Gaston Bachelard  

From The Art and Popular Culture Encyclopedia

(Difference between revisions)
Jump to: navigation, search
Revision as of 12:14, 8 January 2012
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

← Previous diff
Revision as of 09:44, 13 December 2015
Jahsonic (Talk | contribs)

Next diff →
Line 1: Line 1:
 +{| class="toccolours" style="float: left; margin-left: 1em; margin-right: 2em; font-size: 85%; background:#c6dbf7; color:black; width:30em; max-width: 40%;" cellspacing="5"
 +| style="text-align: left;" |
 +"[[D’abord, il n’y a rien, ensuite un rien profond, puis une profondeur bleue]]" --Gaston Bachelard
 +|}
 +
 +[[Image:Nest.jpg|thumb|right|200px|'''''Bird's [[Nest]] and Ferns''''' ([[1863]]) by [[Fidelia Bridges]]
 +<br>
 +"When we examine a nest, we place ourselves at the [[origin]] of [[confidence]] in the [[world]]." -—[[Gaston Bachelard]], ''[[The Poetics of Space]]''
 +]]
{{Template}} {{Template}}
-'''Gaston Bachelard''' ([[June 27]], [[1884]] &ndash; [[October 16]], [[1962]]) was a [[Twentieth-century French philosophy |French 20th century philosopher]] and [[French poetry|poet]]. His most important work is in poetics and the [[philosophy of science]]. He introduced the concepts of ''epistemological obstacle'' and ''[[Epistemological rupture|epistemological break]]'' (''obstacle épistémologique'' et ''rupture épistémologique'') and influenced many [[French theory|French philosophers in the latter part of the twentieth century]], among them [[Michel Foucault]] and [[Louis Althusser]]. His best-known work is ''[[The Poetics of Space]]''.+'''Gaston Bachelard''' (June 27, 1884 &ndash; October 16, 1962) was a [[French philosopher]] and [[French poetry|poet]]. His most important work is in poetics and the [[philosophy of science]]. He introduced the concepts of ''epistemological obstacle'' and ''[[Epistemological rupture|epistemological break]]'' (''obstacle épistémologique'' et ''rupture épistémologique''). He influenced [[Peter Sloterdijk]] whose ''[[Spheres (Peter Sloterdijk)|Spheres]]'' (1998) opens with a citation by Gaston Bachelard from his best-known work ''[[The Poetics of Space]]'':
 + 
 +:"The difficulty that had to be overcome (…) was to avoid all geometrical evidence. In other words, I had to start with a sort of intimacy of roundness."
==Life and work== ==Life and work==
-Bachelard was a [[mail|postmaster]] in [[Bar-Sur-Aube]], and then studied [[physics]] before finally becoming interested in philosophy. He was a professor at [[Dijon]] from 1930 to 1940 and then became the inaugural chair in [[history]] and philosophy of the [[science]]s at the [[University of Paris|Sorbonne]].+Bachelard was a [[postmaster]] in [[Bar-sur-Aube]], and then studied [[physics]] before finally becoming interested in philosophy. He was a professor at [[Dijon]] from 1930 to 1940 and then became the inaugural chair in history and philosophy of the sciences at the [[University of Paris|Sorbonne]].
-Bachelard's studies of the history and philosophy of science in such works as ''[[Le nouvel esprit scientifique]]'' ("The New Scientific Mind") (1934) and ''La formation de l'esprit scientifique'' ("The Formation of the Scientific Mind") (1938) were based on his vision of historical [[epistemology]] as a kind of [[psychoanalysis]] of the scientific mind, or rather of the psychological factors in the development of sciences. For instance, he takes the example of [[Heisenberg]]'s first chapters of the ''[[The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory]]'', where he alternatively defends a [[Corpuscular theory of light|corpuscular theory]] and an [[undulatory theory]], correcting each by the others (''[[The New Scientific Mind]]'', IV). This, claims Bachelard, is an excellent example of the importance of psychological training in sciences, as one should correct spontaneous defaults by taking the opposite stance.+=== Bachelard's psychology of science ===
 +Bachelard's studies of the history and philosophy of science in such works as ''Le nouvel esprit scientifique'' ("The New Scientific Spirit", 1934) and ''La formation de l'esprit scientifique'' ("The Formation of the Scientific Mind", 1938) were based on his vision of historical [[epistemology]] as a kind of [[psychoanalysis]] of the scientific mind, or rather of the psychological factors in the development of sciences. For instance, he takes the example of [[Werner Heisenberg|Heisenberg]]'s first chapters of the ''Physical principles of the quantum theory'', where he alternatively defends a [[Corpuscular theory of light|corpuscular theory]] and an [[undulatory theory]], correcting each by the others (''The New Scientific Mind'', IV). This, claims Bachelard, is an excellent example of the importance of psychological training in sciences, as one should correct spontaneous errors by taking the opposite stance.
In the English-speaking world, the connection Bachelard made between [[psychology]] and the history of science has been little understood. Bachelard demonstrated how the progress of science could be blocked by certain types of mental patterns, creating the concept of ''obstacle épistémologique'' ("epistemological obstacle"). One task of epistemology is to make clear the mental patterns at use in science, in order to help scientists overcome the obstacles to knowledge. In the English-speaking world, the connection Bachelard made between [[psychology]] and the history of science has been little understood. Bachelard demonstrated how the progress of science could be blocked by certain types of mental patterns, creating the concept of ''obstacle épistémologique'' ("epistemological obstacle"). One task of epistemology is to make clear the mental patterns at use in science, in order to help scientists overcome the obstacles to knowledge.
-Bachelard argued against [[Auguste Comte]]'s [[positivism]], which considered science as a continual [[progress]], that it had been superseded by such scientific developments as the [[theory of Relativity]], which demonstrated the discontinuous nature of [[history of sciences]]. Through his concept of "epistemological break", Bachelard underlined the discontinuity at work in the history of sciences &mdash; the term itself is almost never used by Bachelard, but became famous through [[Louis Althusser|Althusser]]. For this reason, he was a tough critic of [[Émile Meyerson]], who supported a continuist view of the history of sciences.+=== Epistemological breaks: the discontinuity of scientific progress ===
 +Bachelard was critical of [[Auguste Comte]]'s [[positivism]], which considered science as a continual [[Progress (history)|progress]]. To Bachelard, scientific developments such as Einstein's [[theory of relativity]] demonstrated the discontinuous nature of the [[history of sciences]]. Thus models that framed scientific development as continuous, such as that of Comte and [[Émile Meyerson]], seemed simplistic and erroneous to Bachelard.
-He showed that new theories integrated old theories in new paradigms, changing the sense of concepts (for instance, the concept of [[mass]], used by [[Newton]] and [[Einstein]] in two different senses). Thus, [[non-Euclidean geometry]] did not contradict [[Euclidean geometry]], but integrated it into a larger framework. +Through his concept of "epistemological break", Bachelard underlined the discontinuity at work in the history of sciences. However the term "epistemological break" itself is almost never used by Bachelard, but became famous through [[Louis Althusser]].
-A [[rationalist]] in the [[Descartes|Cartesian]] sense (although he proned a "non-Cartesian epistemology" which was to succeed, as a new theory, to Cartesian epistemology - ''The New Scientific Mind'', conclusion), he opposed "scientific knowledge" to ordinary knowledge, and held that error is only [[negativity]] or illusion:+He showed that new theories integrated old theories in new paradigms, changing the sense of concepts (for instance, the concept of [[mass (physics)|mass]], used by [[Isaac Newton|Newton]] and [[Einstein]] in two different senses). Thus, [[non-Euclidean geometry]] did not contradict [[Euclidean geometry]], but integrated it into a larger framework.
-:"Scientifically, we think the truth as the historical rectification of a long error, and we think experience as the rectification of the common and originary illusion (''illusion première'')"+=== The role of epistemology in science ===
 +Bachelard was a [[rationalist]] in the [[Descartes|Cartesian]] sense, although he recommended his "non-Cartesian epistemology" as a replacement for the more standard Cartesian epistemology. He compared "scientific knowledge" to ordinary knowledge in the way we deal with it, and saw error as only illusion: "Scientifically, one thinks truth as the historical rectification of a persistent error, and experiments as correctives for an initial, common illusion (''illusion première'').
-The role of [[epistemology]] is to show the history of the (scientific) production of concepts; those concepts are not just theoretical propositions: they are simultaneously abstract and [[concrete (philosophy)|concrete]], pervading [[technic]]al and [[pedagogic]]al activity. This explains why "The electric bulb is an object of scientifical thought… an example of an abstract-concrete object." To understand the way it works, one has to pass by the detour of scientific knowledge. Epistemology is thus not a general philosophy that aims at justifying scientific reasoning. Instead it produces regional [[history of science|histories of science]].+The role of [[epistemology]] is to show the history of the (scientific) production of concepts; those concepts are not just theoretical propositions: they are simultaneously abstract and [[concrete (philosophy)|concrete]], pervading [[technic]]al and [[pedagogic]]al activity. This explains why "The electric bulb is an object of scientific thought… an example of an abstract-concrete object." To understand the way it works, one has to take the detour of scientific knowledge. Epistemology is thus not a general philosophy that aims at justifying scientific reasoning. Instead it produces regional [[history of science|histories of science]].
-Bachelard opposed the duality between rationality and irrationality, claiming that, for instance, the [[theory of probabilities]] was just another way of complexifying reality through a deepening of rationality (while someone as [[William Thomson, 1st Baron Kelvin|Lord Kelvin]] found it somehow irrational). One of his main thesis in ''The New Scientific Mind'' was that modern sciences had replaced the classical [[ontology]] of the [[substance]] with an "ontology of relations", which could be assimilated to something as a [[Process philosophy]]. For instance, the physical concepts of matter and rays correspond, according to him, to the metaphysical concepts of the thing and of movement; but whereas classical philosophy considered both as distinct, and the thing as ontologically real, modern science can not distinguish matter from rays: it is thus impossible to examine an immobile thing, which was precisely the conditions of knowledge according to classical [[theory of knowledge]] (Becoming being impossible to be known, in accordance with [[Aristotle]] and [[Plato]]'s [[theory of knowledge|theories of knowledge]]).+=== Shifts in scientific perspective ===
 +Bachelard saw how seemingly irrational theories often simply represented a drastic shift in scientific perspective. For instance, he claimed that the [[theory of probabilities]] was just another way of complexifying reality through a deepening of rationality (even though critics like [[William Thomson, 1st Baron Kelvin|Lord Kelvin]] found this theory irrational).<
-In non-Cartesian epistemology, there is no "simple substance" as in [[Cartesianism]], but only complex objects built by theories and experiments, and continuously improved (VI, 4). [[Intuition (philosophy)|Intuition]] is therefore not primitive, but built (VI, 2). These themes led Bachelard to support a sort of [[constructivist epistemology]]. +One of his main theses in ''The New Scientific Mind'' was that modern sciences had replaced the classical [[ontology]] of the [[Substance theory|substance]] with an "ontology of relations", which could be assimilated to something like a [[process philosophy]]. For instance, the physical concepts of matter and rays correspond, according to him, to the metaphysical concepts of the thing and of movement; but whereas classical philosophy considered both as distinct, and the thing as [[Ontology|ontologically]] real, modern science can not distinguish matter from rays: it is thus impossible to examine an immobile thing, which was precisely the condition for knowledge according to classical [[theory of knowledge]] (Becoming being impossible to be known, in accordance with [[Aristotle]] and [[Plato]]'s [[theory of knowledge|theories of knowledge]]).
-In addition to epistemology, Bachelard's work deals with many other topics, including poetry, dreams, psychoanalysis, and the imagination. ''[[The Psychoanalysis of Fire]]'' (1938) and ''[[The Poetics of Space]]'' (1958) are among the most popular of his works.+In non-Cartesian epistemology, there is no "simple substance" as in [[Cartesianism]], but only complex objects built by theories and experiments, and continuously improved (VI, 4). [[Intuition (philosophy)|Intuition]] is therefore not primitive, but built (VI, 2). These themes led Bachelard to support a sort of [[constructivist epistemology]].
-== Legacy ==+=== Other academic interests ===
 +In addition to epistemology, Bachelard's work deals with many other topics, including poetry, dreams, [[psychoanalysis]], and the imagination. ''[[The Psychoanalysis of Fire]]'' (1938) and ''[[The Poetics of Space]]'' (1958) are among the most popular of his works, and the latter had a wide reception in architectural theory circles. [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] cites the former and Bachelard's "[[Water and Dreams]]" in his ''[[Being and Nothingness]]''.
-[[Thomas Kuhn|Thomas S. Kuhn]] used Bachelard's notion of "epistemological rupture" (''coupure'' or ''rupture épistémologique'') as re-interpreted by [[Alexandre Koyré]] to develop his theory of [[paradigm shift]]s; Althusser, [[Georges Canguilhem]] (his successor at the Sorbonne) and [[Michel Foucault]] also drew upon Bachelard's epistemology.+== Legacy ==
 +[[Thomas Kuhn|Thomas S. Kuhn]] used Bachelard's notion of "epistemological rupture" (''coupure'' or ''rupture épistémologique'') as re-interpreted by [[Alexandre Koyré]] to develop his theory of [[paradigm shift|paradigm change]]s; Althusser, [[Georges Canguilhem]] (his successor at the Sorbonne) and [[Michel Foucault]] also drew upon Bachelard's epistemology.
-Bachelard's daughter, Suzanne, translated [[Husserl]]'s ''Formale und transzendentale Logik'' in French. 
==Bibliography== ==Bibliography==
His works include: His works include:
-* [[1932]]: ''L'intuition de l'instant''+* ''Essai sur la connaissance approchée'' (1928)
-* [[1934]]: ''Le nouvel esprit scientifique'' <small>ISBN 2-13-044374-5</small>+* ''Étude sur l'évolution d'un problème de physique: la propagation thermique dans les solides'' (1928)
-* [[1938]]: ''La formation de l'esprit scientifique'' <small>ISBN 2-7116-1150-7</small>+* ''La valeur inductive de la relativité'' (1929)
-* [[1938]]: ''[[La psychanalyse du feu]]''+* ''La pluralisme cohérent de la chimie moderne'' (1932)
-* [[1940]]: ''La philosophie du non'' <small>ISBN 2-13-052578-4</small>+* ''L'Intuition de l'instant'' (1932)
-* [[1942]]: ''L'eau et les rêves'' <small>ISBN 2-253-06099-2</small>+* ''Les intuitions atomistiques: essai de classification'' (1933)
-* [[1943]]: ''[[L'air et les songes]]''+* ''Le nouvel esprit scientifique'' (1934)
-* [[1946]]: ''La terre et les rêveries du repos'' <small>ISBN 2-7143-0299-8</small>+* ''La dialectique de la durée'' (1936)
-* [[1948]]: ''La terre et les rêveries de la volonté''+* ''L'expérience de l'espace dans la physique contemporaine'' (1937)
-* [[1949]]: ''Le Rationalisme appliqué'' (PUF, Paris)+* ''La formation de l'esprit scientifique: contribution à une psychanalyse de la connaissance objective'' (1938)
-* [[1958]]: ''[[La Poétique de l'espace]]'' <small> English translation ''[[The Poetics of Space]]'' ISBN 0-8070-6473-4</small>+* ''[[La psychanalyse du feu]]'' (''[[The Psychoanalysis of Fire]]'', 1938)
-* [[1960]]: ''La poétique de la rêverie''+* ''La philosophie du non: essai d'une philosophie du nouvel esprit scientifique'' (1940), publisher, 1978
-* [[1961]]: ''La flamme d'une chandelle'' <small>ISBN 2-13-053901-7</small>+* ''L'eau et les rêves'' (Water and Dreams'', 1942)
 +* ''L'air et les songes'' (''Air and Dreams'', 1943)
 +* ''La terre et les rêveries du repos'' (''Earth and Reveries of Repose, 1946)
 +* ''La terre et les rêveries de la volonté'' (''Earth and Reveries of Will'', 1948)
 +* ''Le Rationalisme appliqué'' (1949)
 +* ''L'activité rationaliste de la physique contemporaine'' (1951)
 +* ''Le matérialisme rationnel'' (1953)
 +* ''[[The Poetics of Space|La poétique de l'espace]] (The Poetics of Space)'' <small> English translation ISBN 0-8070-6473-4</small> (1958)
 +* ''La poétique de la rêverie'' (1960 [http://www.tanbou.com/1994/Spring/Bachelard.htm])
 +* ''La flamme d'une chandelle'' (1961)
 +* ''L'engagement rationaliste'' [The Rationalist Engagement] (1972)
 + 
 +===English translations===
 +Though most of Bachelard's major works on poetics have been translated into English, only a few of his works on the philosophy of science have been translated.
 +*''The Philosophy of No: A Philosophy of the New Scientific Mind.'' Orion Press, New York, 1968. Translation by G.C. Waterston. (''La philosophie du non'')
 +*''The New Scientific Spirit.'' Beacon Press, Boston, 1985. Translation by A. Goldhammer. (''Le nouvel esprit scientifique'')
 +*''Dialectic of Duration.'' Clinamen, Bolton, 2000. Translation by M. McAllester Jones. (''La dialectique de la durée'')
 +*''The Formation of the Scientific Mind.'' Clinamen, Bolton, 2002. Translation by M. McAllester Jones. (''La formation de l'esprit scientifique'')
 +* ''Intuition of the Instant. ''Northwestern University Press, 2013. Translation by Eileen Rizo-Patron (''L'intuition de l'instant'')
 + 
 +=== Sources ===
 +* [[Dominique Lecourt]], ''L’épistémologie historique de Gaston Bachelard'' (1969). Vrin, Paris, 11e édition augmentée, 2002.
 +* Dominique Lecourt, ''Pour une critique de l’épistémologie : Bachelard, Canguilhem, Foucault'' (1972, réed. Maspero, Paris, 5e éd. 1980).
 +* D. Lecourt, ''Marxism and Epistemology: Bachelard, Canguilhem and Foucault'', New Left Books, London (1975).
 +* Dominique Lecourt, ''Bachelard, Epistémologie, textes choisis'' (1971). PUF, Paris, 6e édition, 1996.
 +* Dominique Lecourt, ''Bachelard, le jour et la nuit'', Grasset, Paris, 1974.
 +* Didier Gil, ''Bachelard et la culture scientifique'', Presses Universitaires de France, 1993.
 +* Didier Gil, ''Autour de Bachelard - esprit et matière, un siècle français de philosophie des sciences (1867-1962)'', Les Belles Lettres, Encre marine, 2010.
 +*''Hommage à Gaston Bachelard. Etudes de philosophie et d'histoire des sciences'', by C. Bouligand, [[Georges Canguilhem|G. Canguilhem]], P. Costabel, F. Courtes, [[François Dagognet]], M. Daumas, Gilles Granger, [[Jean Hyppolite|J. Hyppolite]], R. Martin, R. Poirier and R. Taton
 +*''[http://www.ccic-cerisy.asso.fr/bachelardTM74.html Actes du Colloque sur Bachelard de 1970]'' ([[Colloque de Cerisy]]).
 +*''[http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-7910(198609)101%3A4%3C895%3ALDCBUE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-6 L'imaginaire du concept: Bachelard, une épistémologie de la pureté]'' by [[Françoise Gaillard]], MLN, Vol. 101, No. 4, French Issue (Sep 1986), pp.&nbsp;895–911.
 +*''Gaston Bachelard ou le rêve des origines'', by Jean-Luc Pouliquen, L'Harmattan, Paris, 2007.
 + 
 +==See also==
 +*[[Constructivist epistemology]]
 +*[[Epistemological psychology]]
 +*[[Suzanne Bachelard]]
 + 
{{GFDL}} {{GFDL}}
[[Category:Canon]] [[Category:Canon]]

Revision as of 09:44, 13 December 2015

"D’abord, il n’y a rien, ensuite un rien profond, puis une profondeur bleue" --Gaston Bachelard

Bird's Nest and Ferns (1863) by Fidelia Bridges  "When we examine a nest, we place ourselves at the origin of confidence in the world." -—Gaston Bachelard, The Poetics of Space
Enlarge
Bird's Nest and Ferns (1863) by Fidelia Bridges
"When we examine a nest, we place ourselves at the origin of confidence in the world." -—Gaston Bachelard, The Poetics of Space

Related e

Wikipedia
Wiktionary
Shop


Featured:

Gaston Bachelard (June 27, 1884 – October 16, 1962) was a French philosopher and poet. His most important work is in poetics and the philosophy of science. He introduced the concepts of epistemological obstacle and epistemological break (obstacle épistémologique et rupture épistémologique). He influenced Peter Sloterdijk whose Spheres (1998) opens with a citation by Gaston Bachelard from his best-known work The Poetics of Space:

"The difficulty that had to be overcome (…) was to avoid all geometrical evidence. In other words, I had to start with a sort of intimacy of roundness."

Contents

Life and work

Bachelard was a postmaster in Bar-sur-Aube, and then studied physics before finally becoming interested in philosophy. He was a professor at Dijon from 1930 to 1940 and then became the inaugural chair in history and philosophy of the sciences at the Sorbonne.

Bachelard's psychology of science

Bachelard's studies of the history and philosophy of science in such works as Le nouvel esprit scientifique ("The New Scientific Spirit", 1934) and La formation de l'esprit scientifique ("The Formation of the Scientific Mind", 1938) were based on his vision of historical epistemology as a kind of psychoanalysis of the scientific mind, or rather of the psychological factors in the development of sciences. For instance, he takes the example of Heisenberg's first chapters of the Physical principles of the quantum theory, where he alternatively defends a corpuscular theory and an undulatory theory, correcting each by the others (The New Scientific Mind, IV). This, claims Bachelard, is an excellent example of the importance of psychological training in sciences, as one should correct spontaneous errors by taking the opposite stance.

In the English-speaking world, the connection Bachelard made between psychology and the history of science has been little understood. Bachelard demonstrated how the progress of science could be blocked by certain types of mental patterns, creating the concept of obstacle épistémologique ("epistemological obstacle"). One task of epistemology is to make clear the mental patterns at use in science, in order to help scientists overcome the obstacles to knowledge.

Epistemological breaks: the discontinuity of scientific progress

Bachelard was critical of Auguste Comte's positivism, which considered science as a continual progress. To Bachelard, scientific developments such as Einstein's theory of relativity demonstrated the discontinuous nature of the history of sciences. Thus models that framed scientific development as continuous, such as that of Comte and Émile Meyerson, seemed simplistic and erroneous to Bachelard.

Through his concept of "epistemological break", Bachelard underlined the discontinuity at work in the history of sciences. However the term "epistemological break" itself is almost never used by Bachelard, but became famous through Louis Althusser.

He showed that new theories integrated old theories in new paradigms, changing the sense of concepts (for instance, the concept of mass, used by Newton and Einstein in two different senses). Thus, non-Euclidean geometry did not contradict Euclidean geometry, but integrated it into a larger framework.

The role of epistemology in science

Bachelard was a rationalist in the Cartesian sense, although he recommended his "non-Cartesian epistemology" as a replacement for the more standard Cartesian epistemology. He compared "scientific knowledge" to ordinary knowledge in the way we deal with it, and saw error as only illusion: "Scientifically, one thinks truth as the historical rectification of a persistent error, and experiments as correctives for an initial, common illusion (illusion première).

The role of epistemology is to show the history of the (scientific) production of concepts; those concepts are not just theoretical propositions: they are simultaneously abstract and concrete, pervading technical and pedagogical activity. This explains why "The electric bulb is an object of scientific thought… an example of an abstract-concrete object." To understand the way it works, one has to take the detour of scientific knowledge. Epistemology is thus not a general philosophy that aims at justifying scientific reasoning. Instead it produces regional histories of science.

Shifts in scientific perspective

Bachelard saw how seemingly irrational theories often simply represented a drastic shift in scientific perspective. For instance, he claimed that the theory of probabilities was just another way of complexifying reality through a deepening of rationality (even though critics like Lord Kelvin found this theory irrational).<

One of his main theses in The New Scientific Mind was that modern sciences had replaced the classical ontology of the substance with an "ontology of relations", which could be assimilated to something like a process philosophy. For instance, the physical concepts of matter and rays correspond, according to him, to the metaphysical concepts of the thing and of movement; but whereas classical philosophy considered both as distinct, and the thing as ontologically real, modern science can not distinguish matter from rays: it is thus impossible to examine an immobile thing, which was precisely the condition for knowledge according to classical theory of knowledge (Becoming being impossible to be known, in accordance with Aristotle and Plato's theories of knowledge).

In non-Cartesian epistemology, there is no "simple substance" as in Cartesianism, but only complex objects built by theories and experiments, and continuously improved (VI, 4). Intuition is therefore not primitive, but built (VI, 2). These themes led Bachelard to support a sort of constructivist epistemology.

Other academic interests

In addition to epistemology, Bachelard's work deals with many other topics, including poetry, dreams, psychoanalysis, and the imagination. The Psychoanalysis of Fire (1938) and The Poetics of Space (1958) are among the most popular of his works, and the latter had a wide reception in architectural theory circles. Jean-Paul Sartre cites the former and Bachelard's "Water and Dreams" in his Being and Nothingness.

Legacy

Thomas S. Kuhn used Bachelard's notion of "epistemological rupture" (coupure or rupture épistémologique) as re-interpreted by Alexandre Koyré to develop his theory of paradigm changes; Althusser, Georges Canguilhem (his successor at the Sorbonne) and Michel Foucault also drew upon Bachelard's epistemology.

Bibliography

His works include:

  • Essai sur la connaissance approchée (1928)
  • Étude sur l'évolution d'un problème de physique: la propagation thermique dans les solides (1928)
  • La valeur inductive de la relativité (1929)
  • La pluralisme cohérent de la chimie moderne (1932)
  • L'Intuition de l'instant (1932)
  • Les intuitions atomistiques: essai de classification (1933)
  • Le nouvel esprit scientifique (1934)
  • La dialectique de la durée (1936)
  • L'expérience de l'espace dans la physique contemporaine (1937)
  • La formation de l'esprit scientifique: contribution à une psychanalyse de la connaissance objective (1938)
  • La psychanalyse du feu (The Psychoanalysis of Fire, 1938)
  • La philosophie du non: essai d'une philosophie du nouvel esprit scientifique (1940), publisher, 1978
  • L'eau et les rêves (Water and Dreams, 1942)
  • L'air et les songes (Air and Dreams, 1943)
  • La terre et les rêveries du repos (Earth and Reveries of Repose, 1946)
  • La terre et les rêveries de la volonté (Earth and Reveries of Will, 1948)
  • Le Rationalisme appliqué (1949)
  • L'activité rationaliste de la physique contemporaine (1951)
  • Le matérialisme rationnel (1953)
  • La poétique de l'espace (The Poetics of Space) English translation ISBN 0-8070-6473-4 (1958)
  • La poétique de la rêverie (1960 [1])
  • La flamme d'une chandelle (1961)
  • L'engagement rationaliste [The Rationalist Engagement] (1972)

English translations

Though most of Bachelard's major works on poetics have been translated into English, only a few of his works on the philosophy of science have been translated.

  • The Philosophy of No: A Philosophy of the New Scientific Mind. Orion Press, New York, 1968. Translation by G.C. Waterston. (La philosophie du non)
  • The New Scientific Spirit. Beacon Press, Boston, 1985. Translation by A. Goldhammer. (Le nouvel esprit scientifique)
  • Dialectic of Duration. Clinamen, Bolton, 2000. Translation by M. McAllester Jones. (La dialectique de la durée)
  • The Formation of the Scientific Mind. Clinamen, Bolton, 2002. Translation by M. McAllester Jones. (La formation de l'esprit scientifique)
  • Intuition of the Instant. Northwestern University Press, 2013. Translation by Eileen Rizo-Patron (L'intuition de l'instant)

Sources

  • Dominique Lecourt, L’épistémologie historique de Gaston Bachelard (1969). Vrin, Paris, 11e édition augmentée, 2002.
  • Dominique Lecourt, Pour une critique de l’épistémologie : Bachelard, Canguilhem, Foucault (1972, réed. Maspero, Paris, 5e éd. 1980).
  • D. Lecourt, Marxism and Epistemology: Bachelard, Canguilhem and Foucault, New Left Books, London (1975).
  • Dominique Lecourt, Bachelard, Epistémologie, textes choisis (1971). PUF, Paris, 6e édition, 1996.
  • Dominique Lecourt, Bachelard, le jour et la nuit, Grasset, Paris, 1974.
  • Didier Gil, Bachelard et la culture scientifique, Presses Universitaires de France, 1993.
  • Didier Gil, Autour de Bachelard - esprit et matière, un siècle français de philosophie des sciences (1867-1962), Les Belles Lettres, Encre marine, 2010.
  • Hommage à Gaston Bachelard. Etudes de philosophie et d'histoire des sciences, by C. Bouligand, G. Canguilhem, P. Costabel, F. Courtes, François Dagognet, M. Daumas, Gilles Granger, J. Hyppolite, R. Martin, R. Poirier and R. Taton
  • Actes du Colloque sur Bachelard de 1970 (Colloque de Cerisy).
  • L'imaginaire du concept: Bachelard, une épistémologie de la pureté by Françoise Gaillard, MLN, Vol. 101, No. 4, French Issue (Sep 1986), pp. 895–911.
  • Gaston Bachelard ou le rêve des origines, by Jean-Luc Pouliquen, L'Harmattan, Paris, 2007.

See also




Unless indicated otherwise, the text in this article is either based on Wikipedia article "Gaston Bachelard" or another language Wikipedia page thereof used under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License; or on research by Jahsonic and friends. See Art and Popular Culture's copyright notice.

Personal tools