the mediation of the brain and its particular organization. The way that the brain knows determines the way that material objects are experienced. "Everything objective, extended, active, and hence everything material, is regarded by materialism as so solid a basis for its explanations that a reduction to this (especially if it should ultimately result in thrust and counter-thrust) can leave nothing to be desired. But all this is something that is given only very indirectly and conditionally, and is therefore only relatively present, for it has passed through the machinery and fabrication of the brain, and hence has entered the forms of time, space, and causality, by virtue of which it is first of all presented as extended in space and operating in time." (ibid., I, §7)

Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, turning the idealist dialectics of Georg Hegel upside down, provided materialism with a view on processes of quantitative and qualitative change called dialectical materialism, and with a materialist account of the course of history, known as historical materialism.

Many current and recent philosophers — e.g. Dennett, Quine, Davidson, Searle, Fodor and Kim — operate within a broadly physicalist or materialist framework, producing rival accounts of how best to accommodate mindfunctionalism, anomalous monism, identity theory and so on.

In recent years, Paul and Patricia Churchland have advocated a more extreme position, eliminativist materialism, which holds that mental phenomena simply do not exist at all -- that talk of the mental reflects a totally spurious "folk psychology" that simply has no basis in fact, something like the way that folk science speaks of demon-caused illness.

See also




Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "Materialism" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools