Hylomorphism  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 12:29, 10 March 2011
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

← Previous diff
Revision as of 12:30, 10 March 2011
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Next diff →
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Template}} {{Template}}
-The '''third man argument''' (commonly referred to as '''TMA'''), first offered by [[Plato]] in his dialogue ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'', is a [[philosophical]] criticism of Plato's own [[theory of Forms]]. This argument was furthered by [[Aristotle]] who used the example of a man (hence the name of the argument) to explain this objection to Plato's theory; he posits that if a man is a man because he partakes in the form of man, then a third form would be required to explain how man and the form of man are both man, and so on, so on, ''ad infinitum''.+'''Hylomorphism''' (Greek ὑλο- ''hylo-'', "wood, matter" + -morphism < Greek μορφή, ''morphē'', "form") is a [[philosophy|philosophical]] theory developed by [[Aristotle]], which analyzes [[wiktionary:substance|substance]] into [[matter]] and form. More precisely, substances are conceived of as forms inhering in matter.
-==Principles of Plato's Theory of Forms==+[[Medieval]] [[theology|theologians]], newly exposed to Aristotle's philosophy, applied hylomorphism to Christian doctrines such as the [[transubstantiation]] of the Eucharist's bread and wine into the body and blood of [[Jesus]]. Theologians such as [[Duns Scotus]] developed Christian applications of hylomorphism.
- +
-Plato's [[Theory of Forms]], as it is presented in such dialogues as the ''Phaedo'', ''Republic'' and the first part of the ''Parmenides'', seems committed to the following principles: +
- +
-("F" stands for any [[Theory_of_Forms#Forms|Form]] (appearance, property). Plato, in the ''Parmenides'', uses the example "largeness" for "F-ness"; Aristotle uses the example "man".+
- +
-*One-over-many: For any plurality of F things, there is a form of F-ness by virtue of partaking of which each member of that plurality is F.+
-*Self-predication: Every form of F-ness is itself F.+
-*Non-self-partaking: No form partakes of itself.+
-*Uniqueness: For any property F, there is exactly one form of F-ness.+
-*Purity: No form can have contrary properties.+
-*One/many: The property of being one and the property of being many are contraries.+
-*Oneness: Every form is one.+
- +
-==The argument==+
- +
-However, the '''TMA''' shows that these principles are mutually contradictory, as long as there is a plurality of things that are F:+
- +
-(In the following sentences, large is used as an example; however the argumentation obviously holds for any F.)+
- +
-Begin, then, with the assumption that there is a plurality of large things, say (A, B, C). By one-over-many, there is a form of largeness (say, L1) by virtue of partaking of which A, B, and C are large. By self-predication, L1 is large. +
- +
-But then we can add L1 to (A, B, C) to form a new plurality of large things: (A, B, C, L1). By One-Over-Many, there is a form of largeness (say, L2) by virtue of partaking of which A, B, C, and L1 are large. But in that case L1 partakes of L2, and by Non-Self-Partaking, L1 is not identical to L2. So there are at least two forms of largeness, L1 and L2. This already contradicts Uniqueness, according to which there is exactly one (and hence no more than one) form of largeness.+
- +
-But it gets worse for the theory of Forms. For by Self-Predication, L2 is large, and hence L2 can be added to (A, B, C, L1) to form a new plurality of large things: (A, B, C, L1, L2). By One-Over-Many, there is a form of largeness (say, L3) by virtue of partaking of which A, B, C, L1, and L2 are large. But in that case L1 and L2 both partake of L3, and by Non-Self-Partaking, neither of L1 and L2 is identical to L3. So there must be at least three forms of largeness, L1, L2, and L3.+
- +
-Repetition of this reasoning shows that there is an infinite hierarchy of forms of largeness, with each form partaking of the infinite number of forms above it in the hierarchy. According to Plato, anything that partakes of many things must itself be many. So each form in the infinite hierarchy of forms of largeness is many. But then, given Purity and One/Many, it follows that each form in the infinite hierarchy of forms of largeness is not one. This contradicts Oneness.+
- +
-== Interpretation ==+
- +
-Some scholars (including [[Gregory Vlastos]]) believe that the TMA is a "record of honest perplexity". Other scholars think that Plato means us to reject one of the premises that produces the infinite regress (namely, One-Over-Many, Self-Predication, or Non-Self-Partaking). But it is also possible to avoid the contradictions produced by the TMA by rejecting Uniqueness and Purity (while accepting One-Over-Many, Self-Predication, and Non-Self-Partaking). Many say that these arguments are null and void if, as Plato said originally, perfected forms exist in another world outside of human comprehension.+
==See also== ==See also==
-[[Hylomorphism#Aristotle]]+* [[Endurantism]]
- +* [[Hyle]]
- +* [[Hylozoism]]
 +* [[Identity and change]]
 +* [[Inherence]]
 +* [[Materialism]]
 +* [[Substance theory]]
{{GFDL}} {{GFDL}}

Revision as of 12:30, 10 March 2011

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

Hylomorphism (Greek ὑλο- hylo-, "wood, matter" + -morphism < Greek μορφή, morphē, "form") is a philosophical theory developed by Aristotle, which analyzes substance into matter and form. More precisely, substances are conceived of as forms inhering in matter.

Medieval theologians, newly exposed to Aristotle's philosophy, applied hylomorphism to Christian doctrines such as the transubstantiation of the Eucharist's bread and wine into the body and blood of Jesus. Theologians such as Duns Scotus developed Christian applications of hylomorphism.

See also




Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "Hylomorphism" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools